|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
Plato has often been read as denigrating the cognitive and ethical
value of poetry. In his dialogues, the faculty that corresponds to
the poetic the imagination is located at the lowest level of human
intelligence, and so it is furthest from true understanding.
Simultaneously, the Platonic dialogues violate Plato s own alleged
prohibitions against quoting and imitating poets, and much of the
writing in the dialogues is poetic. All too often, the voluminous
literature on Plato dismisses Plato s poetic formulations as merely
the unintended contradictions of an otherwise meticulous author. In
Praise of Plato s Poetic Imagination asks whether this ubiquitous
reading misses something truly significant in Plato s understanding
of the cognitive and ethical dimensions of human existence.
Throughout the dialogues, Plato formulates ideas so precisely,
utilizing carefully crafted images and structures, that we must
question whether his flagrant and performative poetics can be mere
mistakes, and inquire into how the poetic and creative arts
contribute to true understanding. This book approaches the latter
question by analyzing the role of the imagination in Platonic
dialogues. It argues that critiquing poetry by poetic means, just
as arguing against mimesis mimetically in the Republic or writing
against the written word in the Phaedrus, constitute performative
contradictions that bear significant philosophical meaning on
further examination. The book suggests that the elusive examples of
dialectic referred to in the divided line are the dialogues
themselves the putting into practice of ethical ideals. If so, the
role of the imagination is to be sought in the unfolding of the
dialogues themselves, not simply in what is said, but also in what
takes place within the dialogues.
'a wealth of detailed and resourceful argument that helps us to a
deeper understanding of the major philosophical issues' Terence
Irwin, Times Literary Supplement
Olympiodorus (AD c. 500-570), possibly the last non-Christian
teacher of philosophy in Alexandria, delivered these lectures as an
introduction to Plato with a biography. For us, they can serve as
an accessible introduction to late Neoplatonism. Olympiodorus
locates the First Alcibiades at the start of the curriculum on
Plato, because it is about self-knowledge. His pupils are
beginners, able to approach the hierarchy of philosophical virtues,
like the aristocratic playboy Alcibiades. Alcibiades needs to know
himself, at least as an individual with particular actions, before
he can reach the virtues of mere civic interaction. As Olympiodorus
addresses mainly Christian students, he tells them that the
different words they use are often symbols of truths shared between
their faiths.
This book articulates the theoretical outlines of a feminism
developed from Aristotle's metaphysics, making a new contribution
to feminist theory. Readers will discover why Aristotle was not a
feminist and how he might have become one, through an investigation
of Aristotle and Aristotelian tradition. The author shows how
Aristotle's metaphysics can be used to articulate a particularly
subtle and theoretically powerful understanding of gender that may
offer a highly useful tool for distinctively feminist arguments.
This work builds on Martha Nussbaum's 'capabilities approach' in a
more explicitly and thoroughly hylomorphist way. The author shows
how Aristotle's hylomorphic model, developed to run between the
extremes of Platonic dualism and Democritean atomism, can similarly
be used today to articulate a view of gender that takes bodily
differences seriously without reducing gender to biological
determinations. Although written for theorists, this scholarly yet
accessible book can be used to address more practical issues and
the final chapter explores women in universities as one example.
This book will appeal to both feminists with limited familiarity
with Aristotle's philosophy, and scholars of Aristotle with limited
familiarity with feminism.
This book is a study both of anachronism in antiquity and of
anachronism as a vehicle for understanding antiquity. It explores
the post-classical origins and changing meanings of the term
'anachronism' as well as the presence of anachronism in all its
forms in classical literature, criticism and material objects.
