|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
Throughout the history of philosophy, skepticism has posed one of
the central challenges of epistemology. Opponents of
skepticism--including externalists, contextualists,
foundationalists, and coherentists--have focussed largely on one
particular variety of skepticism, often called Cartesian or
Academic skepticism, which makes the radical claim that nobody can
know anything. However, this version of skepticism is something of
a straw man, since virtually no philosopher endorses this radical
skeptical claim. The only skeptical view that has been truly
held--by Sextus, Montaigne, Hume, Wittgenstein, and, most recently,
Robert Fogelin--has been Pyrrohnian skepticism. Pyrrhonian skeptics
do not assert Cartesian skepticism, but neither do they deny it.
The Pyrrhonian skeptics' doubts run so deep that they suspend
belief even about Cartesian skepticism and its denial. Nonetheless,
some Pyrrhonians argue that they can still hold "common beliefs of
everyday life" and can even claim to know some truths in an
everyday way.
This edited volume presents previously unpublished articles on this
subject by a strikingly impressive group of philosophers, who
engage with both historical and contemporary versions of Pyrrhonian
skepticism. Among them are Gisela Striker, Janet Broughton, Don
Garrett, Ken Winkler, Hans Sluga, Ernest Sosa, Michael Williams,
Barry Stroud, Robert Fogelin, and Roy Sorensen. This volume is
thematically unified and will interest a broad spectrum of scholars
in epistemology and the history of philosophy.
Roslyn Weiss contends that, contrary to prevailing notions, Plato's Crito does not show an allegiance between Socrates and the state that condemned him. Weiss argues that Socrates considers the laws of the state to be more concerned with creating deference than justice, and asserts that, by submitting to his judgement, Socrates acts from a personal sense of justice rather than a set of imposed rules.
This book explores the complex relationship between myth and philosophy in writings by Greek intellectuals between the late-sixth and mid-fourth centuries BC. Although philosophy may seem far removed from mythological stories, closer examination reveals that Plato and others realized that philosophic accounts too were "stories" about reality. Kathryn Morgan shows how these philosophers used myth to express philosophic problems. Her book traces a tradition of strictly rational and philosophical myth through two centuries.
Greek tragedy occupies a prominent place in the development of
early Greek thought. However, even within the partial renaissance
of debates about tragedy's roots in the popular thought of archaic
Greece, its potential connection to the early philosophical
tradition remains, with few exceptions, at the periphery of current
interest. This book aims to show that our understanding of
Aeschylus' Oresteia is enhanced by seeing that the trilogy's
treatment of Zeus and Justice (Dike) shares certain concepts,
assumptions, categories of thought, and forms of expression with
the surviving fragments and doxography of certain Presocratic
thinkers (especially Anaximander, Xenophanes, Heraclitus, and
Parmenides). By examining several aspects of the tragic trilogy in
relation to Presocratic debates about theology and cosmic justice,
it shows how such scrutiny may affect our understanding of the
theological 'tension' and metaphysical assumptions underpinning the
Oresteia's dramatic narrative. Ultimately, it argues that Aeschylus
bestows on the experience of human suffering, as it is given in the
contradictory multiplicity of the world, the status of a profound
form of knowledge: a meeting point between the human and divine
spheres.
This book presents a thorough study and an up to date anthology of
Plato's Protagoras. International authors' papers contribute to the
task of understanding how Plato introduced and negotiated a new
type of intellectual practice - called philosophy - and the
strategies that this involved. They explore Plato's dialogue,
looking at questions of how philosophy and sophistry relate, both
on a methodological and on a thematic level. While many of the
contributing authors argue for a sharp distinction between
sophistry and philosophy, this is contested by others. Readers may
consider the distinctions between philosophy and traditional forms
of poetry and sophistry through these papers. Questions for
readers' attention include: To what extent is Socrates' preferred
mode of discourse, and his short questions and answers, superior to
Protagoras' method of sophistic teaching? And why does Plato make
Socrates and Protagoras reverse positions as it comes to virtue and
its teachability? This book will appeal to graduates and
researchers with an interest in the origins of philosophy,
classical philosophy and historical philosophy.
