|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present
Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity offers a radical new
interpretation of Heidegger's later philosophy, developing his
argument that art can help lead humanity beyond the nihilistic
ontotheology of the modern age. Providing pathbreaking readings of
Heidegger's The Origin of the Work of Art and his notoriously
difficult Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning), this book
explains precisely what postmodernity meant for Heidegger, the
greatest philosophical critic of modernity, and what it could still
mean for us today. Exploring these issues, Iain D. Thomson examines
several postmodern works of art, including music, literature,
painting, and even comic books, from a post-Heideggerian
perspective. Clearly written and accessible, this book will help
readers gain a deeper understanding of Heidegger and his relation
to postmodern theory, popular culture, and art.
Presented as a Vorlesung in the German philosophical tradition,
this book presents the most detailed account of Nelson's method of
argument analysis, celebrated by many luminaries such as Karl
Popper. It was written in 1921 in opposition to the relativistic,
subjectivistic and nihilistic tendencies of Nelson's time. The book
contains an exposition of a method that is a further development of
Kant's transcendental dialectics, followed by an application to the
critical analysis of arguments by many famous thinkers, including
Bentham, Mill, Poincare, Leibniz, Hegel, Einstein, Bergson,
Rickert, Simmel, Brentano, Stammler, Jellinek, Dingler, and
Meinong. The book presents a general theory of philosophical
argumentation as seen from the viewpoint of the typical fallacies
committed by anybody arguing philosophically, whether professional
philosophers or philosophical laypeople. Although the nature of
philosophy and philosophical argumentation is one of the most
recurrent objects of reflection for philosophers, this book
represents the first attempt at a general theory of philosophical
fallacy. According to Nelson, it is in the shape of false dilemmas
that errors in reasoning always emerge, and false dilemmas are
always the result of the same mechanism--the unwitting replacement
of one concept for another.
This book investigates the complex, sometimes fraught relationship
between phenomenology and the natural sciences. The contributors
attempt to subvert and complicate the divide that has historically
tended to characterize the relationship between the two fields.
Phenomenology has traditionally been understood as methodologically
distinct from scientific practice, and thus removed from any claim
that philosophy is strictly continuous with science. There is some
substance to this thinking, which has dominated consideration of
the relationship between phenomenology and science throughout the
twentieth century. However, there are also emerging trends within
both phenomenology and empirical science that complicate this too
stark opposition, and call for more systematic consideration of the
inter-relation between the two fields. These essays explore such
issues, either by directly examining meta-philosophical and
methodological matters, or by looking at particular topics that
seem to require the resources of each, including imagination,
cognition, temporality, affect, imagery, language, and perception.
The commonly held view that Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion
is fideistic loses plausibility when contrasted with recent
scholarship on Wittgenstein's corpus and biography. This book
reevaluates the place of Wittgenstein in the philosophy of religion
and charts a path forward for the subfield by advancing three
themes.
"The World Unclaimed" argues that Heidegger's critique of modern
epistemology in "Being and Time" is seriously flawed. Heidegger
believes he has done away with epistemological problems concerning
the external world by showing that the world is an existential
structure of Dasein. However, the author argues that Heidegger
fails to make good his claim that he has "rescued" the phenomenon
of the world, which he believes the tradition of philosophy has
bypassed. Heidegger fails not only to reclaim the world but also to
acknowledge its loss. Alweiss thus calls into question Heidegger's
claim that ontology is more fundamental than epistemology.
"The World Unclaimed" develops its powerful critique of Being and
Time by arguing for a return to Husserl. It draws on Husserl's
insight that it is the moving and sensing body that discloses how
we are already familiar with the world. Kinaesthesia provides a key
for understanding our relation to the world. The author thus
suggests that thinkers in the vein of Husserl and Kant -who, for
Heidegger, epitomize the tradition of modern philosophy by
returning to a "worldless subject"- may provide us with the
resources to reclaim the phenomenon of the world that "Being and
Time" sets out to salvage.
Alweiss's fresh and innovative study demonstrates that it is
possible to overcome epistemological skepticism without ever losing
sight of the phenomenon of the world. Moreover, Alweiss challenges
us to reconsider the relation between Husserl and Heidegger by
providing a forceful defense of Husserl's critique of cognition.
This edited volume offers a new approach to understanding social
conventions by way of Martin Heidegger. It connects the
philosopher's conceptions of the anyone, everydayness, and
authenticity with an analysis and critique of social normativity.