Contrary to the position taken by many modern philosophers of
history, this book argues that classical antiquity had a rich and
varied understanding of historical difference, which is reflected
in sophisticated notions of anachronism. This central hypothesis is
tested by an examination of attitudes to temporal errors in ancient
literary texts and chronological writings and by analysing notions
of anachronistic survival and multitemporality. Rather than seeing
a sense of anachronism as something that separates modernity from
antiquity, the book suggests that in both ancient writings and
their modern receptions chronological rupture can be used as a way
of creating a dialogue between past and present. With a selection
of case-studies and theoretical discussions presented in a manner
suitable for scholars and students both of classical antiquity and
of modern history, anthropology, and visual culture, the book's
ambition is to offer a new conceptual map of antiquity through the
notion of anachronism.
Socrates famously claimed that he knew nothing, and that wisdom
consisted in awareness of one's ignorance. In Ignorance, Irony and
Knowledge in Plato, Kevin Crotty makes the case for the centrality
and fruitfulness of Socratic ignorance throughout Plato's
philosophical career. Knowing that you don't know is more than a
maxim of intellectual humility; Plato shows how it lies at the
basis of all the virtues, and inspires dialogue, the best and most
characteristic activity of the philosophical life. Far from being
simply a lack or deficit, ignorance is a necessary constituent of
genuine knowledge. Crotty explores the intricate ironies involved
in the paradoxical relationship of ignorance and knowledge. He
argues, further, that Plato never abandoned the historical Socrates
to pursue his own philosophical agenda. Rather, his philosophical
career can be largely understood as a progressive deepening of his
appreciation of Socratic ignorance. Crotty presents Plato as a
forerunner of the scholarly interest in ignorance that has gathered
force in a wide variety of disciplines over the last 20 years.
How did writers understand the soul in late seventeenth-century
England? New discoveries in medicine and anatomy led Restoration
writers to question the substance of the soul and its motions in
literature written during the neo-Epicurean revival. Writers
throughout Stuart England found Lucretius both liberating and
disturbing and engaged Epicureanism in ways that cohered with their
own philosophy, beliefs, values, or perceptions of the soul.
Lucretian Thought in Late Stuart England considers depictions of
the soul in several representative literary texts from the period
that engage with Lucretius's Epicurean philosophy in De rerum
natura directly or through the writings of the most important
natural philosopher, anatomist, and prolific medical writer to
disseminate Epicurean atomism in Stuart England, Walter Charleton
(1619-1707). Laura Linker thoughtfully recasts the Restoration
literary imagination and offers close readings of the understudied
texts 'P. M. Gent' 's The Cimmerian Matron, To which is added; THE
MYSTERIES And MIRACLES OF LOVE (1668); George Etherege's The Man of
Mode (1676); and Lady Mary Chudleigh's Poems (1703).
Consciousness: From Perception to Reflection in the History of
Philosophy shows that the concept of consciousness was explicated
relatively late in the tradition, but that its central features,
such as reflexivity, subjectivity and aboutness, attained avid
interest very early in philosophical debates. This book reveals how
these features have been related to other central topics, such as
selfhood, perception, attention and embodiment. At the same time,
the articles display that consciousness is not just an isolated
issue of philosophy of mind, but is bound to ontological,
epistemological and moral discussions. Integrating historical
inquiries into the systematic ones enables understanding the
complexity and richness of conscious phenomena.
Richard Sorabji presents a fascinating study of Gandhi's philosophy
in comparison with Christian and Stoic thought. Sorabji shows that
Gandhi was a true philosopher. He not only aimed to give a
consistent self-critical rationale for his views, but also thought
himself obliged to live by what he taught-something that he had in
common with the ancient Greek and Christian ethical traditions.
Understanding his philosophy helps with re-assessing the
consistency of his positions and life. Gandhi was less influenced
by the Stoics than by Socrates, Christ, Christian writers, and
Indian thought. But whereas he re-interpreted those, he discovered
the congeniality of the Stoics too late to re-process them. They
could supply even more of the consistency he sought. He could show
them the effect of putting their unrealised ideals into actual
practice. They from the Cynics, he from the Bhagavadgita, learnt
the indifference of most objectives. But both had to square that
with their love for all humans and their political engagement.
