|
Books > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Ethics & moral philosophy
Jonas Olson presents a critical survey of moral error theory, the
view that there are no moral facts and so all moral claims are
false. In Part I (History), he explores the historical context of
the debate, and discusses the moral error theories of David Hume
and of some more or less influential twentieth century
philosophers, including Axel Hagerstroem, Bertrand Russell, Ludwig
Wittgenstein, and Richard Robinson. He argues that the early cases
for moral error theory are suggestive but that they would have been
stronger had they included something like J. L. Mackie's arguments
that moral properties and facts are metaphysically queer. Part II
(Critique) focuses on these arguments. Olson identifies four
queerness arguments, concerning supervenience, knowledge,
motivation, and irreducible normativity, and goes on to establish
that while the first three are not compelling, the fourth has
considerable force, especially when combined with debunking
explanations of why we tend to believe that there are moral
properties and facts when in fact there are none. One conclusion of
Part II is that a plausible error theory takes the form of an error
theory about irreducible normativity. In Part III (Defence), Olson
considers challenges according to which that kind of error theory
has problematic ramifications regarding hypothetical reasons,
epistemic reasons, and deliberation. He ends his discussion with a
consideration of the implications of moral error theory for
ordinary moral thought and talk, and for normative theorizing.
Reading Augustine presents concise, personal readings of St.
Augustine of Hippo from leading philosophers and religion scholars.
Augustine of Hippo knew that this fallen world is a place of
sadness and suffering. In such a world, he determined that
compassion is the most suitable and virtuous response. Its
transformative powers could be accessed through the mind and its
memories, through the healing of the Incarnation, and through the
discernment of Christians who are forced to navigate through a
corrupt and deceptive world. Susan Wessel considers Augustine's
theology of compassion by examining his personal experience of loss
and his reflections concerning individual and corporate suffering
in the context of the human condition and salvation.
This book addresses how Plato, Kant, and Iris Murdoch (each in
different ways) view the connection aesthetic experience has to
morality. While offering an examination of Iris Murdoch's
philosophy, it analyses deeply the suggestive links (as well as
essential distinctions) between Plato's and Kant's philosophies.
Meredith Trexler Drees considers not only Iris Murdoch's concept of
unselfing, but also its relationship with Kant's view of Achtung
and Plato's view of Eros. In addition, Trexler Drees suggests an
extended, and partially amended, version of Murdoch's view, arguing
that it is more compatible with a religious way of life than
Murdoch herself realized. This leads to an expansion of the overall
argument to include Kant's affirmation of religion as an area of
life that can be improved through Plato's and Murdoch's vision of
how being good and being beautiful can be part of the same
life-task.
Mary Midgley is one of the most influential moral philosophers of
the twentieth century. Over the last 40 years, Midgley's writings
on such central yet controversial topics as human nature, morality,
science, animals, the environment, religion, and gender have shaped
the landscape of contemporary philosophy. She is celebrated for the
complexity, nuance, and sensibility with which she approaches some
of the most challenging issues in philosophy without falling into
the pitfalls of close-minded extremism. In turn, Midgley's
sophisticated treatment of the interconnected and often muddled
issues related to human nature has drawn interest from outside the
philosophical world, stretching from scientists, artists,
theologians, anthropologists, and journalists to the public more
broadly. Mary Midgley: An Introduction systematically introduces
readers to Midgley's collected thought on the most central and
influential areas of her corpus. Through clear and lively
engagement with Midgley's work, this volume offers readers
accessible explanation, interpretation, and analysis of the
concepts and perspectives for which she is best known, most notably
her integrated understanding of human nature, her opposition to
reductionism and scientism, and her influential conception of our
relationship to animals and the wider world. These insights,
supplemented by excerpts from original interviews with Midgley
herself, provide readers of all backgrounds with an informed
understanding and appreciation of Mary Midgley and the
philosophical problems to which she has devoted her life's work.
Despite the nuclear accident at the Fukushima Daiichi plant in
Japan, a growing number of countries are interested in expanding or
introducing nuclear energy. However, nuclear energy production and
nuclear waste disposal give rise to pressing ethical questions that
society needs to face. This book takes up this challenge with
essays by an international team of scholars focusing on the key
issues of risk, justice, and democracy. The essays consider a range
of ethical issues, including radiological protection, the influence
of gender in the acceptability of nuclear risk, and environmental,
international, and intergenerational justice in the context of
nuclear energy. They also address the question of when, and under
which conditions, nuclear energy should play a role in the world's
future supply of electricity, looking at both developing and
industrialized countries. The book will interest readers in ethics
and political philosophy, social and political sciences, nuclear
engineering, and policy studies.
In this important and original interdisciplinary work, well-known
environmental philosopher Eric Katz explores technology's role in
dominating both nature and humanity. He argues that technology
dominates, and hence destroys, the natural world; it dominates, and
hence destroys, critical aspects of human life and society.
Technology causes an estrangement from nature, and thus a loss of
meaning in human life. As a result, humans lose the power to make
moral and social choices; they lose the power to control their
lives. Katz's argument innovatively connects two distinct areas of
thought: the fundamental goal of the Holocaust, including Nazi
environmental policy, to heal the degenerate elements of society;
and the plan to heal degraded natural systems that informs the
contemporary environmental policy of 'ecological restoration'. In
both arenas of 'healing,' Katz argues that technological forces
drive action, while domination emerges as the prevailing ideology.
