|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present > General
Hegel's Transcendental Ontology argues that Hegel presents the
kernel of his metaphysics, in the Doctrine of the Concept, the
final part of his Science of Logic. The Concept has three moments:
universality (a process through which conceptual content of
empirical determinations is formed), particularity (a holistic
system of inferentially interrelated determinations comprising the
totality of conceptual content), and individuality (the totality of
objects conditioned by the shared system of empirical
determinations that comprise the particular moment). The book
details these three moments as well as the specific schema of their
relation to one another. One of its aims is to offer a resolution
to the recent debate between Kantian and traditional
metaphysics-based readings of Hegel that has been dominating Hegel
scholarship. The author claims that Hegel walked a narrow path
between Scylla, of offering just another version of the traditional
kind of metaphysics and Charybdis of abstaining from making any
substantive claims about the nature of reality and focusing
exclusively on the analysis of the faculty of understanding. Hegel
left behind traditional approaches to the problems of metaphysics
and, through a radical reformulation of the relationship between
thought and being, proposed a new kind of metaphysics that is
Kantian through and through.
Der Widerspruch, den Kant in der Kritik der praktischen Vernunft
unter den Titeln "Dialektik" und "Antinomie der praktischen
Vernunft" beschreibt, wurde bisher sehr unterschiedlich verstanden.
Das Buch dokumentiert zum ersten Mal die enorme Vielfalt der
divergierenden Deutungen und bietet eine textorientierte Analyse
der Antinomie und ihrer Aufloesung, die in vielen Aspekten heute
weithin akzeptierten Auslegungen und Bewertungen widerspricht. Die
Arbeit zeigt, dass die Antinomie erst moeglich wurde, nachdem Kant
noch nach 1781 wichtige Korrekturen an den Prinzipien der
sittlichen Verpflichtung und Triebfeder vorgenommen hatte. Sie
macht deutlich, dass die Antinomie der praktischen Vernunft sich in
ihrer Struktur und Funktion charakteristisch von den Antinomien in
der Kritik der reinen Vernunft unterscheidet.
GWF Hegel has long been considered one of the most influential and
controversial thinkers of the nineteenth century, and his work
continues to provoke debate in contemporary philosophy. This new
book provides readers with an accessible introduction to Hegel's
thought, offering a lucid and highly readable account of his
"Phenomenology of Spirit," "Science of Logic," "Philosophy of
Nature," "Philosophy of History," and "Philosophy of Right." It
provides a cogent and careful analysis of Hegel's main arguments,
considers critical responses, evaluates competing interpretations,
and assesses the legacy of Hegel's work for philosophy in the
present day.In a comprehensive discussion of the major works, J.M
Fritzman considers crucial questions of authorial intent raised by
the "Phenomenology of Spirit," and discusses Hegel's conceptions of
necessity and of philosophical method. In his presentation of
Hegel's "Logic," Fritzman evaluates the claim that logic has no
presuppositions and examines whether this endorses a
foundationalist or coherentist epistemology. Fritzman goes on to
scrutinize Hegel's claims that history represents the progressive
realization of human freedom, and details how Hegel believes that
this is also expressed in art and religion. This book serves as
both an excellent introduction to Hegel's wide-ranging philosophy
for students, as well as an innovative critique which will
contribute to ongoing debates in the field.
Schellings "Philosophie der Mythologie" ist Teil seiner positiven
Philosophie, mit der er Hegel zu uberwinden sucht. Sein neuer
Theorietyp weist sich dadurch aus, dass er Religion nicht immer
schon vom Logos aus denkt. Damit kritisiert er insbesondere Hegels
Allegorese des Mythos, die in diesem nur Logos in der Form der
Unmittelbarkeit zu erkennen vermag. Daraus folgen wichtige
Modifikationen auf dem Gebiet der Metaphysik. Gegen Hegels
Vollendung der Autonomie eines absoluten Subjekts geht Schelling
auf die antike Ontonomie zuruck, die er ihrerseits aus der
Theonomie des mythologischen Bewusstseins herleitet. Die Arbeit
untersucht Schellings Antwort auf die Fragen nach dem Sinn von
Sein, nach dem Wesen des Menschen sowie nach der Stellung des
Selbstbewusstseins in der Geschichte.
The Early Romantics met resistance from artists and academics alike
in part because they defied the conventional wisdom that philosophy
and the arts must be kept separate. Indeed, as the literary
component of Romanticism has been studied and celebrated in recent
years, its philosophical aspect has receded from view. This book,
by one of the most respected scholars of the Romantic era, offers
an explanation of Romanticism that not only restores but enhances
understanding of the movement's origins, development, aims, and
accomplishments--and of its continuing relevance.
