|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
Hegel and Plato are united as political theorists by the
convergence of their philosophical aspirations. But their political
writings manifest the general disparities involved in their
particular ways of seeking to fulfil these aspirations. Professor
Browning compares the political thought of Plato and Hegel by
locating their political theorizing within the context of their
divergent modes of philosophizing.
Edward Urwick's original work draws upon Plato's best known work,
the Republic, to provide a new interpretation of Plato's teaching
based upon Indian religious thought. Most scholars have sought to
interpret the Republic from the standpoint of politics, ethics, and
metaphysics and indeed the accepted title of the dialogue -
Concerning a Polity or Republic - would seem to legitimate this.
Even the alternative title for the work - Concerning Justice -
seems to justify such an approach. Yet the original Greek work,
Dikaiosune, had a fuller meaning: righteousness. The author
believes this gives a truer clue to the meaning of the dialogue. It
is a discussion of righteousness in all its forms, from the just
dealing of the law-abiding citizen to the spirit of holiness in the
saint.
This volume provides a comprehensive, learned and lively
presentation of the whole range of Plato's thought but with a
particular emphasis upon how Plato developed his metaphysics with a
view to supporting his deepest educational convictions. The author
explores the relation of Plato's metaphysics to the
epistemological, ethical and political aspects of Plato's theory of
education and shows how Plato's basic positions bear directly on
the most fundamental questions faced by contemporary education.
Did Plato abandon, or sharply modify, the Theory of Forms in later
life? In the Phaedo, Symposium, and Republic it is generally agreed
that Plato held that universals exist. But in Parmenides, he
subjected that theory to criticism. If the criticism were valid,
and Plato knew so, then the Parmenides marks a turning point in his
thought. If, however, Plato became aware that there are radical
differences in the logical behaviour of concepts, and the later
dialogues are a record of his attempt to analyse those differences,
then Plato's thought can be said to have moved in a new and vitally
important direction after the Parmenides. Studies in Plato's
Metaphysics brings together twenty essays by leading philosophers
from the UK and the USA reflecting upon this important issue and
upon the questions arising from it.
R. S. Bluck's engaging volume provides an accessible introduction
to the thought of Plato. In the first part of the book the author
provides an account of the life of the philosopher, from Plato's
early years, through to the Academy, the first visit to Dionysius
and the third visit to Syracuse, and finishing with an account of
his final years. In the second part contains a discussion of the
main purpose and points of interest of each of Plato's works. There
is a chapter on Plato's central doctrine, the Theory of Ideas, and
a translation of Plato's Seventh Letter, which not only provides
valuable additional material for the study of Plato's thought but
also contains a vivid account of many incidents in Plato's life.
This valuable work of reference provides a comprehensive
bibliography on all scholarly work that was published on Plato and
Socrates during the years 1958-73. It thus forms an important
addition to Harold Cherniss's bibliography, which covered the years
1950-7. The author has sought to include all materials primarily
concerned with Socrates and Plato, together with other works which
make a contribution to our understanding of the two philosophers.
The bibliography is arranged by topic and there are
cross-references at the end of each section. The works in each
category are arranged chronologically and then alphabetically (by
author) within each year. An effort has been made to distinguish
when a book has had more than one edition and when an article has
been reprinted. Additionally the author has listed reviews of books
and dissertations as these have come to his attention.
Studies of Plato's metaphysics have tended to emphasise either the
radical change between the early Theory of Forms and the late
doctrines of the Timaeus and the Sophist, or to insist on a unity
of approach that is unchanged throughout Plato's career. The author
lays out an alternative approach. Focussing on two metaphysical
doctrines of central importance to Plato's thought - the Theory of
Forms and the doctrine of Being and Becoming - he suggests a
continuous progress can be traced through Plato's works. He
presents his argument through an examination of the metaphysical
sections of six of the dialogues: the Euthyphro, Phaedo, Republic,
Parmenides, Timaeus, and Sophist.
This book provides an introduction to Plato's work that gives a
clear statement of what Plato has to say about the problems of
thought and life. In particular, it tells the reader just what
Plato says, and makes no attempt to force a system on the Platonic
text or to trim Plato's works to suit contemporary philosophical
tastes. The author also gives an account that has historical
fidelity - we cannot really understand the Republic or the Gorgias
if we forget that the Athens of the conversations is meant to be
the Athens of Nicias or Cleon, not the very different Athens of
Plato's own manhood. To understand Plato's thought we must see it
in the right historical perspective.
Plato's Timaeus was his only cosmological dialogue and for almost
thirteen hundred years it provided the basis in the West for
educated people's general view of the natural world. The author
provides a translation of this important work, together with the
Critias - the source of the legendary tale of Atlantis. He has
taken particular care to provide an accurate rendering of Plato's
words and to avoid putting his own or any other interpretation on
the works.
This book provides a clear and informed account of aesthetic and
callistic concepts as they occur in the works of Plato and
Aristotle. The author illustrates their ideas on art and beauty by
close reference to their texts and finds a profound similarity
which unites them, revealing many of their differences to be
complementary aspects of an essentially similar viewpoint. He also
shows how Greek notions of art and beauty are not merely primitive
steps in the advance to modern ideas but have a direct relevance to
modern critical controversies.
