|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present
In explicit form, Kant does not speak that much about values or
goods. The reason for this is obvious: the concepts of 'values' and
'goods' are part of the eudaimonistic tradition, and he famously
criticizes eudaimonism for its flawed 'material' approach to
ethics. But he uses, on several occasions, the traditional
teleological language of goods and values. Especially in the
Groundwork and the Critique of Practical Reason, Kant develops
crucial points on this conceptual basis. Furthermore, he implicitly
discusses issues of conditional and unconditional values,
subjective and objective values, aesthetic or economic values etc.
In recent Kant scholarship, there has been a controversy on the
question how moral and nonmoral values are related in Kant's
account of human dignity. This leads to the more fundamental
problem if Kant should be seen as a prescriptvist (antirealist) or
as subscribing to a more objective rational agency account of
goods. This issue and several further questions are addressed in
this volume.
In her new book, Corine Pelluchon argues that the dichotomy between
nature and culture privileges the latter. She laments that the
political system protects the sovereignty of the human and leaves
them immune to impending environmental disaster. Using the
phenomenological writings of French philosophers like Emmanuel
Levinas, Jacques Derrida, and Paul Ricoeur, Pelluchon contends that
human beings have to recognise humanity's dependence upon the
natural world for survival and adopt a new philosophy of existence
that advocates for animal welfare and ecological preservation. In
an extension of Heidegger's ontology of concern, Pelluchon declares
that this dependence is not negative or a sign of weakness. She
argues instead, that we are nourished by the natural world and that
the very idea of nourishment contains an element of pleasure. This
sustenance comforts humans and gives their lives taste. Pelluchon's
new philosophy claims then, that eating has an affective, social
and cultural dimension, but that most importantly it is a political
act. It solidifies the eternal link between human beings and
animals, and warns that the human consumption of animals and other
natural resources impacts upon humanity's future.
Trees and tree products have long been central to human life and
culture, taking on intensified significance during the long
eighteenth century. As basic raw material they were vital economic
resources, objects of international diplomatic and commercial
exchange, and key features in local economies. In an age of ongoing
deforestation, both individuals and public entities grappled with
the complex issues of how and why trees mattered. In this
interdisciplinary volume, contributors build on recent research in
environmental history, literary and material culture, and
postcolonial studies to develop new readings of the ways trees were
valued in the eighteenth century. They trace changes in early
modern theories of resource management and ecology across European
and North American landscapes, and show how different and sometimes
contradictory practices were caught up in shifting conceptions of
nature, social identity, physical health and moral wellbeing. In
its innovative and thought-provoking exploration of man's
relationship with trees, Invaluable trees: cultures of nature, 1660
-1830 argues for new ways of understanding the long eighteenth
century and its values, and helps re-frame the environmental
challenges of our own time.
Addressing Merleau-Ponty's work Phenomenology of Perception, in
dialogue with The Visible and the Invisible, his lectures at the
College de France, and his reading of Proust, this book argues that
at play in his thought is a philosophy of "ontological lateness".
This describes the manner in which philosophical reflection is
fated to lag behind its objects; therefore an absolute grasp on
being remains beyond its reach. Merleau-Ponty articulates this
philosophy against the backdrop of what he calls "cruel thought", a
style of reflecting that seeks resolution by limiting,
circumscribing, and arresting its object. By contrast, the
philosophy of ontological lateness seeks no such finality-no
apocalypsis or unveiling-but is characterized by its ability to
accept the veiling of being and its own constitutive lack of
punctuality. To this extent, his thinking inaugurates a new
relation to the becoming of sense that overcomes cruel thought.
Merleau-Ponty's work gives voice to a wisdom of dispossession that
allows for the withdrawal of being. Never before has anyone engaged
with the theme of Merleau-Ponty's own understanding of philosophy
in such a sustained way as Whitmoyer does in this volume.
Marx's early work is well known and widely available, but it
usually interpreted as at best a kind of stepping-stone to the Marx
of Capital. This book offers something completely different; it
reconstructs, from his first writings spanning from 1835 to 1846, a
coherent and well-rounded political philosophy. The influence of
Engels upon the development of that philosophy is discussed. This,
it is argued, was a philosophy that Marx could have presented had
he put the ideas together, as he hinted was his eventual intention.
Had he done so, this first Marx would have made an even greater
contribution to social and political philosophy than is generally
acknowledged today. Arguments regarding revolutionary change,
contradiction and other topics such as production, alienation and
emancipation contribute to a powerful analysis in the early works
of Marx, one which is worthy of discussion on its own merits. This
analysis is distributed among a range of books, papers, letters and
other writings, and is gathered here for the first time. Marx's
work of the period was driven by his commitment to emancipation.
Moreover, as is discussed in the conclusion to this book, his
emancipatory philosophy continues to have resonance today. This new
book presents Marx in a unique, new light and will be indispensable
reading for all studying and following his work.
Best known for the progressive school he founded in Dessau during
the 18th century, Johann Bernhard Basedow was a central thinker in
the German Enlightenment. Since his death in 1790 a substantial
body of German-language literature about his life, work, and school
(the Philanthropin) has developed. In the first English
intellectual biography of this influential figure, Robert B. Louden
answers questions that continue to surround Basedow and provides a
much-needed examination of Basedow's intellectual legacy. Assessing
the impact of his ideas and theories on subsequent educational
movements, Louden argues that Basedow is the unacknowledged father
of the progressive education movement. He unravels several
paradoxes surrounding the Philanthropin to help understand why it
was described by Immanuel Kant as "the greatest phenomenon which
has appeared in this century for the perfection of humanity",
despite its brief and stormy existence, its low enrollment and
insufficient funding. Among the many neglected stories Louden tells
is the enormous and unacknowledged debt that Kant owes to Basedow
in his philosophy of education, history, and religion. This is a
positive reassessment of Basedow and his difficult personality that
leads to a reevaluation of the originality of major figures as well
as a reconsideration of the significance of allegedly minor authors
who have been eclipsed by the politics of historiography. For
anyone looking to gain a deeper understanding of the history of
German philosophy, Louden's book is essential reading.
|
You may like...
Street God
Dimas Salaberrios
Paperback
(1)
R435
R376
Discovery Miles 3 760
|