|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present > Western philosophy, from c 1900 - > Phenomenology & Existentialism
In Phenomenology and Lacan on Schizophrenia, Alphonse De Waelhens
provides a clear summary of Lacan's theory of schizophrenia, as
Lacan derived it from his commentary of Freud's study of the
Memoirs of Schreber. De Waelhens also shows how Lacan's
understanding of the schizophrenic as having a defective relation
to language can also explain four other characteristics of
schizophrenic behavior: the fragmented body image; lack of
realistic evaluation of the world; so-called bisexuality; and
confusion of birth and death. Third, De Waelhens gives a Hegelian
interpretation of the pre-Oedipal experience of the child. He makes
use of Freud's study on his grand-child using a bobbin and later
the words fort-da (away-here), to demonstrate that a transitional
object allows the child to take distance from its attachment to the
mother so that it can start to separate itself from the mother.
Taking distance is, according to De Waelhens, introducing the
Hegelian negative, which is the birth of the subject. Fourth, De
Waelhens gives a dialectic reading of the history of German and
French psychiatry. He shows the epistemological contradictions in
the work of some of the great nineteenth century psychiatrists
relying too exclusively on a biological model of schizophrenia.In
his contribution to this volume, Wilfried Ver Eecke draws several
lessons from evaluating the literature on schizophrenia. He argues
that epistemologically neither a biological nor a psychological
method of reasoning can capture all the factors that can play a
role in the creation of schizophrenia. He relies heavily, but not
exclusively, on the Finnish studies of Tienari, Myrhman, and
Wahlberg and their colleagues to provide statistical evidence that
non-biological factors also play an important role in causing
schizophrenia. He relies heavily, but again not exclusively, on the
study by Karon and VandenBos to demonstrate statistically the
efficiency of psychodynamically inspired therapy of
schizophrenics.Ver Eecke also addresses an apparent inconsistency
in De Waelhens' presentation of Lacan's theory of schizophrenia.
Where De Waelhens seemed to argue at one time that the mother
figure was the crucial figure to explain schizophrenia (leading to
a defective relation to the body) and at another time that it was
the role of the father which was crucial (leading to a defective
relation to language and the symbolic), there Ver Eecke argues that
the defective function of each influences the function of the
other. He then draws a conclusion for the therapy of
schizophrenics: to be helpful a therapist will have to address both
deficiencies. The problem for treating schizophrenics is that
correcting an unconscious deficiency to the body-a deficiency in
the imaginary-requires a totally different kind of intervention
than an attempt to correct a symbolic deficiency-a deficiency in
the paternal function. A correction of the imaginary requires a
kind of maternal mirroring; a correction of the symbolic requires
making a distinction or a prohibition stick. One further difficulty
arises. Psychotherapy uses language in its treatment. However,
language in schizophrenics is deficient. We can therefore expect
that language will be inefficient. This is so unless the therapist
uses language, first, to make a repair at the imaginary level and
only thereafter makes an attempt to make a correction in the
symbolic. In analyzing successful therapeutic techniques reported
by several therapists Ver Eecke discovers that all of them first
try to repair the imaginary before they attempt to make corrections
to the symbolic.
The German poet and mystic Novalis once identified philosophy as a
form of homesickness. More than two centuries later, as modernity's
displacements continue to intensify, we feel Novalis's homesickness
more than ever. Yet nowhere has a longing for home flourished more
than in contemporary environmental thinking, and particularly in
eco-phenomenology. If only we can reestablish our sense of material
enmeshment in nature, so the logic goes, we might reverse the
degradation we humans have wrought-and in saving the earth we can
once again dwell in the nearness of our own being. Unsettling
Nature opens with a meditation on the trouble with such ecological
homecoming narratives, which bear a close resemblance to narratives
of settler colonial homemaking. Taylor Eggan demonstrates that the
Heideggerian strain of eco-phenomenology-along with its well-trod
categories of home, dwelling, and world-produces uncanny effects in
settler colonial contexts. He reads instances of nature's
defamiliarization not merely as psychological phenomena but also as
symptoms of the repressed consciousness of coloniality. The book at
once critiques Heidegger's phenomenology and brings it forward
through chapters on Willa Cather, D. H. Lawrence, Olive Schreiner,
Doris Lessing, and J. M. Coetzee. Suggesting that alienation may in
fact be "natural" to the human condition and hence something worth
embracing instead of repressing, Unsettling Nature concludes with a
speculative proposal to transform eco-phenomenology into
"exo-phenomenology"-an experiential mode that engages deeply with
the alterity of others and with the self as its own Other.