Plato's Republic is one of the most well-known and widely discussed
texts in the history of philosophy, but how might we get to the
heart of this work today, 2500 years after it was originally
composed? Alain Badiou invents a new genre in order to breathe
fresh life into Plato's text and restore its universality. Rather
than producing yet another critical commentary, he has retranslated
the work from the original Greek and, by making various changes,
adapted it for our times. In this innovative reimagining of a
classic text, Badiou has removed all references specific to ancient
Greek society, from the endless exchanges about the moral courage
of poets to those political considerations that were only of
interest to the aristocratic elite. On the other hand, Badiou has
expanded the range of cultural references: here philosophy is
firing on all cylinders, and Socrates and his companions are joined
by Beckett, Pessoa, Freud and Hegel. They demonstrate the enduring
nature of true philosophy, always ready to move with the times.
Moreover, Badiou the dramatist has made the Socratic dialogue a
true oratorial contest: in his version of the Republic, the
interlocutors have more in mind than merely agreeing with the
Master. They stand up to him, put him on the spot and thereby show
thought in motion. Through this work of writing, scholarship and
philosophy, we are able, for the first time, to read a version of
Plato's text which is alive, stimulating and directly relevant to
our world today.
A new approach to understanding the relationship between
Aristotle's political philosophy and the natural law tradition.
"Aristotle and Natural Law" offers an important new examination of
Aristotle's political thought and its relationship to the natural
law tradition. The book challenges recent alternative
interpretations of Aristotle and argues that Aristotle's ethics is
most usefully seen as a particular type of natural law theory. Tony
Burns shows that the type of natural law theory to which Aristotle
subscribes is an unusual one because it does not allow for the
possibility that individuals might appeal to natural law in order
to critically evaluate existing laws and institutions. Rather its
function is to provide legitimacy for existing laws and conventions
by providing them with a philosophical justification from the
standpoint of Aristotle's metaphysics. Burns claims that this way
of thinking about natural law can be traced in the writings of a
number of thinkers in the history of philosophy, from Aquinas
through to Hegel, but argues that because this tradition begins
with Aristotle it is appropriate to describe it as 'the
Aristotelian natural law tradition'. "Continuum Studies in Ancient
Philosophy" presents cutting edge scholarship in the history of
ancient philosophy. The wholly original arguments, perspectives and
research findings in titles in this series make it an important and
stimulating resource for students and academics from across the
fields of Philosophy and Classical Studies.
Chinese and Greek ethics remain influential in modern philosophy,
yet it is unclear how they can be compared to one another. This
volume, following its predecssor 'How should one live?' (DeGruyter
2011), is a contribution to comparative ethics, loosely centered on
the concepts of life and the good life. Methods of comparing ethics
are treated in three introductory chapters (R.A.H.King, Ralph
Weber, G.E.R. Lloyd), followed by chapters on core issues in each
of the traditions: human nature (David Wong, Guo Yi), ghosts (Paul
Goldin), happiness (Christoph Harbsmeier), pleasure (Michael
Nylan), qi (Elisabeth Hsu & Zhang Ruqing), cosmic life and
individual life (Dennis Schilling), the concept of mind (William
Charlton), knowledge and happiness (Joerg Hardy), filial piety
(Richard Stalley), the soul (Hua-kuei Ho), and deliberation (Thomas
Buchheim). The volume closes with three essays in comparison -
Mencius and the Stoics (R.A.H. King), equanimity (Lee Yearley),
autonomy and the good life (Lisa Raphals). An index locorum each
for Chinese and Greco-Roman authors, and a general index complete
the volume.
This book argues that, rather than being conceived merely as a
hindrance, the body contributes constructively in the fashioning of
a Platonic unified self. The Phaedo shows awareness that the
indeterminacy inherent in the body infects the validity of any
scientific argument but also provides the subject of inquiry with
the ability to actualize, to the extent possible, the ideal self.