Poetry is in fact the general ideal of the Romantics, Frederick
Beiser tells us, but only if poetry is understood not just narrowly
as poems but more broadly as things made by humans. Seen in this
way, poetry becomes a revolutionary ideal that demanded--and still
demands--that we transform not only literature and criticism but
all the arts and sciences, that we break down the barriers between
art and life, so that the world itself becomes "romanticized."
Romanticism, in the view Beiser opens to us, does not conform to
the contemporary division of labor in our universities and
colleges; it requires a multifaceted approach of just the sort
outlined in this book.
Vittorio Morfino draws out the implications of the dynamic
Spinoza-Machiavelli encounter by focusing on the concepts of
causality, temporality and politics. This allows him to think
through the relationship between ontology and politics, leading to
an understanding of history as a complex and plural interweaving of
different rhythms.
First published in 1818, The World as Will and Representation
contains Schopenhauer's entire philosophy, ranging through
epistemology, metaphysics, philosophy of mind and action,
aesthetics and philosophy of art, to ethics, the meaning of life
and the philosophy of religion, in an attempt to account for the
world in all its significant aspects. It gives a unique and
influential account of what is and is not of value in existence,
the striving and pain of the human condition and the possibility of
deliverance from it. This new translation of the first volume of
what later became a two-volume work reflects the eloquence and
power of Schopenhauer's prose and renders philosophical terms
accurately and consistently. It offers an introduction, glossary of
names and bibliography, and succinct editorial notes, including
notes on the revisions of the text which Schopenhauer made in 1844
and 1859.
Many philosophers and scientists over the course of history have
held that the world is alive. It has a soul, which governs it and
binds it together. This suggestion, once so wide-spread, may strike
many of us today as strange and antiquated-in fact, there are few
other concepts that, on their face, so capture the sheer distance
between us and our philosophical inheritance. But the idea of a
world soul has held so strong a grip upon philosophers'
imaginations for over 2,000 years, that it continues to underpin
and even structure how we conceive of time and space. The concept
of the world soul is difficult to understand in large part because
over the course of history it has been invoked to very different
ends and within the frameworks of very different ontologies and
philosophical systems, with varying concepts of the world soul
emerging as a result. This volume brings together eleven chapters
by leading philosophers in their respective fields that
collectively explore the various ways in which this concept has
been understood and employed, covering the following philosophical
areas: Platonism, Stoicism, Medieval, Indian or Vedantic, Kabbalah,
Renaissance, Early Modern, German Romanticism, German Idealism,
American Transcendentalism, and contemporary quantum mechanics and
panpsychism theories. In addition, short reflections illuminate the
impact the concept of the world soul has had on a small selection
of areas outside of philosophy, such as harmony, the biological
concept of spontaneous generation, Henry Purcell, psychoanalysis,
and Gaia theories.
Philosophy enquires into the relationship between being and
thought, existence and determination. In his early works, Kant
approaches this basic problem of philosophy as determined by
conventional rationalist metaphysics. Starting from the realisation
that existence is not the determination, is not the predicate of an
object, but its absolute position, Kant intervenes in the
ontological and theological discussion of his age and develops his
own philosophical position from the differentiation between real
and philosophical reasons. The author demonstrates Kant's struggle
with this basic problem from his pre-critical writings up to his
Critiques. In an excursus he deals with the posthumous works and
with the return of the approach in Schelling's late philosophy and
its turn to an unpredicated being.
Defends Reid's Common Sense philosophy against the claim that
perception does not allow us to experience the physical world With
a new reading of Thomas Reid on primary and secondary qualities,
Christopher A. Shrock illuminates the Common Sense theory of
perception. Shrock follow's Reid's lead in defending common sense
philosophy against the problem of secondary qualities, which claims
that our perceptions are only experiences in our brains, and don't
let us know about the world around us. At the same time, Schrock
maintains a healthy optimism about science and reason.
 |
Leaves of Grass
(Hardcover)
Walt Whitman; Introduction by Ken Mondschein
|
R645
R577
Discovery Miles 5 770
Save R68 (11%)
|
Ships in 9 - 17 working days
|
|
 |
The Joyous Science
(Paperback)
Friedrich Nietzsche; Translated by R. Kevin Hill; Edited by R. Kevin Hill
|
R338
R307
Discovery Miles 3 070
Save R31 (9%)
|
Ships in 9 - 17 working days
|
|
The Joyous Science is a liberating voyage of discovery as
Nietzsche's realization that 'God is dead' and his critique of
morality, the arts and modernity give way to an exhilarating
doctrine of self-emancipation and the concept of eternal
recurrence. Here is Nietzsche at his most personal and affirmative;
in his words, this is a book of 'exuberance, restlessness,
contrariety and April showers'. With its unique voice and style,
its playful combination of poetry and prose, and its invigorating
quest for self-emancipation, The Joyous Science is a literary tour
de force and quite possibly Nietzsche's best book.