This book helps understand Plato's writings by describing the
circumstances in which they were produced. The author begins with
an account of Plato's life and development and a brief analysis of
some of the more difficult points arising from the criticism of
Plato's writings. The remainder of the work considers the total
setting - political, literary and philosophical - in which Plato's
writings were produced. There are extensive appendices on the
Platonic Epistles, Aristotle and the Theory of Ideas, and on the
post-Aristotelian tradition. The result is both a lucid account of
Plato himself and a comprehensive view of culture in fifth century
Greece.
Ian Crombie's impressive volumes provide a comprehensive
interpretation of Plato's doctrines. Volume 1 contains topics of
more general interest and is mainly concerned with what Plato has
to say in the fields of moral philosophy, political philosophy, the
philosophy of mind and the philosophy of religion.
Ian Crombie's impressive volumes provide a comprehensive
interpretation of Plato's doctrines. Volume 2 deals with more
technical philosophical topics, including the theory of knowledge,
philosophy of nature, and the methodology of science and
philosophy. Each volume is self-contained.
In Plato's Theaetetus, Socrates is portrayed as a midwife to the
intellect, a metaphor for his task as a dialectician as he seeks to
help give birth to wisdom. Thus it is that the author refers to
Plato as the midwife's apprentice. This volume represents an
attempt to provide a more manageable account of the author's two
volume magnum opus, An Examination of Plato's Doctrines. An
accessible and lucid introduction to Plato's ideas is provided
which nonetheless challenges traditional interpretations. In
particular the author is concerned to offer an interpretation of
the significance of what Plato said. The chapters are arranged by
topic, for ease of comprehension.
Plato was born around 2,500 years ago. He lived in a small
city-state in Greece and busied himself with the problems of his
fellow Greeks, a people living in scattered cities around the
Mediterranean and the Black Sea. In all he tried to do for the
Greeks he failed. Why, then, should people in the modern world
bother to read what he had to say? Does it make sense to go to a
Greek thinker for advice on the problems of an age so different
from his own? To anyone who has questioned the relevance of Plato
to the modern world Richard Crossman's lively book provides a
brilliant reply. The problems facing Plato's world bear striking
parallels to ours today, the author maintains, so who better to
turn to than Plato, the most objective and most ruthless observer
of the failures of Greek society. Crossman's engaging text provides
both an informed introduction to Greek ideas and an original and
controversial view of Plato himself.
Translated by Henrik Rosenmeier, A History of Ancient Philosophy
charts the origins and development of ancient philosophical
thought. For easy reference, the book is divided chronologically
into six main parts. The sections are further divided into
philosophers and philosophical movements: *Pre-Socratic Philosophy,
including mythology, the Pythagoreans and Parmenides *The Great
Century of Athens, including the Sophists and Socrates *Plato,
including The Republic, The Symposium and The Timaeus *Aristotle,
including The Physics, The Metaphysics and The Poetics *Hellenistic
Philosophy, including the Sceptics, the Stoics, the Epicureans and
Cicero *Late Antiquity, including Neoplatonism, Origen and St
Augustine. This comprehensive and meticulously documented book is
structured to make ancient philosophical thought and ancient
thinkers accessible. It contains: *full references to primary
sources *detailed interpretations of key philosophical passages,
including surveys of previous philosophical readings *an overview
of the development of ancient philosophical thought *discussions of
the relationships between philosophers and their ideas *analyses of
key philosophical concepts and ideologies including ontology,
epistemology, logic, semantics, moral and political philosophy,
theology and aesthetics *explanations of Greek philosophical
terminology.
There are many fallacious arguments in the dialogues of Plato. The
author argues that Plato was fully conscious of the fallacious
character of at least an important number of these arguments and
that he sometimes made deliberate use of fallacy as an indirect
means of setting forth certain of his fundamental philosophical
views. Plato introduces them, the author maintains, for the purpose
of working out their implications. Plato is thus able to expose
them for what they are, to clear away possible lines of attack upon
his own position, and even to show that when the proper correction
is applied his own views receive support.
This book explores the life-history of the individual within the
context of Plato's social thought. The author examines Plato's
treatment of the principal crises in an individual life - birth,
educational selection, sex, the individual's contract with society,
old age, death, and life after death - and provides an
unprecedented analysis of Plato's theory of genetics as it appears
in the Timaeus. Comparisons are made with contemporary developments
in anthropology, sociology, and comparative myth but without losing
sight of the fact that Plato, whilst having much to say to the
modern world, was not a modern.
