|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present
Almost everyone can run. Only very few can run a marathon. But what
is it for agents to be able to do things? This question, while
central to many debates in philosophy, is still awaiting a
comprehensive answer. The book provides just that. Drawing on some
valuable insights from previous works of abilities and making use
of possible world semantics, Jaster develops the "success view", a
view on which abilities are a matter of successful behavior. Along
the way, she explores the gradable nature of abilities, the
contextsensitivity of ability statements, the difference between
general and specific abilities, the relationship between abilities
and dispositions, and the ability to act otherwise. The book is
mandatory reading for anyone working on abilities, and provides
valuable insights for anyone dealing with agents' abilities in
other fields of philosophy. For this book, Romy Jaster has received
both the Wolfgang Stegmuller Prize and the De Gruyter Prize for
Analytical Philosophy of Mind or Metaphysics/Ontology.
The present volume contains many of the papers presented at a
four-day conference held by the Husserl-Archives in Leuven in April
2009 to c- memorate the one hundred and ?ftieth anniversary of
Edmund Husserl's birth. The conference was organized to facilitate
the critical evaluation of Husserl's philosophical project from
various perspectives and in light of the current philosophical and
scienti?c climate. Still today, the characteristic tension between
Husserl's concrete and detailed descriptions of consciousness, on
the one hand, and his radical philosophical claim to ultimate truth
and certainty in thinking, feeling, and acting, on the other, calls
for a sustained re?ection on the relation between a Husserlian
phenomenological philosophy and philosophy in general. What can
phenomenological re?ection contribute to the ongoing discussion of
certain perennial philosophical questions and which phi- sophical
problems are raised by a phenomenological philosophy itself? In
addition to addressing the question of the relation between p-
nomenology and philosophy in general, phenomenology today cannot
avoid addressing the nature of its relation to the methods and
results of the natural and human sciences. In fact, for Husserl,
phenomenology is not just one among many philosophical methods and
entirely unrelated to the sciences. Rather, according to Husserl,
phenomenology should be a "?rst philosophy" and should aim to
become the standard for all true science.
This book explores the ways deconstruction addresses the issue of
futurity (what Jacques Derrida calls the "to-come," [l'a-venir]).
In order to achieve this, it focuses on three French expressions,
venue, survenue, and voir-venir, each taken from the work of
Jacques Derrida, Jean-Luc Nancy, and Catherine Malabou. The idea
behind this focus is to elude the issue of the one and only
"to-come," as if this was a uniform and coherent entity or
structure of experience, and to put forward instead the possibility
of a multiplicity of structures, each with a different intonation
or pitch. Overall, this book makes an original contribution to the
way deconstruction addresses the issue of futurity in the act of
writing and translation.
If I am asked in the framework of Book 1, "Who are you?" I, in
answering, might say "I don't know who in the world I am."
Nevertheless there is a sense in which I always know what "I"
refers to and can never not know, even if I have become, e.g.,
amnesiac. Yet in Book 2, "Who are you?" has other senses of oneself
in mind than the non-sortal "myself". For example, it might be the
pragmatic context, as in a bureaucratic setting; but "Who are you?"
or "Who am I?" might be more anguished and be rendered by "What
sort of person are you?" or "What sort am I?" Such a question often
surfaces in the face of a "limit-situation", such as one's death or
in the wake of a shameful deed where we are compelled to find our
"centers", what we also will call "Existenz". "Existenz" here
refers to the center of the person. In the face of the
limit-situation one is called upon to act unconditionally in the
determination of oneself and one's being in the world. In this Book
2 we discuss chiefly one's normative personal-moral identity which
stands in contrast to the transcendental I where one's non-sortal
unique identity is given from the start. This moral identity
requires a unique self-determination and normative
self-constitution which may be thought of with the help of the
metaphor of "vocation". We will see that it has especial ties to
one's Existenz as well as to love. This Book 2 claims that the
moral-personal ideal sense of who one is is linked to the
transcendental who through a notion of entelechy. The person
strives to embody the I-ness that one both ineluctably is and
which, however, points to who one is not yet and who one ought to
be. The final two chapters tell a philosophical-theological likely
story of a basic theme of Plotinus: We must learn to honor
ourselves because of our honorable kinship and lineage "Yonder".