Heidegger's account of the anyone is ambiguous. Some see it as a
good description of human sociality, others think of it as an
important critique of modern mass society. This volume seeks to
understand this ambiguity as reflecting the tension between the
constitutive function of conventions for human action and the
critical aspects of conformism. It argues that Heidegger's anyone
should neither be reduced to its pejorative nor its constitutive
dimension. Rather, the concept could show how power and norms
function. This volume would be of interest to scholars and students
of philosophy and the social sciences who wish to investigate the
social applications of the works of Martin Heidegger.
In Nietzsche and Zen: Self-Overcoming Without a Self, Andre van der
Braak engages Nietzsche in a dialogue with four representatives of
the Buddhist Zen tradition: Nagarjuna (c. 150-250), Linji (d. 860),
Dogen (1200-1253), and Nishitani (1900-1990). In doing so, he
reveals Nietzsche's thought as a philosophy of continuous
self-overcoming, in which even the notion of "self" has been
overcome. Van der Braak begins by analyzing Nietzsche's
relationship to Buddhism and status as a transcultural thinker,
recalling research on Nietzsche and Zen to date and setting out the
basic argument of the study. He continues by examining the
practices of self-overcoming in Nietzsche and Zen, comparing
Nietzsche's radical skepticism with that of Nagarjuna and comparing
Nietzsche's approach to truth to Linji's. Nietzsche's methods of
self-overcoming are compared to Dogen's zazen, or sitting
meditation practice, and Dogen's notion of forgetting the self.
These comparisons and others build van der Braak's case for a
criticism of Nietzsche informed by the ideas of Zen Buddhism and a
criticism of Zen Buddhism seen through the Western lens of
Nietzsche - coalescing into one world philosophy. This treatment,
focusing on one of the most fruitful areas of research within
contemporary comparative and intercultural philosophy, will be
useful to Nietzsche scholars, continental philosophers, and
comparative philosophers."
This book begins with an observation: At the time when empiricism
arose and slowly established itself, the word itself had not yet
been coined. Hence the central question of this volume: What does
it mean to conduct empirical science in early modern Europe? How
can we catch the elusive figure of the empiricist? Our answer
focuses on the practices established by representative scholars.
This approach allows us to demonstrate two things. First, that
empiricism is not a monolith but exists in a plurality of forms.
Today's understanding of the empirical sciences was gradually
shaped by the exchanges among scholars combining different
traditions, world views and experimental settings. Second, the long
proclaimed antagonism between empiricism and rationalism is not the
whole story. Our case studies show that a very fruitful exchange
between both systems of thought occurred. It is a story of
integration, appropriation and transformation more than one of mere
opposition. We asked twelve authors to explore these fascinating
new facets of empiricisms. The plurality of their voices mirrors
the multiple faces of the concept itself. Every contribution can be
understood as a piece of a much larger puzzle. Together, they help
us better understand the emergence of empiricism and the
inventiveness of the scientific enterprise.
This book offers a clear, analytic, and innovative interpretation
of Heidegger's late work. This period of Heidegger's philosophy
remains largely unexplored by analytic philosophers, who consider
it filled with inconsistencies and paradoxical ideas, particularly
concerning the notions of Being and nothingness. This book takes
seriously the claim that the late Heidegger endorses dialetheism -
namely the position according to which some contradictions are true
- and shows that the idea that Being is both an entity and not an
entity is neither incoherent nor logically trivial. The author
achieves this by presenting and defending the idea that reality has
an inconsistent structure. In doing so, he takes one of the most
discussed topics in current analytic metaphysics, grounding theory,
into a completely unexplored area. Additionally, in order to make
sense of Heidegger's concept of nothingness, the author introduces
an original axiomatic mereological system that, having a
paraconsistent logic as a base logic, can tolerate inconsistencies
without falling into logical triviality. This is the first book to
set forth a complete and detailed discussion of the late Heidegger
in the framework of analytic metaphysics. It will be of interest to
Heidegger scholars and analytic philosophers working on theories of
grounding, mereology, dialetheism, and paraconsistent logic.
This volume presents political phenomenology as a new specialty in
western philosophical and political thought that is post-classical,
post-Machiavellian, and post-behavioral. It draws on history and
sets the agenda for future explorations of political issues. It
discloses crossroads between ethics and politics and explores
border-crossing issues. All the essays in this volume challenge
existing ideas of politics significantly. As such they open new
ways for further explorations BY future generations of
phenomenologists and non-phenomenologists alike. Moreover, the
comprehensive chronological bibliography is unprecedented and
provides not only an excellent picture of what phenomenologists
have already done but also a guide for the future.
