|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Western philosophy, c 500 to c 1600 > General
This is an exploration and analysis of Aquinas's contribution to
the philosophy of religion. It examines Aquinas's contexts, his
views on philosophy and theology, as well as faith and reason. His
arguments for God's existence, responses to objections against
God's existence and his characterization of the nature of God are
examined.
This is the first comprehensive study of the Renaissance
commonplace-book. Commonplace-books were the information-organizers
of Early Modern Europe, notebooks of quotations methodically
arranged for easy retrieval. From their first introduction to the
rudiments of Latin to the specialized studies of leisure reading of
their later years, the pupils of humanist schools were trained to
use commonplace-books, which formed an immensely important element
of Renaissance education. The common-place book mapped and
resourced Renaissance culture's moral thinking, its accepted
strategies of argumentation, its rhetoric, and its deployment of
knowledge. In this ground-breaking study Ann Moss investigates the
commonplace-book's medieval antecedents, its methodology and use as
promulgated by its humanist advocates, its varieties as exemplified
in its printed manifestations, and the reasons for its gradual
decline in the seventeenth century. The book covers the Latin
culture of Early Modern Europe and its vernacular counterparts and
continuations, particularly in France. Printed Commonplace-Books
and the Structuring of Renaissance Thought is much more than an
account of humanist classroom practice: it is a major work of
cultural history.
Though the subject of this work, "nominalism and contemporary nom
inalism," is philosophical, it cannot be fully treated without
relating it to data gathered from a great variety of domains, such
as biology and more especially ethology, psychology, linguistics
and neurobiology. The source of inspiration has been an academic
work I wrote in order to obtain a postdoctoral degree, which is
called in Belgium an "Aggregaat voor het Hoger Onderwijs"
comparable to a "Habilitation" in Germany. I want to thank the
National Fund of Scientific Research, which accorded me several
grants and thereby enabled me to write the academic work in the
first place and thereafter this book. I also want to thank Prof.
SJ. Doorman (Technical University of Delft) and Prof. G. Nuchelmans
(University of Leiden), who were members of the jury of the "Aggre
gaatsthesis," presented to the Free University of Brussels in 1981
and who by their criticisms and suggestions encouraged me to write
the present book, the core of which is constituted by the general
ideas then formulated. I am further obliged to Mr. X, the referee
who was asked by Jaakko Hintikka to read my work and who made a
series of constructive remarks and recom mendations. My colleague
Marc De Mey (University of Ghent) helped me greatly with the more
formal aspects of my work and spent too much of his valuable time
and energy to enable me to deliver a presentable copy. All
remaining shortcomings are entirely my responsibility. I asked
Prof."
In this collection of articles, Kari Elisabeth Borresen and Kari
Vogt point out the convergence of androcentric gender models in the
Christian and Islamic traditions. They provide extensive surveys of
recent research in women's studies, with bio-socio-cultural
genderedness as their main analytical category. Matristic writers
from late Antiquity, the Middle Ages and the Renaissance are
analysed in terms of a female God language, reshaping traditional
theology. The persisting androcentrism of 20th-century Christianity
and Islam, as displayed in institutional documents promoting
women's specific functions, is critically exposed. This volume
presents a pioneering investigation of correlated Christian and
Islamic gender models which has hitherto remained uncompared by
women's studies in religion. This work will serve scholars and
students in the humanistic disciplines of theology, religious
studies, Islamic studies, history of ideas, Medieval philosophy and
women's history. "
In the year 1985, presumed to mark the 850th anniversary of
Maimonides' birth, the Sixth Jerusalem Philosophical Encounter was
dedicated to Maim onides as philosopher. We did not enter into the
other aspects of his work, rabbinical, legal, medical, etc., except
in so far as the relation between his philosophy and his work in
halakha (Jewish law) is itself a philosophical question. That no
one is quite certain about Maimonides' date of birth is symbolic of
the state of his philosophy as well. Maimonides' thought poses
various enigmas, lends itself to contradictory interpretations and
gives rise today, as it did in the Middle Ages, to sustained
controversies. Some of the contribu tions to the present volume
deal with these and cognate topics. Others deal with certain
aspects of the philosophical tradition in which Maimonides was
rooted, with some traits peculiar to the Islamic society in the
midst of which he lived, and with his influence on Christian
scholasticism. Maimonides' thought had many facets, and for this
and other reasons the question as to his place and stature in the
history of philosophy admits of no simple answer. In this volume an
attempt has been made to draw atten tion to some of these
complexities."
