|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present
If I am asked in the framework of Book 1, "Who are you?" I, in
answering, might say "I don't know who in the world I am."
Nevertheless there is a sense in which I always know what "I"
refers to and can never not know, even if I have become, e.g.,
amnesiac. Yet in Book 2, "Who are you?" has other senses of oneself
in mind than the non-sortal "myself". For example, it might be the
pragmatic context, as in a bureaucratic setting; but "Who are you?"
or "Who am I?" might be more anguished and be rendered by "What
sort of person are you?" or "What sort am I?" Such a question often
surfaces in the face of a "limit-situation", such as one's death or
in the wake of a shameful deed where we are compelled to find our
"centers", what we also will call "Existenz". "Existenz" here
refers to the center of the person. In the face of the
limit-situation one is called upon to act unconditionally in the
determination of oneself and one's being in the world. In this Book
2 we discuss chiefly one's normative personal-moral identity which
stands in contrast to the transcendental I where one's non-sortal
unique identity is given from the start. This moral identity
requires a unique self-determination and normative
self-constitution which may be thought of with the help of the
metaphor of "vocation". We will see that it has especial ties to
one's Existenz as well as to love. This Book 2 claims that the
moral-personal ideal sense of who one is is linked to the
transcendental who through a notion of entelechy. The person
strives to embody the I-ness that one both ineluctably is and
which, however, points to who one is not yet and who one ought to
be. The final two chapters tell a philosophical-theological likely
story of a basic theme of Plotinus: We must learn to honor
ourselves because of our honorable kinship and lineage "Yonder".
This book explores the ways deconstruction addresses the issue of
futurity (what Jacques Derrida calls the "to-come," [l'a-venir]).
In order to achieve this, it focuses on three French expressions,
venue, survenue, and voir-venir, each taken from the work of
Jacques Derrida, Jean-Luc Nancy, and Catherine Malabou. The idea
behind this focus is to elude the issue of the one and only
"to-come," as if this was a uniform and coherent entity or
structure of experience, and to put forward instead the possibility
of a multiplicity of structures, each with a different intonation
or pitch. Overall, this book makes an original contribution to the
way deconstruction addresses the issue of futurity in the act of
writing and translation.
Literature and Encyclopedism in Enlightenment Britain tells the
story of long-term aspirations to comprehend, record, and
disseminate complete knowledge of the world. It draws on a wide
range of literary and non-literary works from the early modern era
and British Enlightenment.
The digital age we now live in is fundamentally changing how we
relate to our perceptions and images. Daniel O'Shiel provides the
first comprehensive phenomenology of virtual technology in order to
show how the previously well-established experiential lines and
structures between three basic categories of phenomenal experience
- our everyday perceptions of reality; our everyday fantasies of
irreality; and our everyday engagements with external images, not
least digital ones - are becoming blurred, inverted or are even
collapsing in a new era where a specific type of virtuality is
coming to the fore. O'Shiel examines in depth just what this means
for the phenomenology behind it, as well as the concrete practical
consequences going forward. The work is divided into two main
parts. In the first O'Shiel fully investigates the phenomenological
natures of perception and imagination through close textual
analyses of the relevant works by Edmund Husserl, Eugen Fink and
Jean-Paul Sartre. In each phenomenologist perception and
imagination are ultimately seen as different in kind, although the
dividing line differs, especially with reference to a middle
category of 'image-consciousness' (Bildbewusstsein). This first
part argues for basic phenomenological differences between
perceptions; physical and external images; and more mental imagery,
while also allowing for a more general gradation between them. The
second part then applies these theoretical findings to some of the
most influential 'virtual technologies' today - social media;
online gaming; and some virtual, augmented and mixed reality
technologies - in order to show how previously clear categories of
real and irreal, present and absent, genuine and fake, and even
true and false, are becoming less so.
What role do fables play in Cartesian method and psychology? By
looking at Descartes' use of fables, James Griffith suggests there
is a fabular logic that runs to the heart of Descartes' philosophy.
First focusing on The World and the Discourse on Method, this
volume shows that by writing in fable form, Descartes allowed his
readers to break from Scholastic methods of philosophizing. With
this fable-structure or -logic in mind, the book reexamines the
relationship between analysis, synthesis, and inexact sciences;
between metaphysics and ethico-political life; and between the
imagination, the will, and the passions.