Featuring scholars at the forefront of contemporary political
theology and the study of German Idealism, Nothing Absolute
explores the intersection of these two flourishing fields. Against
traditional approaches that view German Idealism as a secularizing
movement, this volume revisits it as the first fundamentally
philosophical articulation of the political-theological problematic
in the aftermath of the Enlightenment and the advent of secularity.
Nothing Absolute reclaims German Idealism as a
political-theological trajectory. Across the volume's
contributions, German thought from Kant to Marx emerges as crucial
for the genealogy of political theology and for the ongoing
reassessment of modernity and the secular. By investigating anew
such concepts as immanence, utopia, sovereignty, theodicy, the
Earth, and the world, as well as the concept of political theology
itself, this volume not only rethinks German Idealism and its
aftermath from a political-theological perspective but also
demonstrates what can be done with (or against) German Idealism
using the conceptual resources of political theology today.
Contributors: Joseph Albernaz, Daniel Colucciello Barber, Agata
Bielik-Robson, Kirill Chepurin, S. D. Chrostowska, Saitya Brata
Das, Alex Dubilet, Vincent Lloyd, Thomas Lynch, James Martel,
Steven Shakespeare, Oxana Timofeeva, Daniel Whistler
Brian Leiter defends a set of radical ideas from Nietzsche: there
is no objectively true morality, there is no free will, no one is
ever morally responsible, and our conscious thoughts and reasoning
play almost no significant role in our actions and how our lives
unfold. He presents a new interpretation of main themes of
Nietzsche's moral psychology, including his anti-realism about
value (including epistemic value), his account of moral judgment
and its relationship to the emotions, his conception of the will
and agency, his scepticism about free will and moral
responsibility, his epiphenomenalism about certain kinds of
conscious mental states, and his views about the heritability of
psychological traits. In combining exegesis with argument, Leiter
engages the views of philosophers like Harry Frankfurt, T. M.
Scanlon, and Gary Watson, and psychologists including Daniel
Wegner, Benjamin Libet, and Stanley Milgram. Nietzsche emerges not
simply as a museum piece from the history of ideas, but as a
philosopher and psychologist who exceeds David Hume for insight
into human nature and the human mind, repeatedly anticipates later
developments in empirical psychology, and continues to offer
sophisticated and unsettling challenges to much conventional wisdom
in both philosophy and psychology.
What do we know about Hegel? What do we know about Marx? What do we
know about democracy and totalitarianism? Communism and
psychoanalysis? What do we know that isn't a platitude that we've
heard a thousand times - or a self-satisfied certainty? Through his
brilliant reading of Hegel, Slavoj Zizek - one of the most
provocative and widely-read thinkers of our time - upends our
traditional understanding, dynamites every cliche and undermines
every conviction in order to clear the ground for new ways of
answering these questions. When Lacan described Hegel as the most
sublime hysteric , he was referring to the way that the hysteric
asks questions because he experiences his own desire as if it were
the Other's desire. In the dialectical process, the question asked
of the Other is resolved through a reflexive turn in which the
question begins to function as its own answer. We had made Hegel
into the theorist of abstraction and reaction, but by reading Hegel
with Lacan, Zizek unveils a Hegel of the concrete and of revolution
- his own, and the one to come. This early and dazzlingly original
work by Zizek offers a unique insight into the ideas which have
since become hallmarks of his mature thought. It will be of great
interest to anyone interested in critical theory, philosophy and
contemporary social thought.
In Everything in Its Right Place, Joseph Almog develops the
unitarian and universalist metaphysics of Spinoza. Spinoza's ground
zero thesis is that "Nature is one and all. " Everything (including
God, mathematics, morals, our own thoughts) finds its place within
Spinoza's (capital N) Nature. It is the place that each thing
occupies within the grid of Nature-from God on down the cosmic tree
of being-that determines its fundamental (lowercase n) nature. For
Spinoza, one's nature is determined by one's place in Nature or, in
terms of the fundamental axiom of the book-the Nature-unfolding
axiom: the nature of x=Nature at x. Almog's reading of Spinoza is
distinct in its understanding of the deductive abstractions of part
I-II of the Ethics by means of the concrete illustrations of
Spinoza's intended subject matter in his political writings, where
he tells us directly (i) what Nature is and (ii) how man's nature
is not a separate kingdom from the Nature-kingdom but merely an
unfolding of it. This leads, as in the Ethics, to a final chapter
on what it meant to Spinoza to live in symbiosis with Nature and,
therefore, to be one with it-and with God.
