|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present > Western philosophy, from c 1900 - > Analytical & linguistic philosophy
This revised and considerably expanded 2nd edition brings together
a wide range of topics, including modal, tense, conditional,
intuitionist, many-valued, paraconsistent, relevant, and fuzzy
logics. Part 1, on propositional logic, is the old Introduction,
but contains much new material. Part 2 is entirely new, and covers
quantification and identity for all the logics in Part 1. The
material is unified by the underlying theme of world semantics. All
of the topics are explained clearly using devices such as tableau
proofs, and their relation to current philosophical issues and
debates are discussed. Students with a basic understanding of
classical logic will find this book an invaluable introduction to
an area that has become of central importance in both logic and
philosophy. It will also interest people working in mathematics and
computer science who wish to know about the area.
Wilfrid Sellars, Idealism, and Realism is the first study of its
kind to address a range of realist and idealist views inspired by
psychological nominalism. Bringing together premier analytic
realists and distinguished defenders of German idealism, it reveals
why psychological nominalism is one of the most important theories
of the mind to come out the 20th century. The theory, first put
forward by Wilfrid Sellars, argues that language is the only means
by which humans can learn the types of socially shared practices
that permit rationality. Although wedded to important aspects of
German idealism, Sellars' theory is couched in bold realist terms
of the analytic tradition. Those who are sympathetic to German
idealism find this realist's appropriation of German idealism
problematic. Wilfrid Sellars, Idealism and Realism thus creates a
rare venue for realists and idealists to debate the epistemic
outcome of the mental processes they both claim are essential to
experience. Their resulting discussion bridges the gap between
analytic and continental philosophy. In providing original and
accessible chapters on psychological nominalism, this volume raises
themes that intersect with numerous disciplines: the philosophy of
mind, philosophy of language, epistemology, and metaphysics. It
also provides clarity on arguably the best available account of why
humans can reason, be self-aware, know, and act as agents.
Beauty and the End of Art shows how a resurgence of interest in
beauty and a sense of ending in Western art are challenging us to
rethink art, beauty and their relationship. By arguing that
Wittgenstein's later work and contemporary theory of perception
offer just what we need for a unified approach to art and beauty,
Sonia Sedivy provides new answers to these contemporary challenges.
These new accounts also provide support for the Wittgensteinian
realism and theory of perception that make them possible.
Wittgenstein's subtle form of realism explains artworks in terms of
norm governed practices that have their own varied constitutive
norms and values. Wittgensteinian realism also suggests that
diverse beauties become available and compelling in different
cultural eras and bring a shared 'higher-order' value into view.
With this framework in place, Sedivy argues that perception is a
form of engagement with the world that draws on our conceptual
capacities. This approach explains how perceptual experience and
the perceptible presence of the world are of value, helping to
account for the diversity of beauties that are available in
different historical contexts and why the many faces of beauty
allow us to experience the value of the world's perceptible
presence. Carefully examining contemporary debates about art,
aesthetics and perception, Beauty and the End of Art presents an
original approach. Insights from such diverse thinkers as Immanuel
Kant, Hans-Georg Gadamer and Arthur Danto, Alexander Nehamas,
Elaine Scarry and Dave Hickey are woven together to reveal how they
make good sense if we bring contemporary theory of perception and
Wittgensteinian realism into the conversation.
Wittgenstein: Comparisons and Context is a collection of P. M. S.
Hacker's papers on Wittgenstein and Wittgensteinian themes written
over the last decade. It presents Hacker's own (Wittgensteinian)
conception of philosophy, and defends it against criticisms. Two
essays compare Wittgenstein with Kant on transcendental arguments,
and offer a Wittgensteinian critique of Kant's transcendental
deduction. Two further essays trace the development of
Wittgenstein's philosophy of psychology, and examine his
anthropological and ethnological approach to philosophical
problems. This leads naturally to a synoptic comparison of
Wittgenstein's later philosophy of language with formal,
truth-conditional conceptions of language. A further two
clarificatory essays follow these comparative ones: the first
concerns Wittgenstein's conception of grammar, and his exclusion of
theses, doctrines, dogmas, and opinions in philosophy; the second
concerns his treatment of intentionality. The penultimate essay
examines Quine's epistemological naturalism, which is often
presented as a more scientific approach to philosophical problems
than Wittgenstein's. The final essay offers a synoptic view of
analytic philosophy and its history, in which Wittgenstein played
so notable a part. The volume complements Hacker's previous
collection, Wittgenstein: Connections and Controversies (OUP,
2001), but stands as an independent contribution to work in the
field.
Sandra Laugier has long been a key liaison between American and
European philosophical thought, responsible for bringing American
philosophers such as Ralph Waldo Emerson, Henry David Thoreau, and
Stanley Cavell to French readers - but until now her books have
never been published in English. "Why We Need Ordinary Language
Philosophy" rights that wrong with a topic perfect for
English-language readers: the idea of analytic philosophy. Focused
on clarity and logical argument, analytic philosophy has dominated
the discipline in the United States, Australia, and Britain over
the past one hundred years, and it is often seen as a unified,
coherent, and inevitable advancement. Laugier questions this
assumption, rethinking the very grounds that drove analytic
philosophy to develop and uncovering its inherent tensions and
confusions. Drawing on J. L. Austin and the later works of Ludwig
Wittgenstein, she argues for the solution provided by ordinary
language philosophy - a philosophy that trusts and utilizes the
everyday use of language and the clarity of meaning it provides -
and in doing so offers a major contribution to the philosophy of
language and twentieth- and twenty-first-century philosophy as a
whole.