Katz's work is a plea for the development of a technology that does
not dominate and destroy but instead promotes autonomy and
freedom.Anne Frank, a victim of Nazi ideology and action, saw the
titular tree behind her secret annex as a symbol of freedom and
moral goodness. In Katz's argument, the tree represents a free and
autonomous nature, resistant to human control and domination. Anne
Frank's Tree is rooted in an empirical approach to philosophy,
seating complex ethical ideas in an accessible and powerful
narrative of historical fact and deeply personal lived experience.
As political discourse had been saturated with the ideas of
"post-truth", "fake news", "epistemic bubbles", and "truth decay",
it was no surprise that in 2017 The New Scientist declared:
"Philosophers of knowledge, your time has come." Political
epistemology has old roots, but is now one of the most rapidly
growing and important areas of philosophy. The Routledge Handbook
of Political Epistemology is an outstanding reference source to
this exciting field, and the first collection of its kind.
Comprising 41 chapters by an international team of contributors, it
is divided into seven parts: Politics and truth: historical and
contemporary perspectives Political disagreement and polarization
Fake news, propaganda, and misinformation Ignorance and
irrationality in politics Epistemic virtues and vices in politics
Democracy and epistemology Trust, expertise, and doubt. Within
these sections crucial issues and debates are examined, including:
post-truth, disagreement and relativism, epistemic networks, fake
news, echo chambers, propaganda, ignorance, irrationality,
political polarization, virtues and vices in public debate,
epistocracy, expertise, misinformation, trust, and digital
democracy, as well as the views of Plato, Aristotle, Mozi, medieval
Islamic philosophers, Mill, Arendt, and Rawls on truth and
politics. The Routledge Handbook of Political Epistemology is
essential reading for those studying political philosophy, applied
and social epistemology, and politics. It is also a valuable
resource for those in related disciplines such as international
relations, law, political psychology, political science,
communication studies, and journalism.
This volume brings together fourteen mostly previously published
articles by the prominent Nietzsche scholar Maudemarie Clark.
Clark's previous two books on Nietzsche focused on his views on
truth, metaphysics, and knowledge, but she has published a great
deal on Nietzsche's views on ethics and politics in article form.
Putting those articles - many of which appeared in obscure venues -
together in book form will allow readers to see more easily how her
views fit together as a whole, exhibit important developments of
her ideas, and highlight Clark's distinctive voice in Nietzsche
studies. Clark provides an introduction tying her themes together
and placing them in their broader context.
This book provides cross-cultural ethical exploration of sex robots
and their social impact. What are the implications of sex robots
and related technological innovations for society and culture? How
should we evaluate the significance of sexual relations with robots
that look like women, men or children? Critics argue that sex
robots present a clear risk to real persons and a social
degradation that will increase sexual violence, objectify women,
encourage pedophilia, reinforce negative body images, increase
forms of sexual dysfunction, and pass on sexually transmitted
disease. Proponents judge robotic sexual companionship as just
another step in the exploration of human desire. They see sex
robots, and similar technology, such as virtual reality
pornography, as providing autonomy affirming companionship for the
lonely and a relatively harmless outlet for sexual fantasies that
avoids the use of human prostitutes and thus reduces sexual
victimization. Some appreciate sex robots as a social evil, others
as a positive good, and still others as a harmless pastime. How we
come to terms with such conceptual and moral concerns will have
significant implications for society and the future of human
relations. This book is of great interest to researchers in
bioethics, human sexual behavior, AI ethics, and philosophy of sex.
Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics is an annual forum for new work
in normative ethical theory. Leading philosophers present original
contributions to our understanding of a wide range of moral issues
and positions, from analysis of competing approaches to normative
ethics (including moral realism, constructivism, and expressivism)
to questions of how we should act and live well. OSNE will be an
essential resource for scholars and students working in moral
philosophy.
In this comprehensive assessment of Kant's metaethics, Frederick
Rauscher shows that Kant is a moral idealist rather than a moral
realist and argues that Kant's ethics does not require metaphysical
commitments that go beyond nature. Rauscher frames the argument in
the context of Kant's non-naturalistic philosophical method and the
character of practical reason as action-oriented. Reason operates
entirely within nature, and apparently non-natural claims - God,
free choice, and value - are shown to be heuristic and to reflect
reason's ordering of nature. The book shows how Kant hesitates
between a transcendental moral idealism with an empirical moral
realism and a complete moral idealism. Examining every aspect of
Kant's ethics, from the categorical imperative to freedom and
value, this volume argues that Kant's focus on human moral agency
explains morality as a part of nature. It will appeal to academic
researchers and advanced students of Kant, German idealism and
intellectual history.
The problem of free will arises from ordinary, commonsense
reflection. Shaun Nichols examines these ordinary attitudes from a
naturalistic perspective. He offers a psychological account of the
origins of the problem of free will. According to his account the
problem arises because of two naturally emerging ways of thinking
about ourselves and the world, one of which makes determinism
plausible while the other makes determinism implausible. Although
contemporary cognitive science does not settle whether choices are
determined, Nichols argues that our belief in indeterminist choice
is grounded in faulty inference and should be regarded as
unjustified. However, even if our belief in indeterminist choice is
false, it's a further substantive question whether that means that
free will doesn't exist. Nichols argues that, because of the
flexibility of reference, there is no single answer to whether free
will exists. In some contexts, it will be true to say 'free will
exists'; in other contexts, it will be false to say that. With this
substantive background in place, Bound promotes a pragmatic
approach to prescriptive issues. In some contexts, the prevailing
practical considerations suggest that we should deny the existence
of free will and moral responsibility; in other contexts the
practical considerations suggest that we should affirm free will
and moral responsibility. This allows for the possibility that in
some contexts, it is morally apt to exact retributive punishment;
in other contexts, it can be apt to take up the exonerating
attitude of hard incompatibilism.
|
|