This is the first volume dedicated to a direct exploration of
Wittgenstein and Plato. It is a compilation of essays by thirteen
authors of diverse geographical provenance, orientation and
philosophical interest.
The volume offers the most complete and detailed view to date on
Wittgenstein and Plato, without being tied to any unilateral
guidelines from either a critical or philosophical perspective. The
authors are scholars of Wittgenstein, but also of Plato and Greek
philosophy. The book is a sort of game of mirrors: Plato in the
mirror of Wittgenstein, and Wittgenstein in the mirror of Plato.
All essays always seek to combine philosophical interest and
philological attention, although, in some essays one interest
prevails over the other.
Despite the preponderance of scholars of Wittgenstein, the volume
seeks to be not only a book on Wittgenstein and Plato, but also,
simultaneously, on Plato and Wittgenstein.
In this brief and accessible introduction, Russell guides the
reader through his famous 1910 distinction between "knowledge by
acquaintance and knowledge by description" and introduces important
theories of Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Hume, Locke, Kant, Hegel
and others. He lays the foundation for philosophical inquiry for
general readers and scholars.There are sixteen chapters: Appearance
and Reality, The Existence of Matter, The Nature of Matter,
Idealism, Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description,
On Induction, On Our Knowledge Of General Principles, How A Priori
Knowledge Is Possible, The World of Universals, On Our Knowledge of
Universals, On Intuitive Knowledge, Truth and Falsehood, Knowledge,
Error, and Probable Opinion, The Limits of Philosophical Knowledge,
The Value of Philosophy. Russell also provides a short
supplementary reading list.
One hundred years ago, Russell and Whitehead published their
epoch-making Principia Mathematica (PM), which was initially
conceived as the second volume of Russell's Principles of
Mathematics (PoM) that had appeared ten years before. No other
works can be credited to have had such an impact on the development
of logic and on philosophy in the twentieth century. However, until
now, scholars only focused on the first parts of the books - that
is, on Russell's and Whitehead's theory of logic, set-theory and
arithmetic.
Sebastien Gandon aims at reversing the perspective. His goal is to
give a picture of Russell's logicism based on a detailed reading of
the developments dealing with advanced mathematics - namely
projective geometry and the theory of quantity. This book is not
only the first study ever made of the 'later' portions of PoM and
PM, it also shows how this shift of perspective compels us to
change our view of the logicist program taken as a whole.
This book presents Heidegger as a thinker of revolution.
Understanding revolution as an occurrence whereby the previously
unforeseeable comes to appear as inevitable, the temporal character
of such an event is explored through Heidegger's discussion of
temporality and historicity. Beginning with his magnum opus, Being
and Time, Heidegger is shown to have undertaken a radical
rethinking of time in terms of human action, understood as
involving both doing and making and as implicated in an interplay
of the opportune moment (kairos) and temporal continuity (chronos).
Developing this theme through his key writings of the early 1930s,
the book shows how Heidegger's analyses of truth and freedom led to
an increasingly dialectical account of time and action culminating
in his phenomenology of the - artistic and political - 'work'. A
context is thus given for Heidegger's political engagement in 1933.
While diagnosing the moral failure of this engagement, the book
defends Heidegger's account of the time of human action and shows
it to foreshadow his later thought of a 'new beginning'.
A collection of essays which explores the significance of
Wittgenstein for the Philosophy of Religion. Explorations of
central notions in Wittgenstein's later philosophy are brought to
bear on the clash between belief and atheism; understanding
religious experience; language and ritual; evil and theodicies;
miracles; and the possibility of a Christian philosophy.
This book defines the relationship between the thought of Adam Smith and that of the ancients---Plato, Aristotle, Cicero, and the Stoics. Vivenza offers a complete survey of all Smith's writings with the aim of illustrating how classical arguments shaped opinions and scholarship in the eighteenth century.
Kevin Hermberg's book fills an important gap in previous Husserl
scholarship by focusing on intersubjectivity and empathy (i.e., the
experience of others as other subjects) and by addressing the
related issues of validity, the degrees of evidence with which
something can be experienced, and the different senses of
'objective' in Husserl's texts. Despite accusations by commentators
that Husserl's is a solipsistic philosophy and that the
epistemologies in Husserl's late and early works are contradictory,
Hermberg shows that empathy, and thus other subjects, are related
to one's knowledge on the view offered in each of Husserl's
Introductions to Phenomenology. Empathy is significantly related to
knowledge in at least two ways, and Husserl's epistemology might,
consequently, be called a social epistemology: (a) empathy helps to
give evidence for validity and thus to solidify one's knowledge,
and (b) it helps to broaden one's knowledge by giving access to
what others have known. These roles of empathy are not at odds with
one another; rather, both are at play in each of the Introductions
(if even only implicitly) and, given his position in the earlier
work, Husserl needed to expand the role of empathy as he did. Such
a reliance on empathy, however, calls into question whether
Husserl's is a transcendental philosophy in the sense Husserl
claimed.