The discussion of Kant's Practical Philosophy has been marred by viewing it as purely formalist and centered only on the categorical imperative. This important new study sets out a much more vivid account of the nature and range of Kant's concerns demonstrating his commitment to the notion of rational religion and including extensive discussion of his treatment of evil. Culminating with accounts of property, the nature of right and virtue, this work presents Kant as a vital revolutionary thinker.
Engaging recent developments within the bio-cultural study of
religion, Shults unveils the evolved cognitive and coalitional
mechanisms by which god-conceptions are engendered in minds and
nurtured in societies. He discovers and attempts to liberate a
radically atheist trajectory that has long been suppressed within
the discipline of theology.
Literature and Encyclopedism in Enlightenment Britain tells the
story of long-term aspirations to comprehend, record, and
disseminate complete knowledge of the world. It draws on a wide
range of literary and non-literary works from the early modern era
and British Enlightenment.
Alain Badiou is arguably the most important and original
philosopher working in France today. Swimming against the tide of
postmodern orthodoxy, Badiou's thought revitalizes philosophy's
perennial attempt to provide a systematic theory of truth. This
volume, assembled with the collaboration of the author, presents
for the first time in English a comprehensive outline of Badiou's
ambitious system. Starting from the controversial assertion that
ontology is mathematics, this volume sets out the theory of the
emergence of truths from the singular relationship between a
subject and an event. Also included is a substantial excerpt from
Badiou's forthcoming work on the logics of appearance and the
concept of world, presented here in advance of its French
publication. Ranging from startling re-readings of canonical
figures (Spinoza, Kant and Hegel) to decisive engagements with
poetry, psychoanalysis and radical politics, Theoretical Writings
is an indispensable introduction to one of the great thinkers of
our time. The volume includes a preface by Alain Badiou, an
extensive editor's introduction, and a glossary of key terms.
Building on the results of the Groundwork and the Critique of
Practical Reason, Kant finally published his system of moral
philosophy in two volumes in 1797. By then, he had been planning to
write a Metaphysics of Morals for three decades; but only the title
remained unchanged while the basic principles of his theoretical
and practical philosophy changed dramatically. While for many years
academic moral philosophy focused mainly on Kant's earlier ethical
treatises, there has recently been much interest in this later and
perhaps more mature work on moral philosophy, particularly the
ethical part of the Metaphysics of Morals, the "Metaphysical
Principles of the Doctrine of Virtue" or "Tugendlehre". The present
volume responds to these demands. Following a series of research
workshops, 18 scholars from Germany, Italy, Britain and the United
States provide a seamless commentary on the "Doctrine of Virtue",
discussing topics such as suicide, truthfulness, moral perfection,
beneficence, gratitude, sympathy, respect and friendship as well as
Kant's moral psychology, philosophy of action and theory of moral
education. This book will be an invaluable resource for moral
philosophers and Kant scholars alike.
Even though important developments within 20th and 21st century
philosophy have widened the scope of epistemology, this has not yet
resulted in a systematic meta-epistemological debate about
epistemology's aims, methods, and criteria of success. Ideas such
as the methodology of reflective equilibrium, the proposal to
"naturalize" epistemology, constructivist impulses fuelling the
"sociology of scientific knowledge", pragmatist calls for taking
into account the practical point of epistemic evaluations, as well
as feminist criticism of the abstract and individualist assumptions
built into traditional epistemology are widely discussed, but they
have not typically resulted in the call for, let alone the
construction of, a suitable meta-epistemological framework. This
book motivates and elaborates such a new meta-epistemology. It
provides a pragmatist, social and functionalist account of
epistemic states that offers the conceptual space for revised or
even replaced epistemic concepts. This is what it means to
"refurbish epistemology": The book assesses conceptual tools in
relation to epistemology's functionally defined conceptual space,
responsive to both intra-epistemic considerations and political and
moral values.