This book locates Christine de Pizan's argument that women are
virtuous members of the political community within the context of
earlier discussions of the relative virtues of men and women. It is
the first to explore how women were represented and addressed
within medieval discussions of the virtues. It introduces readers
to the little studied "Speculum Dominarum" (Mirror of Ladies), a
mirror for a princess, compiled for Jeanne of Navarre, which
circulated in the courtly milieu that nurtured Christine.Throwing
new light on the way in which Medieval women understood the
virtues, and were represented by others as virtuous subjects,
itpositions the ethical ideas of Anne of France, Laura Cereta,
Marguerite of Navarre and the Dames de la Roche within an evolving
discourse on the virtues that is marked by the transition from
Medieval to Renaissance thought.
"Virtue Ethics for Women 1250-1500" will be of interest to those
studying virtue ethics, the history of women's ideas and Medieval
and Renaissance thought in general."
This is a fully revised edition of one of the most successful
volumes in the Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought
series. Incorporating extensive updates to the editorial apparatus,
including the introduction, suggestions for further reading, and
footnotes, this third edition of More's Utopia has been
comprehensively re-worked to take into account scholarship
published since the second edition in 2002. The vivid and engaging
translation of the work itself by Robert M. Adams includes all the
ancillary materials by More's fellow humanists that, added to the
book at his own request, collectively constitute the first and best
interpretive guide to Utopia. Unlike other teaching editions of
Utopia, this edition keeps interpretive commentary - whether
editorial annotations or the many pungent marginal glosses that are
an especially attractive part of the humanist ancillary materials -
on the page they illuminate instead of relegating them to endnotes,
and provides students with a uniquely full and accessible
experience of More's perennially fascinating masterpiece.
In this groundbreaking collection of essays the history of
philosophy appears in a fresh light, not as reason's progressive
discovery of its universal conditions, but as a series of
unreconciled disputes over the proper way to conduct oneself as a
philosopher. By shifting focus from the philosopher as proxy for
the universal subject of reason to the philosopher as a special
persona arising from rival forms of self-cultivation, philosophy is
approached in terms of the social office and intellectual
deportment of the philosopher, as a personage with a definite moral
physiognomy and institutional setting. In so doing, this collection
of essays by leading figures in the fields of both philosophy and
the history of ideas provides access to key early modern disputes
over what it meant to be a philosopher, and to the institutional
and larger political and religious contexts in which such disputes
took place.
This book offers a comprehensive treatment of the philosophical
system of the seventeenth-century philosopher Pierre Gassendi.
Gassendi's importance is widely recognized and is essential for
understanding early modern philosophers and scientists such as
Locke, Leibniz and Newton. Offering a systematic overview of his
contributions, LoLordo situates Gassendi's views within the context
of sixteenth- and early seventeenth-century natural philosophy as
represented by a variety of intellectual traditions, including
scholastic Aristotelianism, Renaissance Neo-Platonism, and the
emerging mechanical philosophy. LoLordo's work will be essential
reading for historians of early modern philosophy and science.
Treatise on Divine Predestination is one of the early writings of
the author of the great philosophical work Periphyseon (On the
Division of Nature), Johannes Scottus (the Irishman), known as
Eriugena (died c. 877 A.D.). It contributes to the age-old debate
on the question of human destiny in the present world and in the
afterlife.
Since its publication in 1677, Spinoza s Ethics has fascinated
philosophers, novelists, and scientists alike. It is undoubtedly
one of the most exciting and contested works of Western philosophy.