Indifference was to both a source of freedom. Gandhi was converted
to non-violence by Tolstoy's picture of Christ. But he addressed
the sacrifice it called for, and called even protective killing
violent. He was nonetheless not a pacifist, because he recognized
the double-bind of rival duties, and the different duties of
different individuals, which was a Stoic theme. For both Gandhi and
the Stoics it accompanied doubts about universal rules. Sorabji's
expert understanding of these ethical traditions allows him to
offer illuminating new perspectives on a key intellectual figure of
the modern world, and to show the continuing resonance of ancient
philosophical ideas.
These essays reveal a dynamic range of interactions, reactions,
tensions, and ambiguities, showing how Greek literary creations
impacted and provided the background against which Greek philosophy
arose in more intricate and complex ways than previously believed.
This study explores the theoretical relationship between
Aristotle's theory of syllogism and his conception of demonstrative
knowledge. More specifically, I consider why Aristotle's theory of
demonstration presupposes his theory of syllogism. In reconsidering
the relationship between Aristotle's two Analytics, I modify this
widely discussed question. The problem of the relationship between
Aristotle's logic and his theory of proof is commonly approached
from the standpoint of whether the theory of demonstration
presupposes the theory of syllogism. By contrast, I assume the
theoretical relationship between these two theories from the start.
This assumption is based on much explicit textual evidence
indicating that Aristotle considers the theory of demonstration a
branch of the theory of syllogism. I see no textual reasons for
doubting the theoretical relationship between Aristotle's two
Analytics so I attempt to uncover here the common theoretical
assumptions that relate the syllogistic form of reasoning to the
cognitive state (i. e. , knowledge), which is attained through
syllogistic inferences. This modification of the traditional
approach reflects the wider objective of this essay. Unlike the
traditional interpretation, which views the Posterior Analytics in
light of scientific practice, this study aims to lay the foundation
for a comprehensive interpretation of the Posterior Analytics,
considering this work from a metaphysical perspective. One of my
major assertions is that Aristotle's conception of substance is
essential for a grasp of his theory of demonstration in general,
and of the role of syllogistic logic in particular.
The mythical narrative of transmigration tells the story of myriad
wandering souls, each migrating from body to body along a path of
recurrence amid the becoming of the All.
In this highly original study, James Luchte explores the ways in
which the concept of transmigration is a central motif in
Pythagoras' philosophy, representing its fundamental meaning.
Luchte argues that the many strands of the tale of transmigration
come together in the Pythagorean philosophical movement, revealing
a unity in which, for Pythagoreans, existence and eschatology are
separated only by forgetfulness. Such an interpretation that seeks
to retrieve the unity of Pythagorean thought goes against the grain
of a long-standing tradition of interpretation that projects upon
Pythagoras the segregation of 'mysticism' and 'science'. Luchte
lays out an alternative interpretation of Pythagorean philosophy as
magical in the sense that it orchestrates a holistic harmonization
of theoria and praxis and through this reading discloses the
radical character of Pythagorean philosophy.
The earlier part of the commentary by 'Philoponus' on Aristotle's
On the Soul is translated by William Charlton in another volume in
the series. This volume includes the latter part of the commentary
along with a translation of Stephanus' commentary on Aristotle 's
On Interpretation. It thus enables readers to assess for themselves
Charlton's view that the commentary once ascribed to Philoponus
should in fact be ascribed to Stephanus. The two treatises of
Aristotle here commented on are very different from each other. In
On Interpretation Aristotle studies the logic of opposed pairs of
statements. It is in this context that Aristotle discusses the
nature of language and the implications for determinism of opposed
predictions about a future occurrence, such as a sea-battle. And
Stephanus, like his predecessor Ammonius, brings in other
deterministic arguments not considered by Aristotle ('The Reaper'
and the argument from God's foreknowledge). In On the Soul 3.9-13,
Aristotle introduces a theory of action and motivation and sums up
the role of perception in animal life. Despite the differences in
subject matter between the two texts, Charlton is able to make a
good case for Stephanus' authorship of both commentaries. He also
sees Stephanus as preserving what was valuable from Ammonius'
earlier commentary On Interpretation, while bringing to bear the
virtue of greater concision. At the same time, Stephanus reveals
his Christian affiliations, in contrast to Ammonius, his pagan
predecessor.