The Letter to Strahan is an ostensible letter that Adam Smith wrote
on the last days, death, and character of his closest friend, the
philosopher David Hume, and published alongside Hume's
autobiography, My Own Life, in 1777. Other than his two books, it
is the only work that Smith published under his name during his
lifetime, and it elicited a great deal of commentary and
controversy. Because of Hume's reputation for impiety, Smith's
portrayal of his friend's cheerfulness and equanimity during his
final days provoked outrage among the devout. Smith later commented
that this work "brought upon me ten times more abuse than the very
violent attack I had made upon the whole commercial system of Great
Britain"-meaning, of course, The Wealth of Nations. This is the
first annotated version of this fascinating and important work.
Along with the Letter to Strahan, the volume also includes Hume's
My Own Life, the work to which the Letter was a kind of companion
piece; two personal letters related to the Letter; and three
published responses to the Letter-two viciously critical and one
generally favorable. A substantial editor's introduction discusses
the context, composition, publication, and significance of the
Letter, along with the strong reaction that it provoked. Taken
together, the works included in the volume provide an entertaining
and accessible entree into some of the most controversial debates
over religion and morality in the eighteenth century.
Immanuel Kant's legal philosophy and theory have played an enormous
role in the development of law since the eighteenth century.
Although this influence can be seen primarily in German law and in
the law of nations which have traditionally been oriented toward
German legal development, today Kant's philosophy has experienced a
Renaissance in the Anglo-American legal world. This anthology
collects what the editors believe to be the very best of articles
on Kant's legal theory, with an emphasis on his Metaphysics of
Morals of 1797. In particular the articles relate to: 1) the nature
of law and justice, 2) private law, 3) public law, 4) criminal law,
5) international law, and 6) cosmopolitan law.
Few philosophers have been the subject of as much or as intense
debate, yet almost everyone agrees on one thing: Jean-Jacques
Rousseau is among the most important and influential thinkers in
the history of political philosophy. This new edition of his major
political writings renews attention to the perennial importance of
his work. The book brings together superb new translations of three
of Rousseau's works: the Discourse on the Sciences and the Arts,
the Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among
Men, and On the Social Contract. The two Discourses show Rousseau
developing his well-known conception of the natural goodness of man
and the problems posed by life in society. With the Social
Contract, Rousseau became the first major thinker to argue that
democracy is the only legitimate form of political organization.
Translation and editorial notes clarify ideas and terms that might
not be immediately familiar to most readers.
The work of seventeenth-century polymath Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
has proved inspirational to philosophers and scientists alike. In
this thought-provoking book, Pauline Phemister explores the
ecological potential of Leibniz's dynamic, pluralist, panpsychist,
metaphysical system. She argues that Leibniz's philosophy has a
renewed relevance in the twenty-first century, particularly in
relation to the environmental change and crises that threaten human
and non-human life on earth. Drawing on Leibniz's theory of
soul-like, interconnected metaphysical entities he termed 'monads',
Phemister explains how an individual's true good is inextricably
linked to the good of all. Phemister also finds in Leibniz's works
the rudiments of a theory of empathy and strategies for
strengthening human feelings of compassion towards all living
things. Leibniz and the Environment is essential reading for
historians of philosophy and environmental philosophers, and will
also be of interest to anyone seeking a metaphysical perspective
from which to pursue environmental action and policy.
Scottish philosopher Lady Mary Shepherd (1777-1847) wrote two books
that she conceived as one unified project: Essay Upon the Relation
of Cause and Effect (1824) and Essays on the Perception of an
External Universe (1827). While they were well received in her day,
Shepherd's insightful philosophical writings have been neglected
for some 150 years and are only now receiving the scholarly
attention they deserve. Mary Shepherd: A Guide by Deborah Boyle,
part of the Oxford Guides to Philosophy series, navigates students
of philosophy or general readers through Shepherd's two significant
works. The first four chapters address topics raised in the 1824
Essay: Shepherd's arguments for two key causal principles, her
objections to Hume and her alternative accounts of causation and
causal inference; her theory of objects as bundles of qualities;
her critique of Thomas Brown's defence of Humean causation; and her
discussion of London surgeon William Lawrence's accounts of
sentience and life, which Shepherd treats as a case study of how
Humean theory can lead to errors in scientific reasoning. Chapter 5
covers topics central to both of Shepherd's books: what she means
by "sensation," "idea," "will," "imagination," "understanding,"
"reasoning," and "latent reasoning." The remaining five chapters
proceed systematically through Shepherd's 1827 book, where she
seeks to prove, against Berkeleian idealism, that we can know that
an external world of mind-independent matter exists. Boyle
discusses Shepherd's proofs for such an external world, her
responses to various sceptical challenges, and her specific
objections to Berkeley. Each chapter ends with a list of works for
further reading and a glossary of terms that explain Shepherd's
sometimes idiosyncratic philosophical vocabulary, resulting in an
essential guide to a philosopher who exerted considerable influence
during her time.
|
|