Written in an austere, geometrical fashion, the work teaches us how
we should live, ending with an ethics in which the only thing good
in itself is understanding. Spinoza argues that only that which
hinders us from understanding is bad and shows that those endowed
with a human mind should devote themselves, as much as they can, to
a contemplative life. This Companion volume provides a detailed,
accessible exposition of the Ethics. Written by an internationally
known team of scholars, it is the first anthology to treat the
whole of the Ethics and is written in an accessible style.
The first Symposium consisted of three people in a cafe in Warsaw
in 1973. Since then, meetings have grown in size and have been held
in Leyden, Copenhagen, Nijmegen, Rome, Oxford, Poitiers and
Freiburg am-Breisgau. The ninth Symposium was held in St Andrews in
June 1990, with 57 participants who listened to addresses by 28
speakers. It was very fitting that Scotland's oldest university,
founded in the heyday of medievalleaming in 1411, should have been
given the chance to bring together scholars from all over Europe
and beyond to present their researches on the glorious past of
scholastic rational thought. The topic of the Symposium was
"Sophisms in Medieval Logic and Grammar". The present volume
consists, for the most part, of the papers presented at the
Symposium. In fact, however, it proved impossible to include five
of the contributions. Two of the papers included here were intended
for the Symposium but in the event not delivered, because of the
unavoidable absence of the speakers. The Symposium received very
helpful financial support from one of the major philosophical
associations in Britain, the Mind Association, from the
Philosophical Quarterly, a journal published at St Andrews, from
the University of St Andrews, from the British Academy, and from
Low and Bonarplc. In organising the programme for the conference
and in preparing the papers for publication I received invaluable
help from: Professor E.J.
By modern standards Bacon's writings are striking in their range
and diversity, and they are too often considered a separate
specialist concerns in isolation from each other. Dr Jardine finds
a unifying principle in Bacon's preoccupation with 'method', the
evaluation and organisation of information as a procedure of
investigation or of presentation. She shows how such an
interpretation makes consistent (and often surprising) sense of the
whole corpus of Bacon's writings: how the familiar but
misunderstood inductive method for natural science relations to the
more information strategies of argument in his historical, ethical,
political and literary work. There is a substantial and valuable
study of the intellectual Renaissance background from which Bacon
emerged and against which he reacted. Through a series of details
comparisons and contrasts we are led to appreciate the true
originality and ingenuity of Bacon's own views and also to discount
the more superficial resemblances between them and later
developments in the philosophy of science.
What made the Renaissance tick? Why had it such a force that its
thinking spread from a small group of scholars in Florence, working
in their own brilliant ways but coming together in Ficino's small
villa on the Florentine hillside, supported by the powerful but
highly intelligent Medici family - so that it affected the thinking
of the whole of Europe, and eventually of America, for five hundred
years and is continuing to do so? This is the first English
translation of some of the key works: Marsilio Ficino (1433-99),
having translated all the extant works of Plato's Greek philosophy
for the first time into Latin, absorbs their wisdom and here, in
forty short articles, presents to the Medici family, as his patrons
and sponsors, his commentaries on the meaning and implications of
twenty-five of Plato's Dialogues and of the twelve Letters
traditionally ascribed to Plato. The book puts the reader into the
moment of history when Cosimo de' Medici and his family were given
the opportunity which 'good rulers' have sought, from the earliest
Greek state till today, to unite power with wisdom. Though this
book will be an essential buy for Renaissance scholars and
historians, its freshness of thought and wisdom is presented by its
title, jacket illustration and introductory material as a book to
be reflected on by general readers of philosophy and wisdom. Here
is that extraordinary tsunami of human thought and endeavour and
sheer vital power that was the Renaissance, caught for us in its
early stirrings of new thought. This is a book of deep wisdom for
reflection, as well as a glimpse of mankind awakening once more to
its true potential.