In the year 62, citing health issues, the Roman philosopher Seneca
withdrew from public service and devoted his time to writing. His
letters from this period offer a window into his experience as a
landowner, a traveler through Roman Italy, and a man coping with
the onset of old age. They describe the roar of the arena, the
festival of Saturnalia, and the perils of the Adriatic Sea, and
they explain his thoughts about political power, the treatment of
slaves, the origins of civilization, and the key points of Stoic
philosophy. This selection of fifty of his letters brings Seneca to
readers in a fresh modern voice and shows how, as a philosopher, he
speaks to our time. Above all, these letters explore the inner life
of the individual: from the life of heedless vanity to the first
interest in philosophy, to true friendship, self-determination, and
personal excellence.
This volume consists of fourteen essays in honor of Daniel Devereux
on the themes of love, friendship, and wisdom in Plato, Aristotle,
and the Epicureans. Philia (friendship) and eros (love) are topics
of major philosophical interest in ancient Greek philosophy. They
are also topics of growing interest and importance in contemporary
philosophy, much of which is inspired by ancient discussions.
Philosophy is itself, of course, a special sort of love, viz. the
love of wisdom. Loving in the right way is very closely connected
to doing philosophy, cultivating wisdom, and living well. The first
nine essays run the gamut of Plato's philosophical career. They
include discussions of the >Alcibiades<, >Euthydemus<,
>Gorgias<, >Phaedo<, >Phaedrus<, and
>Symposium<. The next four essays turn to Aristotle and
include treatments of the >Nicomachean Ethics< and
>Politics< as well as the lesser-known works
>Protrepticus< and >Magna Moralia<. The volume ends
with friendship in the Epicureans. As a whole, the volume brings
out the centrality of love and friendship for the conception of the
philosophical life held by the ancients. The book should appeal to
anyone interested in these works or in the topics of love,
friendship, or wisdom.
In On the Soul 3.1-8, Aristotle first discusses the functions
common to all five senses, such as self-awareness, and then moves
on to Imagination and Intellect. This commentary on Aristotle's
text has traditionally been ascribed to Philoponus, but William
Charlton argues here that it should be ascribed to a later
commentator, Stephanus. (The quotation marks used around his name
indicate this disputed authorship.) 'Philoponus' reports the
postulation of a special faculty for self-awareness, intended to
preserve the unity of the person. He disagrees with 'Simplicius',
the author of another commentary on On the Soul (also available in
this series), by insisting that Imagination can apprehend things as
true or false, and he disagrees with Aristotle by saying that we
are not always free to imagine them otherwise than as they are. On
Aristotle's Active Intellect. 'Philoponus' surveys different
interpretations, but ascribes to Plutarch of Athens, and rejects,
the view adopted by the real Philoponus in his commentary on
Aristotle's On Intellect that we have innate intellectual knowledge
from a previous existence. Instead he takes the view that the
Active Intellect enables us to form concepts by abstraction through
serving as a model of something already separate from matter. Our
commentator further disagrees with the real Philoponus by denying
the Idealistic view that Platonic forms are intellects. Charlton
sees 'Philoponus' as the excellent teacher and expositor that
Stephanus was said to be.