Nietzsche, the so-called herald of the 'philosophy of the future',
nevertheless dealt with the past on nearly every page of his
writing. Not only was he concerned with how past values, cultural
practices and institutions influence the present - he was plainly
aware that any attempt to understand that influence encounters many
meta-historical problems. This comprehensive and lucid exposition
of the development of Nietzsche's philosophy of history explores
how Nietzsche thought about history and historiography throughout
his life and how it affected his most fundamental ideas. Discussion
of the whole span of Nietzsche's writings, from his earliest
publications as a classical philologist to his later genealogical
and autobiographical projects, is interwoven with careful analysis
of his own forms of writing history, the nineteenth-century
paradigms which he critiqued, and the twentieth-century views which
he anticipated. The book will be of much interest to scholars of
Nietzsche and of nineteenth-century philosophy.
The Courage of the Truth is the last course that Michel Foucault
delivered at the College de France before his death in 1984. In
this course, he continues the theme of the previous year's lectures
in exploring the notion of "truth-telling" in politics to establish
a number of ethically irreducible conditionsbased on courage and
conviction.
In the early twentieth century an apparently obscure philosophical
debate took place between F. H. Bradley and Bertrand Russell. The
historical outcome was momentous: the demise of the movement known
as British Idealism, and its eventual replacement by the various
forms of analytic philosophy. Since then, a conception of this
debate and its rights and wrongs has become entrenched in
English-language philosophy. Stewart Candlish examines afresh the
events of this formative period in twentieth-century thought and
comes to some surprising conclusions.
When I heard the rumor that the findings about the central nervous
system obtained with new technology, such as Magnetic Resonance
Imaging (MRI) and Positron Emission Tomography (PET), were too
subtle to correlate with the crude results of many decades of
behavioristic psychology, and that some psychologists were now
turning to descriptions of subjective phenomena in William James,
Edmund Husserl, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty-and even in Buddhism-I
asked myself, "Why not Aron Gurwitsch as well?" After all, my
teacher regularly reflected on the types, basic concepts, and
methods of psychology, worked with Adhemar Gelb and Kurt Goldstein
in the institute investigating brain-injured veterans at Frankfurt
in the 1920s, conspicuously employed Gestalt theory to revise
central Husserlian doctrines, and taught Merleau-Ponty a thing or
two. That the last book from his Nachlass had recently been
published and that I had recently written an essay on his theory of
1 psychology no doubt helped crystallize this project for me. What
is "cognitive science"? At one point in assembling this volume I
polled the participants, asking whether they preferred "the
cognitive sciences" or "cognitive science. " Most who answered
preferred the latter expression. There is still some vagueness here
for me, but I do suspect that cognitive science is 2 another
example of what I call a "multidiscipline. " A multidiscipline
includes participants who confront a set of issues that is best
approached under more than one disciplinary perspective."
The editor, Iso Kern, of the three volumes on intersubjectivity in
Husserliana XIII-XV, observes that in his "Nachlass" Husserl
probably refers to no other lecture so often as this one, i.e.,
"The Basic Problems of Phenomenology (1910-1911)." Husserl regarded
this work (along with the 1907 "Five Lectures") as basic for his
theory of the phenomenological reduction. He regarded these
lectures as equally fundamental for the theory of empathy and
intersubjectivity, for his theory of the life-world, and for his
planned "great systematic work." It contrasts favorably with
several later "introductions" because, although quite brief, it has
a larger scope than they do and conveys in a relatively elementary
way to the students the sense of fresh new beginnings. Further,
with the appendices, it reveals Husserl in a critical dialogue with
himself. That the second part of the lectures was never written
down, can be accounted for in part, because at that time Husserl
was busy writing the 1911 path-breaking essay, which complements
these lectures, "Philosophy as a Rigorous Science."
What role do fables play in Cartesian method and psychology? By
looking at Descartes' use of fables, James Griffith suggests there
is a fabular logic that runs to the heart of Descartes' philosophy.