Building on the results of the Groundwork and the Critique of
Practical Reason, Kant finally published his system of moral
philosophy in two volumes in 1797. By then, he had been planning to
write a Metaphysics of Morals for three decades; but only the title
remained unchanged while the basic principles of his theoretical
and practical philosophy changed dramatically. While for many years
academic moral philosophy focused mainly on Kant's earlier ethical
treatises, there has recently been much interest in this later and
perhaps more mature work on moral philosophy, particularly the
ethical part of the Metaphysics of Morals, the "Metaphysical
Principles of the Doctrine of Virtue" or "Tugendlehre". The present
volume responds to these demands. Following a series of research
workshops, 18 scholars from Germany, Italy, Britain and the United
States provide a seamless commentary on the "Doctrine of Virtue",
discussing topics such as suicide, truthfulness, moral perfection,
beneficence, gratitude, sympathy, respect and friendship as well as
Kant's moral psychology, philosophy of action and theory of moral
education. This book will be an invaluable resource for moral
philosophers and Kant scholars alike.
The discussion of Kant's Practical Philosophy has been marred by viewing it as purely formalist and centered only on the categorical imperative. This important new study sets out a much more vivid account of the nature and range of Kant's concerns demonstrating his commitment to the notion of rational religion and including extensive discussion of his treatment of evil. Culminating with accounts of property, the nature of right and virtue, this work presents Kant as a vital revolutionary thinker.
Alain Badiou is arguably the most important and original
philosopher working in France today. Swimming against the tide of
postmodern orthodoxy, Badiou's thought revitalizes philosophy's
perennial attempt to provide a systematic theory of truth. This
volume, assembled with the collaboration of the author, presents
for the first time in English a comprehensive outline of Badiou's
ambitious system. Starting from the controversial assertion that
ontology is mathematics, this volume sets out the theory of the
emergence of truths from the singular relationship between a
subject and an event. Also included is a substantial excerpt from
Badiou's forthcoming work on the logics of appearance and the
concept of world, presented here in advance of its French
publication. Ranging from startling re-readings of canonical
figures (Spinoza, Kant and Hegel) to decisive engagements with
poetry, psychoanalysis and radical politics, Theoretical Writings
is an indispensable introduction to one of the great thinkers of
our time. The volume includes a preface by Alain Badiou, an
extensive editor's introduction, and a glossary of key terms.
The cyberworld fast rolling in and impacting every aspect of human
living on the globe today presents an enormous challenge to
humankind. It is taken up by the media following current events
through to all kinds of natural- and social-scientific discourses.
Digitized technoscience develops at a breakneck pace in all areas
accompanied by sociological analysis. What is missing is a
philosophical response genuinely posing the basic ontological
question: What is a digital being's peculiar mode of being? The
present study offers a digital ontology that analyzes the
dissolution of beings into bit-strings, driven by mathematized
science. The mathematization of knowledge reaches back to
Pythagoras, Plato and Aristotle, and continues with Descartes,
Galileo, Newton, Leibniz. Western knowledge from its inception has
always been driven by an unbridled will to efficient-causal power
over all kinds of movement and change. This historical trajectory
culminates in the universal Turing machine that enables efficient,
automated, algorithmic control over the movement of digital beings
through the cyberworld. The book fills in the ontological
foundations underpinning this brave new cyberworld and interrogates
them, especially by questioning the millennia-old conception of
1D-linear time. An alternative ontology of movement arises, based
on a radically alternative conception of 3D-time.
The Courage of the Truth is the last course that Michel Foucault
delivered at the College de France before his death in 1984. In
this course, he continues the theme of the previous year's lectures
in exploring the notion of "truth-telling" in politics to establish
a number of ethically irreducible conditionsbased on courage and
conviction.
In the early twentieth century an apparently obscure philosophical
debate took place between F. H. Bradley and Bertrand Russell. The
historical outcome was momentous: the demise of the movement known
as British Idealism, and its eventual replacement by the various
forms of analytic philosophy. Since then, a conception of this
debate and its rights and wrongs has become entrenched in
English-language philosophy. Stewart Candlish examines afresh the
events of this formative period in twentieth-century thought and
comes to some surprising conclusions.