In "On the Soul" 3.1-5, Aristotle goes beyond the five senses to
the general functions of sense perception, the imagination and the
so-called active intellect, whose identity was still a matter of
controversy in the time of Thomas Aquinas. In his commentary on
Aristotle's text, Simplicius insists that the intellect in question
is not something transcendental, but the human rational soul. He
denies both Plotinus' view that a part of our soul has never
descended from uninterrupted contemplation of the Platonic forms,
and Proclus' view that our soul cannot be changed in its substance
through embodiment. Continuing the debate in Carlos Steel's earlier
volume in this series, Henry Blumenthal assesses the authorship of
the commentary. He concludes against it being by Simplicius, but
not for its being by Priscian. In a novel interpretation, he
suggests that if Priscian had any hand in it at all, it might have
been as editor of notes from Simplicius' lectures.
A detailed research work for the study of the origins,
development, and significance of the Cynical movement among the
Greeks and Romans. The purpose of this volume is to provide
bibliographical information on over 650 books and articles dealing
with various aspects of Cynicism. These works were written as early
as the 16th century and as recently as 1994 in a variety of
languages. This volume includes numerous revealing quotations from
the annotated works. It is a valuable research instrument for
anyone interested in the history of ideas.
The contributions of the Cynic philosophers, both Greek and
Roman, were many. In many ways they were significant in the
development of Western philosophy. The Cynics were a familiar sight
in classical times. They saw themselves as having been called to
fulfill a mission, namely, the denunciation of ordinary human
values and conventions. Offering a wide spectrum of approaches to
Cynicism, the works detailed in this volume include general
histories of philosophy (especially Greek), monographs on Cynicism,
doctoral and university dissertations, collections of articles from
journals and magazines, poetic and dramatic pieces, and
encyclopedia and dictionary entries--selections from strictly
scholarly works in philosophy and philology to popularizations of
Cynic ideas.
The Continuous and the Discrete presents a detailed analysis of
three ancient models of spatial magnitude, time, and local motion.
Professor White connects the Aristotelian model, which represents
spatial magnitude, time, and motion as infinitely divisible and
continuous, with the standard ancient geometrical conception of
extended magnitude. Thus the Aristotelian model is presented as the
marriage of physical theory and mathematical orthodoxy. In the
second half of the book the author discusses two ancient
alternatives to the Aristotelian model: 'quantum' models, and a
Stoic model according to which limit entities such as points,
(one-dimensional) edges, and (two-dimensional) surfaces do not
exist in (physical) reality. Both these alternative models deny the
applicability of standard 'Euclidean' ancient geometry to the
physical world. A unique feature of the book is the discussion of
these ancient models within the context of later philosophical,
scientific, and mathematical developments. A basic assumption of
the author's approach is that such a contemporary perspective can
deepen our understanding not only of ancient philosophy, physics,
and mathematics, but also of later developments in the content and
methodology of these disciplines.
Two treatises on memory which have come down to us from antiquity
are Aristotle's "On memory and recollection" and Plotinus' "On
perception and memory" (IV 6); the latter also wrote at length
about memory in his "Problems connected with the soul" (IV 3-4,
esp. 3.25-4.6). In both authors memory is treated as a 'modest'
faculty: both authors assume the existence of a persistent subject
to whom memory belongs; and basic cognitive capacities are assumed
on which memory depends. In particular, both theories use phantasia
(representation) to explain memory. Aristotle takes representations
to be changes in concrete living things which arise from actual
perception. To be connected to the original perception the
representation has to be taken as a (kind of) copy of the original
experience - this is the way Aristotle defines memory at the end of
his investigation. Plotinus does not define memory: he is concerned
with the question of what remembers. This is of course the soul,
which goes through different stages of incarnation and
disincarnation. Since the disembodied soul can remember, so he does
not have Aristotle's resources for explaining the continued
presence of representations as changes in the concrete thing.
Instead, he thinks that when acquiring a memory we acquire a
capacity in respect of the object of the memory, namely to make it
present at a later time.
|
You may like...
A New Innings
Manoj Badale, Simon Hughes
Hardcover
R608
Discovery Miles 6 080
|