A comprehensive and accessible overview of, and introduction to,
the work of one of the twentieth century's most influential
philosophers, Martin Heidegger, by one of the world's foremost
Heidegger scholars. Martin Heidegger's work is pivotal in the
history of modern European philosophy. The New Heidegger presents a
comprehensive and stimulating overview of, and introduction to, the
work of one of the most influential and controversial philosophers
of our time. Heidegger has had an extraordinary impact on
contemporary philosophical and extra-philosophical life: on
deconstruction, hermeneutics, ontology, technology and
techno-science, art and architecture, politics, psychotherapy, and
ecology. The New Heidegger takes a thematic approach to Heidegger's
work, covering not only the seminal Being and Time, but also
Heidegger's lesser-known works. Lively, clear and succinct, the
book requires no prior knowledge of Heidegger and is an essential
resource for anyone studying or teaching the work of this major
modern philosopher.
Despite Enlightenment scepticism about the supernatural, stories
about spirits were regularly printed and shared throughout the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. This case-study in the
transmission of a single story (of a young gunsmith near Bristol
conjuring spirits, leading to his early death) reveals both how and
why successive generations found meaning in such accounts. It shows
the workings of an expanding national print culture, but also the
continued importance of locality, oral culture and manuscript
copying, especially among the newly educated. It offers an insight
into the culture of Anglican clergy, spiritual autodidacts,
evangelical preachers, pioneering astrologers, mesmerists and
spiritualists, revealing the on-going appeal of Bible-based
providentialism. Initially told as a warning-lesson against
meddling with the demonic, the story also appealed to those keen to
uphold the existence of spirits, and to various groups who
themselves wished to communicate with spirits, while its portrayal
of a doomed youth attracted sympathy.
In Of Liberty and Necessity James A. Harris presents the first
comprehensive account of the free will problem in
eighteenth-century British philosophy. Harris proposes new
interpretations of the positions of familiar figures such as Locke,
Hume, Edwards, and Reid. He also gives careful attention to writers
such as William King, Samuel Clarke, Anthony Collins, Lord Kames,
James Beattie, David Hartley, Joseph Priestley, and Dugald Stewart,
who, while well-known in the eighteenth century, have since been
largely ignored by historians of philosophy. Through detailed
textual analysis, and by making precise use of a variety of
different contexts, Harris elucidates the contribution that each of
these writers makes to the eighteenth-century discussion of the
will and its freedom. In this period, the question of the nature of
human freedom is posed principally in terms of the influence of
motives upon the will. On one side of the debate are those who
believe that we are free in our choices. A motive, these
philosophers believe, constitutes a reason to act in a particular
way, but it is up to us which motive we act upon. On the other side
of the debate are those who believe that, on the contrary, there is
no such thing as freedom of choice. According to these
philosophers, one motive is always intrinsically stronger than the
rest and so is the one that must determine choice. Several
important issues are raised as this disagreement is explored and
developed, including the nature of motives, the value of
'indifference' to the will's freedom, the distinction between
'moral' and 'physical' necessity, the relation between the will and
the understanding, and the internal coherence of the concept of
freedom of will. One of Harris's primary objectives is to place
this debate in the context of the eighteenth-century concern with
replicating in the mental sphere what Newton had achieved in the
philosophy of nature. All of the philosophers discussed in Of
Liberty and Necessity conceive of themselves as 'experimental'
reasoners, and, when examining the will, focus primarily upon what
experience reveals about the influence of motives upon choice. The
nature and significance of introspection is therefore at the very
centre of the free will problem in this period, as is the question
of what can legitimately be inferred from observable regularities
in human behaviour.
This collection is an attempt by a diverse range of authors to
reignite interest in C.I. Lewis's work within the pragmatist and
analytic traditions. Although pragmatism has enjoyed a renewed
popularity in the past thirty years, some influential pragmatists
have been overlooked. C. I. Lewis is arguably the most important of
overlooked pragmatists and was highly influential within his own
time period. The volume assembles a wide range of perspectives on
the strengths and weaknesses of Lewis's contributions to
metaphysics, epistemology, semantics, philosophy of science, and
ethics.
|
|