Joseph Grange's beautifully written book provides a unique
synthesis of two major figures of world philosophy, John Dewey and
Confucius, and points the way to a global philosophy based on
American and Confucian values. Grange concentrates on the major
themes of experience, felt intelligence, and culture to make the
connections between these two giants of Western and Eastern
thought. He explains why the Chinese called Dewey "A Second
Confucius," and deepens our understanding of Confucius's concepts
of the way (dao) of human excellence (ren). The important
dimensions of American and Chinese cultural philosophy are welded
into an argument that calls for the liberation of what is finest in
both traditions. The work gives a new appreciation of fundamental
issues facing Chinese and American relations and brings the
opportunities and dangers of globalization into focus.
"The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms is a milestone in twentieth
century philosophy. Promoting a philosophical vision informed by
Kant, it incorporates the philosophical advances achieved in the
nineteenth century by German Idealism and Neo-Kantianism, whilst
acknowledging the contributions made by his contemporary
phenomenologists. It also encompasses empirical and historical
research on culture and the most contemporary work on myth,
linguistics and psychopathology. As such, it ranks in philosophical
importance along with other major works of the twentieth century,
such as Edmund Husserl's Logical Investigations, Martin Heidegger's
Being and Time, and Ludwig Wittgenstein's Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus. In the first volume, Cassirer explores the
symbolic form of language. Already recognized by thinkers in the
tradition of German Idealism, such as Wilhelm von Humboldt,
language is the primary medium by which we interact with others and
form a common world. As Cassirer emphasizes in the famous Davos
Debate with Heidegger, 'there is one objective human world, in
which a bridge is built from individual to individual. That I find
in the primal phenomenon of language.' The famous trias Cassirer
discerns in the functioning of language - the functions of
expression (Ausdruck), presentation (Darstellung), and
signification (Bedeutung) - has become paradigmatic for accounts of
language, philosophical, linguistic, and anthropological alike."
Sebastian Luft, Professor of Philosophy, Marquette University, USA.
This new translation makes Cassirer's seminal work available to a
new generation of scholars. Each volume includes a translator's
introduction by Steve G. Lofts, a foreword by Peter E. Gordon, a
glossary of key terms, and an index.
"The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms is one of the landmarks of
twentieth century philosophy. Drawing from the influential work of
Wilhelm Dilthey, it transformed neo-Kantianism into a new robust
philosophy of culture. The second volume, on Mythical Thinking,
analyzes the fundamental layers of perception and expression as
well as the articulations with religion and the dialectic with
other forms, essentially language and art. The intellectual breadth
of the volume is remarkable. It initiated the debate with Martin
Heidegger and prompted a long-lasting meditation by Hans
Blumenberg. We are only beginning to recognize its importance for
our understanding of the power of images in the construction of
aesthetics, the self, and the socio-political world. It initiated a
discussion within French sociology (Emile Durkheim, Marcel Mauss)
that ultimately resurfaced in Pierre Bourdieu, while today it is
considered as a resourceful path for cultural and critical theory
(Drucilla Cornell and Kenneth M. Panfilio). Finally, this volume
also offers solid grounds for a political critique of Nazism -
specifically: Alfred Rosenberg's Myth of the 20th Century and Adolf
Hitler's Mein Kampf - as well as the new emerging totalitarian
ideologies." Fabien Capeilleres, Professor of Philosophy, editor of
the French edition of Cassirer's Works. This new translation makes
Cassirer's seminal work available to a new generation of scholars.
Each volume includes a translator's introduction by Steve G. Lofts,
a foreword by Peter E. Gordon, a glossary of key terms, and an
index.