The Republic locates bodily desires and needs in the tripartite
soul. Achievement of maximal unity is dependent upon successful
training of the rational part of the soul, but the earlier
curriculum of Books 2 and 3, which aims at instilling a
pre-reflectively virtuous disposition in the lower parts of the
soul, is a prerequisite for the advanced studies of Republic 7. In
the Timaeus, the world soul is fashioned out of Being, Sameness,
and Difference: an examination of the Sophist and the Parmenides
reveals that Difference is to be identified with the Timaeus'
Receptacle, the third ontological principle which emerges as the
quasi-material component that provides each individual soul with
the alloplastic capacity for psychological growth and alteration.
This is a radically new interpretation of Plato's Meno. Roslyn Weiss takes and defends the position that the Meno is a self-conscious analysis and assessment of the worth not of inquiry itself, but of moral inquiry. Her coherent reading of the Meno identifies serious problems for orthodox interpretations and will appeal to anyone interested in ancient philosophy and the classics.
Lucretius' philosophical epic De Rerum Natura (On the Nature of
Things) is a lengthy didactic and narrative celebration of the
universe and, in particular, the world of nature and creation in
which humanity finds its abode. This earliest surviving full scale
epic poem from ancient Rome was of immense influence and
significance to the development of the Latin epic tradition, and
continues to challenge and haunt its readers to the present day. A
Reading of Lucretius' De Rerum Natura offers a comprehensive
commentary on this great work of Roman poetry and philosophy. Lee
Fratantuono reveals Lucretius to be a poet with deep and abiding
interest in the nature of the Roman identity as the children of
both Venus (through Aeneas) and Mars (through Romulus); the
consequences (both positive and negative) of descent from the
immortal powers of love and war are explored in vivid epic
narrative, as the poet progresses from his invocation to the mother
of the children of Aeneas through to the burning funeral pyres of
the plague at Athens. Lucretius' epic offers the possibility of
serenity and peaceful reflection on the mysteries of the nature of
the world, even as it shatters any hope of immortality through its
bleak vision of post mortem oblivion. And in the process of
defining what it means both to be human and Roman, Lucretius offers
a horrifying vision of the perils of excessive devotion both to the
gods and our fellow men, a commentary on the nature of pietas that
would serve as a warning for Virgil in his later depiction of the
Trojan Aeneas.
Marina McCoy explores Plato's treatment of the rhetoric of
philosophers and sophists through a thematic treatment of six
different Platonic dialogues, including Apology, Protagoras,
Gorgias, Republic, Sophist, and Phaedras. She argues that Plato
presents the philosopher and the sophist as difficult to
distinguish, insofar as both use rhetoric as part of their
arguments. Plato does not present philosophy as rhetoric-free, but
rather shows that rhetoric is an integral part of philosophy.
However, the philosopher and the sophist are distinguished by the
philosopher's love of the forms as the ultimate objects of desire.
It is this love of the forms that informs the philosopher's
rhetoric, which he uses to lead his partner to better understand
his deepest desires. McCoy's work is of interest to philosophers,
classicists, and communications specialists alike in its careful
yet comprehensive treatment of philosophy, sophistry, and rhetoric
as portrayed through the drama of the dialogues.
This book combines the mainstream liberal arguments for religious
tolerance with arguments from religious traditions in India to
offer insights into appropriate attitudes toward religious 'others'
from the perspective of the devout. The respective chapters address
the relationship between religions from a comparative perspective,
helping readers understand the meaning of religion and the
opportunities for interreligious dialogue in the works of
contemporary Indian philosophers such as Gandhi and Ramakrishna
Paramhansa. It also examines various religious traditions from a
philosophical viewpoint in order to reassess religious discussions
on how to respond to differing and different religious others.
Given its comprehensive coverage, the book is of interest to
scholars working in the areas of anthropology, philosophy, cultural
and religious diversity, and history of religion.
Plotinus' mysticism of henosis, unification with the One, is a
highly controversial topic in Plotinian scholarship. This book
presents a careful reading of the Enneads and suggests that
Plotinus' mysticism be understood as mystical teaching that offers
practical guidance concerning henosis. It is further argued that a
rational interpretation thereof should be based on Plotinus'
metaphysics, according to which the One transcends all beings but
is immanent in them. The main thesis of this book is that Plotinus'
mystical teaching does not help man attain henosis on his own, but
serves to remind man that he fails to attain henosis because it
already pertains to his original condition. Plotinus' mysticism
seeks to change man's misconception about henosis, rather than his
finite nature.