Carnap, Quine, and Putnam held that in our pursuit of truth we can
do no better than to start in the middle, relying on
already-established beliefs and inferences and applying our best
methods for re-evaluating particular beliefs and inferences and
arriving at new ones. In this collection of essays, Gary Ebbs
interprets these thinkers' methodological views in the light of
their own philosophical commitments, and in the process refutes
some widespread misunderstandings of their views, reveals the real
strengths of their arguments, and exposes a number of problems that
they face. To solve these problems, in many of the essays Ebbs also
develops new philosophical approaches, including new theories of
logical truth, language use, reference and truth, truth by
convention, realism, trans-theoretical terms, agreement and
disagreement, radical belief revision, and contextually a priori
statements. His essays will be valuable for a wide range of readers
in analytic philosophy.
One of the first philosophers to relate Indian philosophical
thought to Western analytic philosophy, Jaysankar Lal Shaw has been
reflecting on analytic themes from Indian philosophy for over 40
years. This collection of his most important writings, introduces
his work and presents new ways of using Indian classical thought to
approach and understand Western philosophy. By expanding,
reinterpreting and reclassifying concepts and views of Indian
philosophers, Shaw applies them to the main issues and theories
discussed in contemporary philosophy of language and epistemology.
Carefully constructed, this volume of his collected writings, shows
the parallels Shaw draws between core topics in both traditions,
such as proper names, definite descriptions, meaning of a sentence,
knowledge, doubt, inference and testimony. It captures how Shaw
uses the techniques and concepts of Indian philosophers, especially
the followers of the Navya-Nyaya, to address global problems like
false belief, higher order knowledge and extraordinary perception.
Exploring timeless ideas from Indian thought alongside major issues
in contemporary philosophy, Shaw reveals how the two traditions can
interact and throw light on each other, providing better solutions
to philosophical problems. He has also reflected on modern issues
such as freedom, morality and harmony from the classical Indian
thought. Featuring a glossary and updates to his writings,The
Collected Writings of Jaysankar Lal Shaw: Indian Analytic and
Anglophone Philosophy also includes new work by Shaw on the
relationship between Indian and analytic philosophy today.
Language Lost and Found takes as its starting-point Iris Murdoch's
claim that "we have suffered a general loss of concepts." By means
of a thorough reading of Iris Murdoch's philosophy in the light of
this difficulty, it offers a detailed examination of the problem of
linguistic community and the roots of the thought that some
philosophical problems arise due to our having lost the sense of
our own language. But it is also a call for a radical
reconsideration of how philosophy and literature relate to each
other on a general level and in Murdoch's authorship in particular.
The American philosopher Wilfrid Sellars ranks as one of the
leading twentieth-century critics of empiricism a philosophical
approach to knowledge that seeks to ground it in human sense
experience. Sellars stood in the forefront of a recoil within
analytic philosophy from the foundationalist assumptions of
contemporary empiricists. "From Empiricism to Expressivism" is a
far-reaching reinterpretation of Sellars from one of the
philosopher s most brilliant intellectual heirs.
Unifying and extending Sellars s most important ideas, Robert
Brandom constructs a theory of pragmatic expressivism which, in
contrast to empiricism, understands meaning and knowledge in terms
of the role expressions play in social practices. The key lies in
Sellars s radical reworking of Kant s idea of the categories: the
idea that the expressive job characteristic of many of the most
important philosophical concepts is not to describe or explain the
empirical world but rather to make explicit essential features of
the conceptual framework that makes description and explanation
possible.
Brandom reconciles otherwise disparate elements of Sellars s
system, revealing a greater level of coherence and consistency in
the philosopher s arguments against empiricism than has usually
been acknowledged. "From Empiricism to Expressivism" clarifies what
Sellars had in mind when he talked about moving analytic philosophy
from its Humean to its Kantian phase, and why such a move might be
of crucial importance today."
Can literary fictions convey significant philosophical views,
understood in terms of propositional knowledge? This study
addresses the philosophical value of literature by examining how
literary works impart philosophy truth and knowledge and to what
extent the works should be approached as communications of their
authors. Beginning with theories of fiction, it examines the case
against the prevailing 'pretence' and 'make-believe' theories of
fiction hostile to propositional theories of literary truth.
Tackling further arguments against the cognitive function and value
of literature, this study illustrates how literary works can
contribute to knowledge by making assertions and suggestions and by
providing hypotheses for the reader to assess. Through clear
analysis of the concept of the author, the role of the authorial
intention and the different approaches to the 'meaning' of a
literary work, this study provides an historical survey to the
cognitivist-anti-cognitivist dispute, introducing contemporary
trends in the discussion before presenting a novel approach to
recognizing the cognitive function of literature. An important
contribution to philosophical studies of literature and knowledge.
Charles S. Peirce, the founder of pragmatism, was also the
architect of a remarkable theory of signs that continues to puzzle
and inspire philosophers today. In this important new book, Mats
Bergman articulates a bold new approach to Peirce's semeiotic
through a reassessment of the role of rhetoric in his work. This
systematic approach, which is offered as an alternative to
formalistic accounts of Peirce's project, shows how general
sign-theoretical conceptions can plausibly be interpreted as
abstractions from everyday communicative experiences and practices.
Building on this fallible ground of rhetoric-in-use, Bergman
explicates Peirce's semeiotic in a way that is conducive to the
development of rhetorical inquiry and philosophical criticism.
Following this path, the underpinnings of a uniquely Peircean
philosophy of communication is unearthed - a pragmatic conception
encased in a normative rhetoric, motivated by the continual need to
transform and improve our habits of action.
|
|