When I heard the rumor that the findings about the central nervous
system obtained with new technology, such as Magnetic Resonance
Imaging (MRI) and Positron Emission Tomography (PET), were too
subtle to correlate with the crude results of many decades of
behavioristic psychology, and that some psychologists were now
turning to descriptions of subjective phenomena in William James,
Edmund Husserl, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty-and even in Buddhism-I
asked myself, "Why not Aron Gurwitsch as well?" After all, my
teacher regularly reflected on the types, basic concepts, and
methods of psychology, worked with Adhemar Gelb and Kurt Goldstein
in the institute investigating brain-injured veterans at Frankfurt
in the 1920s, conspicuously employed Gestalt theory to revise
central Husserlian doctrines, and taught Merleau-Ponty a thing or
two. That the last book from his Nachlass had recently been
published and that I had recently written an essay on his theory of
1 psychology no doubt helped crystallize this project for me. What
is "cognitive science"? At one point in assembling this volume I
polled the participants, asking whether they preferred "the
cognitive sciences" or "cognitive science. " Most who answered
preferred the latter expression. There is still some vagueness here
for me, but I do suspect that cognitive science is 2 another
example of what I call a "multidiscipline. " A multidiscipline
includes participants who confront a set of issues that is best
approached under more than one disciplinary perspective."
In this volume, Baz offers a wide-ranging discussion of
Wittgenstein's remarks on aspect-perception, with special focus on
Wittgenstein's method. Baz starts out with an interpretation of
Wittgenstein's remarks on aspects and continues with attempts to
characterize and defend Wittgenstein's approach to the
understanding and dissolution of philosophical difficulties. Baz
ends with attempts to articulate-under the inspiration of
Merleau-Ponty's phenomenology-certain dissatisfactions, both with
Wittgenstein's remarks on aspect perception, and with his
philosophical approach more generally. On the way, Baz explores
connections between Wittgenstein's remarks on aspects and Kant's
aesthetics. He examines ways in which the remarks on aspects may be
brought to bear on contemporary philosophical work on perception.
He discusses some of the implications of Wittgenstein's work on
aspect perception for issues in moral philosophy and the philosophy
of action.
The editor, Iso Kern, of the three volumes on intersubjectivity in
Husserliana XIII-XV, observes that in his "Nachlass" Husserl
probably refers to no other lecture so often as this one, i.e.,
"The Basic Problems of Phenomenology (1910-1911)." Husserl regarded
this work (along with the 1907 "Five Lectures") as basic for his
theory of the phenomenological reduction. He regarded these
lectures as equally fundamental for the theory of empathy and
intersubjectivity, for his theory of the life-world, and for his
planned "great systematic work." It contrasts favorably with
several later "introductions" because, although quite brief, it has
a larger scope than they do and conveys in a relatively elementary
way to the students the sense of fresh new beginnings. Further,
with the appendices, it reveals Husserl in a critical dialogue with
himself. That the second part of the lectures was never written
down, can be accounted for in part, because at that time Husserl
was busy writing the 1911 path-breaking essay, which complements
these lectures, "Philosophy as a Rigorous Science."
Kant's omnipresence in contemporary cosmopolitan discourses
contrasts with the fact that little is known about the historical
origins and the systematic status of his cosmopolitan theory. This
study argues that Kant's cosmopolitanism should be understood as
embedded and dynamic. Inspired by Rousseau, Kant developed a form
of cosmopolitanism rooted in a modified form of republican
patriotism. In contrast to static forms of cosmopolitanism, Kant
conceived the tensions between embedded, local attachments and
cosmopolitan obligations in dynamic terms. He posited duties to
develop a cosmopolitan disposition (Gesinnung), to establish common
laws or cosmopolitan institutions, and to found and promote legal,
moral, and religious communities which reform themselves in a way
that they can pass the test of cosmopolitan universality. This is
the cornerstone of Kant's cosmopolitanism, and the key concept is
the vocation (Bestimmung) of the individual as well as of the human
species. Since realizing or at least approaching this vocation is a
long-term, arduous, and slow process, Kant turns to the pedagogical
implications of this cosmopolitan project and spells them out in
his later writings. This book uncovers Kant's hidden theory of
cosmopolitan education within the framework of his overall
practical philosophy.
To what extent can we doubt certainties? How are certainties
expressed in words? Which language games convey certainty? To
answer these questions we have to recall the method Wittgenstein
used in his investigations. When we look at language games and
forms of life as inseparable phenomena, do forms of life then
provide any certainty? On the other hand, do we automatically
relapse into relativism once we doubt certainties? Which formal
structures underlie certainty and doubt? The book is intended to
answer these questions.
|
|