Cosmology and Self in the Apostle Paul challenges the traditional
reading of Paul. Troels Engberg-Pedersen argues that the usual,
mainly cognitive and metaphorical, ways of understanding central
Pauline concepts, such as 'being in Christ', 'having God's pneuma
(spirit), Christ's pneuma, and Christ himself in one', must be
supplemented by a literal understanding that directly reflects
Paul's cosmology.
Engberg-Pedersen shows that Paul's cosmology, not least his
understanding of the pneuma, was a materialist, bodily one: the
pneuma was a physical element that would at the resurrection act
directly on the ordinary human bodies of believers and transform
them into 'pneumatic bodies'. This literal understanding of the
future events is then traced back to the Pauline present as
Engberg-Pedersen considers how Paul conceived in bodily terms of a
range of central themes like his own conversion, his mission, the
believers' reception of the pneuma in baptism, and the way the
apostle took the pneuma to inform his own and their ways of life
from the beginning to the projected end.
In developing this picture of Paul's world view, an explicitly
philosophically oriented form of interpretation ('philosophical
exegesis') is employed, in which the interpreter applies categories
of interpretation that make sense philosophically, whether in an
ancient or a modern context. For this enterprise Engberg-Pedersen
draws in particular on ancient Stoic materialist and monistic
physics and cosmology - as opposed to the Platonic, immaterialist
and dualistic categories that underlie traditional readings of Paul
- and on modern ideas on 'religious experience', 'self', 'body' and
'practice' derived from Foucault and Bourdieu. In this way Paul is
shown to have spelled out philosophically his Jewish, 'apocalyptic'
world view, which remains a central feature of his thought.
The book states the cosmological case for the author's earlier
'ethical' reading of Paul in his prize-winning book, Paul and the
Stoics (2000).
Both Aristotle and moral psychology have been flourishing areas of
philosophical inquiry in recent years. This volume aims to bring
the two streams of research together, offering a fresh infusion of
Aristotelian insights into moral psychology and philosophy of
action, and the application of developed philosophical sensibility
as regards the reading of Aristotelian texts. The contributors
offer stimulating new examinations of Aristotle's understanding of
the various psychological states, dispositions, processes, and acts
-- including reasoning and deliberation -- that contribute to the
understanding of human action and its ethical appraisal.
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy is a volume of original
articles on all aspects of ancient philosophy. The articles may be
of substantial length, and include critical notices of major books.
OSAP is now published twice yearly, in both hardback and paperback.
'The serial Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (OSAP) is fairly
regarded as the leading venue for publication in ancient
philosophy. It is where one looks to find the state-of-the-art.
That the serial, which presents itself more as an anthology than as
a journal, has traditionally allowed space for lengthier studies,
has tended only to add to its prestige; it is as if OSAP thus
declares that, since it allows as much space as the merits of the
subject require, it can be more entirely devoted to the best and
most serious scholarship.' Michael Pakaluk, Bryn Mawr Classical
Review
Confronting the scientific revolution's dismissal of Aristotle's
physics and epistemology, Nathan R. Colaner revives this
foundational philosopher's work to expose within it the
underpinnings of modern philosophers' most common intuitions about
knowledge. After Aristotle's picture of reality had been judged
obsolete by the physics of the scientific revolution, modern
Western epistemologists fumbled along with doctrines that had
little to do with everyday life. These included Descartes' notion
of the evil genius, Hume's claim that we can't know anything that
we are not presently observing, and Kant's rescue of knowledge in
the context of idealism. In Aristotle on Knowledge of Nature and
Modern Skepticism, Colaner articulates a notion of knowledge that
is characteristically Aristotelian without being dependent on his
metaphysics. Simultaneously, Colaner places Aristotle in dialogue
with modern thinkers to create a bridge between classical and
modern philosophy and reinstate Aristotle's prominence in the
discipline of epistemology.
|
You may like...
Republic
Plato
Paperback
R95
R76
Discovery Miles 760
|