First focusing on The World and the Discourse on Method, this
volume shows that by writing in fable form, Descartes allowed his
readers to break from Scholastic methods of philosophizing. With
this fable-structure or -logic in mind, the book reexamines the
relationship between analysis, synthesis, and inexact sciences;
between metaphysics and ethico-political life; and between the
imagination, the will, and the passions.
Consciousness: From Perception to Reflection in the History of
Philosophy shows that the concept of consciousness was explicated
relatively late in the tradition, but that its central features,
such as reflexivity, subjectivity and aboutness, attained avid
interest very early in philosophical debates. This book reveals how
these features have been related to other central topics, such as
selfhood, perception, attention and embodiment. At the same time,
the articles display that consciousness is not just an isolated
issue of philosophy of mind, but is bound to ontological,
epistemological and moral discussions. Integrating historical
inquiries into the systematic ones enables understanding the
complexity and richness of conscious phenomena.
To what extent can we doubt certainties? How are certainties
expressed in words? Which language games convey certainty? To
answer these questions we have to recall the method Wittgenstein
used in his investigations. When we look at language games and
forms of life as inseparable phenomena, do forms of life then
provide any certainty? On the other hand, do we automatically
relapse into relativism once we doubt certainties? Which formal
structures underlie certainty and doubt? The book is intended to
answer these questions.
The author argues that is not obvious what it means for our beliefs
and assertions to be "truth-directed," and that we need to weaken
our ordinary notion of a belief if we are to deal with radical
scepticism without surrendering to idealism. Topics examined also
include whether there could be alien conceptual schemes and what
might happen to us if we abandoned genuine belief in place of mere
pragmatic acceptance. A radically new "ecological" model of
knowledge is defended.
The cyberworld fast rolling in and impacting every aspect of human
living on the globe today presents an enormous challenge to
humankind. It is taken up by the media following current events
through to all kinds of natural- and social-scientific discourses.
Digitized technoscience develops at a breakneck pace in all areas
accompanied by sociological analysis. What is missing is a
philosophical response genuinely posing the basic ontological
question: What is a digital being's peculiar mode of being? The
present study offers a digital ontology that analyzes the
dissolution of beings into bit-strings, driven by mathematized
science. The mathematization of knowledge reaches back to
Pythagoras, Plato and Aristotle, and continues with Descartes,
Galileo, Newton, Leibniz. Western knowledge from its inception has
always been driven by an unbridled will to efficient-causal power
over all kinds of movement and change. This historical trajectory
culminates in the universal Turing machine that enables efficient,
automated, algorithmic control over the movement of digital beings
through the cyberworld. The book fills in the ontological
foundations underpinning this brave new cyberworld and interrogates
them, especially by questioning the millennia-old conception of
1D-linear time. An alternative ontology of movement arises, based
on a radically alternative conception of 3D-time.
Kant's omnipresence in contemporary cosmopolitan discourses
contrasts with the fact that little is known about the historical
origins and the systematic status of his cosmopolitan theory. This
study argues that Kant's cosmopolitanism should be understood as
embedded and dynamic. Inspired by Rousseau, Kant developed a form
of cosmopolitanism rooted in a modified form of republican
patriotism. In contrast to static forms of cosmopolitanism, Kant
conceived the tensions between embedded, local attachments and
cosmopolitan obligations in dynamic terms. He posited duties to
develop a cosmopolitan disposition (Gesinnung), to establish common
laws or cosmopolitan institutions, and to found and promote legal,
moral, and religious communities which reform themselves in a way
that they can pass the test of cosmopolitan universality. This is
the cornerstone of Kant's cosmopolitanism, and the key concept is
the vocation (Bestimmung) of the individual as well as of the human
species. Since realizing or at least approaching this vocation is a
long-term, arduous, and slow process, Kant turns to the pedagogical
implications of this cosmopolitan project and spells them out in
his later writings. This book uncovers Kant's hidden theory of
cosmopolitan education within the framework of his overall
practical philosophy.
|
|