The Spanish Jesuit Francisco Suarez (1548-1617) was an eminent
philosopher and theologian whose Disputationes Metaphysicae was
first published in Spain in 1597 and was widely studied throughout
Europe during the seventeenth century. The Disputationes
Metaphysicae had a great influence on the development of early
modern philosophy and on such well-known figures as Descartes and
Leibniz. This is the first time that Disputations 17, 18, and 19
have been translated into English. The Metaphysical Disputations
provide an excellent philosophical introduction to the medieval
Aristotelian discussion of efficient causality. The work
constitutes a synthesis of monumental proportions: problematic
issues are lucidly delineated and the various arguments are laid
out in depth. Disputations 17, 18, and 19 deal explicitly with such
issues as the nature of causality, the types of efficient causes,
the prerequisites for causal action, causal contingency, human free
choice, and chance.
In the great libraries of Europe and the United States, hidden in
fading manuscripts on forgotten shelves, lie the works of medieval
Hebrew logic. From the end of the twelfth century through the
Renaissance, Jews wrote and translated commentaries and original
compositions in Aristotelian logic. One can say without
exaggeration that wherever Jews studied philosophy - Spain, France,
Northern Africa, Germany, Palestine - they began their studies with
logic. Yet with few exceptions, the manuscripts that were
catalogued in the last century have failed to arouse the interest
of modem scholars. While the history of logic is now an established
sub-discipline of the history of philosophy, the history of Hebrew
logic is only in its infancy. The present work contains a
translation and commentary of what is arguably the greatest work of
Hebrew logic, the Sefer ha-Heqqesh ha-Yashar (The Book of the
Correct Syllogism) of Levi ben Gershom (Gersonides; 1288-1344).
Gersonides is well known today as a philosopher, astronomer,
mathematician, and biblical exegete. But in the Middle Ages he was
also famous for his prowess as a logician. The Correct Syllogism is
his attempt to construct a theory of the syllogism that is free of
what he considers to be the 'mistakes' of Aristotle, as interpreted
by the Moslem commentator A verroes. It is an absorbing,
challenging work, first written by Gersonides when he was merely
thirty-one years old, then significantly revised by him. The
translation presented here is of the revised version.
Modern developments in philosophy have provided us with tools,
logical and methodological, that were not available to Medieval
thinkers - a development that has its dangers as well as
opportunities. Modern tools allow one to penetrate old texts and
analyze old problems in new ways, offering interpretations that the
old thinkers could not have known. But unless one remains sensitive
to the fact that language has undergone changes, bringing with it a
shift in the meaning of terminology, one can easily perpetrate an
anachronism. Yet there is a growing need to bring modern tools and
to bear on the struggle for greater understanding of the problems
studied and the solutions found by the ancient scholars. If we
remain sensitive to the dangers, this openness to new methods can
be expected to widen our perspectives and deepen our knowledge of
old material. The focus in the present volume is on problems in
Medieval and contemporary philosophy of religion.
Neostoicism was one of the most important intellectual movements of
the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. It started in the
Protestant Netherlands during the revolt against Catholic Spain.
Very quickly it began to influence both the theory and practice of
politics in many parts of Europe. It proved to be particularly
useful and appropriate to the early modern militaristic states;
for, on the basis of the still generally accepted humanistic values
of classical antiquity, it promoted a strong central power in the
state, raised above the conflicting doctrines of the theologians.
Characteristically, a great part of Neostoic writing was concerned
with the nationally organized military institutions of the state.
Its aim was the general improvement of social discipline and the
education of the citizen to both the exercise and acceptance of
bureaucracy, controlled economic life and a large army.
Peter Abelard conducted many analyses of Scriptural and Patristic
teachings, and achieved an extensive rapprochement between
Christian and pagan thought. His public career was ended in 1140 by
an ecclesiastical condemnation, but this touched upon the central
issues facing the early leaders of the medieval scholastic movement
and Abelard's own teachings continued to be controversial. Dr
Luscombe considers the influence of Abelard's principal teachings
among his contemporaries and successors. his aim is to explain the
conflicting estimates of Abelard which were current in the twelfth
century and later, and to provide a full account of the writings
and varied fortunes of Abelard's disciples. He also examines the
manuscript tradition of Abelard's work and that of his followers.
The condemnation of 1140 repudiated Abelard's leading doctrines.
This led some of Abelard's disciples to partly retreat from the
position of their master, whereas some chose to adapt and extend
his teachings.
|
|