In fourth-century Greece (BCE), the debate over the nature of
philosophy generated a novel claim: that the highest form of wisdom
is theoria, the rational 'vision' of metaphysical truths (the
'spectator theory of knowledge'). This 2004 book offers an original
analysis of the construction of 'theoretical' philosophy in
fourth-century Greece. In the effort to conceptualise and
legitimise theoretical philosophy, the philosophers turned to a
venerable cultural practice: theoria (state pilgrimage). In this
practice, an individual journeyed abroad as an official witness of
sacralized spectacles. This book examines the philosophic
appropriation and transformation of theoria, and analyses the
competing conceptions of theoretical wisdom in fourth-century
philosophy. By tracing the link between traditional and philosophic
theoria, this book locates the creation of theoretical philosophy
in its historical context, analysing theoria as a cultural and an
intellectual practice. It develops a new, interdisciplinary
approach, drawing on philosophy, history and literary studies.
An engaging new translation of a timeless masterpiece about coping
with the death of a loved one In 45 BCE, the Roman statesman Cicero
fell to pieces when his beloved daughter, Tullia, died from
complications of childbirth. But from the depths of despair, Cicero
fought his way back. In an effort to cope with his loss, he wrote a
consolation speech-not for others, as had always been done, but for
himself. And it worked. Cicero's Consolation was something new in
literature, equal parts philosophy and motivational speech. Drawing
on the full range of Greek philosophy and Roman history, Cicero
convinced himself that death and loss are part of life, and that if
others have survived them, we can, too; resilience, endurance, and
fortitude are the way forward. Lost in antiquity, Cicero's
Consolation was recreated in the Renaissance from hints in Cicero's
other writings and the Greek and Latin consolatory tradition. The
resulting masterpiece-translated here for the first time in 250
years-is infused throughout with Cicero's thought and spirit.
Complete with the original Latin on facing pages and an inviting
introduction, Michael Fontaine's engaging translation makes this
searching exploration of grief available to readers once again.
The history of Pythagoreanism is littered with different and
incompatible interpretations, to the point that Kahn (1974)
suggested that, instead of another thesis on Pythagoreanism, it
would be preferable to assess traditions with the aim of producing
a good historiographical presentation. This almost fourty-year-old
observation by Kahn, directs the author of this book towards a
fundamentally historiographical rather than philological brand of
work, that is, one neither exclusively devoted to the exegesis of
sources such as Philolaus, Archytas or even of one of the
Hellenistic Lives nor even to the theoretical approach of one of
the themes that received specific contributions from
Pythagoreanism, such as mathematics, cosmology, politics or
theories of the soul. Instead, this monograph sets out to
reconstruct the way in which the tradition established
Pythagoreanism's image, facing one of the central problems that
characterizes Pythagoreanism more than other ancient philosophical
movements: the drastically shifting terrain of the criticism of the
sources. The goal of this historiographical approach is to embrace
Pythagoreanism in its entirety, through - and not in spite of - its
complex articulation across more than a millennium.
 |
On Aristotle "Physics 5"
(Hardcover)
Of Cilicia Simplicius; Volume editing by Peter Lautner; Aristotle; Translated by J.O. Urmson
|
R4,239
Discovery Miles 42 390
|
Ships in 12 - 19 working days
|
|
In the sixth century AD Simplicius produced detailed commentaries
on several of the works of Aristotle, which help in our
understanding of the "Physics", and of its interpretation in the
ancient world. This is Urmson's translation of Simplicius'
commentaries on "Physics 5" in which Aristotle lays down some of
the principles of his dynamics and theory of change. What does not
count as a change: change of relation?; the flux of time? There is
no change of change, yet acceleration is recognized. Aristotle
defines "continuous", "contact" and "next", and uses these
definitions in discussing when we can claim that the same change or
event is still going on.
"Essential reading for all students of ancient philosophy -- and a
special provocation to anyone tempted to write as if 'Classical'
thought is exhausted by Plato and his school." -- Geore
Boys-Stones, Professor of Ancient Philosophy, Durham University
"Compulsive reading for anyone who hopes to grasp the wide range of
philosophical opinions that vied for attention in the two golden
centuries that followed the death of Socrates." -- Denis O'Brien,
former Directeur de recherche, Centre Nationale de Recherche
Scientifique, Paris "An important contribution to the continuing
rehabilitation of Hellenistic philosophy." -- C. J. Rowe, Emeritus
Professor of Greek, Durham University The Cyrenaic school of
philosophy (named after its founder Aristippus' native city of
Cyrene in North Africa) flourished in the fifth and fourth
centuries BCE. This book begins by introducing the main figures of
the Cyrenaic school beginning with Aristippus and setting them in
their historical context. Once the reader is familiar with those
figures and with the genealogy of the school, the book offers an
overview of ancient and modern interpretations of the Cyrenaics,
providing readers with alternative accounts of the doctrines they
endorsed and of the role they played in the context of ancient
thought. Finally, the book offers a reconstruction of Cyrenaic
philosophy and shows how the ethical side of their speculation
connected with the epistemology and ontology they endorsed and
that, as a result, the Cyrenaics were able to offer a quite
sophisticated philosophy. Indeed, Zilioli demonstrates that they
represented, in ancient philosophy, an important and original
metaphysical position and alternative to the kind of realism
endorsed by Plato and Aristotle.
|
You may like...
Republic
Plato
Paperback
R95
R85
Discovery Miles 850
|