Marking the 50th anniversary of one among this philosopher’s most
distinguished pieces, Blumenberg’s Rhetoric proffers a decidedly
diversified interaction with the essai polyvalently entitled
‘Anthropological Approach to the Topicality (or Currency,
Relevance, even actualitas) of Rhetoric’ ("Anthropologische
Annäherung an die Aktualität der Rhetorik"), first published in
1971. Following Blumenberg’s lead, the contributors consider and
tackle their topics rhetorically—treating (inter alia) the
variegated discourses of Phenomenology and Truthcraft, of
Intellectual History and Anthropology, as well as the interplay of
methods, from a plurality of viewpoints. The diachronically
extensive, disciplinarily diverse essays of this
publication—notably in the current lingua franca—will
facilitate, and are to conduce to, further scholarship with respect
to Blumenberg and the art of rhetoric. With contributions by Sonja
Feger, Simon Godart, Joachim Küpper, DS Mayfield, Heinrich
Niehues-Pröbsting, Daniel Rudy Hiller, Katrin Trüstedt, Alexander
Waszynski, Friedrich Weber-Steinhaus, Nicola Zambon.
Before now, there has been no comprehensive analysis of the
multiple relations between A. Comte's and J.S. Mill's positive
philosophy and Franz Brentano's work. The present volume aims to
fill this gap and to identify Brentano's position in the context of
the positive philosophy of the 19th century by analyzing the
following themes: the concept of positive knowledge; philosophy and
empirical, genetic and descriptive psychology as sciences in
Brentano, Comte and Mill; the strategies for the rebirth of
philosophy in these three authors; the theory of the ascending
stages of thought, of their decline, of the intentionality in Comte
and Brentano; the reception of Comte's positivism in Whewell and
Mill; induction and phenomenalism in Brentano, Mill and Bain; the
problem of the "I" in Hume and Brentano; mathematics as a
foundational science in Brentano, Kant and Mill; Brentano's
critique of Mach's positivism; the concept of positive science in
Brentano's metaphysics and in Husserl's early phenomenology; the
reception of Brentano's psychology in Twardowski; The Brentano
Institute at Oxford. The volume also contains the translation of
the most significant writings of Brentano regarding philosophy as
science. I. Tanasescu, Romanian Academy; A. Bejinariu, Romanian
Society of Phenomenology; S. Krantz Gabriel, Saint Anselm College;
C. Stoenescu, University of Bucharest.
What is given to us in conscious experience? The Given is an
attempt to answer this question and in this way contribute to a
general theory of mental content. The content of conscious
experience is understood to be absolutely everything that is given
to one, experientially, in the having of an experience. Michelle
Montague focuses on the analysis of conscious perception, conscious
emotion, and conscious thought, and deploys three fundamental
notions in addition to the fundamental notion of content: the
notions of intentionality, phenomenology, and consciousness. She
argues that all experience essentially involves all four things,
and that the key to an adequate general theory of what is given in
experience-of 'the given'-lies in giving a correct specification of
the nature of these four things and the relations between them.
Montague argues that conscious perception, conscious thought, and
conscious emotion each have a distinctive, irreducible kind of
phenomenology-what she calls 'sensory phenomenology', 'cognitive
phenomenology', and 'evaluative phenomenology' respectively-and
that these kinds of phenomenology are essential in accounting for
the intentionality of these mental phenomena.
Soren Kierkegaard's Christian existentialism provides a unique
framework for thinking about the problem of religious pluralism.
This problem arises from the fact that there are lots of different
religions in the world and each of them teaches different things.
Accordingly, it is difficult to know which one, if any, ought to be
believed in as actually being true. Fehir defends his view of
Kierkegaard's understanding of faith and uses it to deal with
common philosophical problems related to pluralism. In the course
of advancing this argument, Kierkegaardian Reflections of the
Problem of Pluralism also engages in interreligious dialogue by
comparing Kierkegaard's views with representatives from Buddhism,
Judaism, and Taoism.
The Risk of Freedom presents an in-depth analysis of the philosophy
of Jan Patocka, one of the most influential Central European
thinkers of the twentieth century, examining both the
phenomenological and ethical-political aspects of his work. In
particular, Francesco Tava takes an original approach to the
problem of freedom, which represents a recurring theme in Patocka's
work, both in his early and later writings. Freedom is conceived of
as a difficult and dangerous experience. In his deep analysis of
this particular problem, Tava identifies the authentic ethical
content of Patocka's work and clarifies its connections with
phenomenology, history of philosophy, politics and dissidence. The
Risk of Freedom retraces Patocka's philosophical journey and
elucidates its more problematic and less evident traits, such as
his original ethical conception, his political ideals and his
direct commitment as a dissident.
It is widely agreed that there is such a thing as sensory
phenomenology and imagistic phenomenology. The central concern of
the cognitive phenomenology debate is whether there is a
distinctive "cognitive phenomenology"--that is, a kind of
phenomenology that has cognitive or conceptual character in some
sense that needs to be precisely determined. This volume presents
new work by leading philosophers in the field, and addresses the
question of whether conscious thought has cognitive phenomenology.
It also includes a number of essays which consider whether
cognitive phenomenology is part of conscious perception and
conscious emotion.
Three broad themes run through the volume. First, some authors
focus on the question of how the notion of cognitive phenomenology
ought to be understood. How should the notion of cognitive
phenomenology be defined? Are there different kinds of cognitive
phenomenology? A second theme concerns the existence of cognitive
phenomenology. Some contributors defend the existence of a
distinctive cognitive phenomenology, whereas others deny it. The
arguments for and against the existence of cognitive phenomenology
raise questions concerning the nature of first-person knowledge of
thought, the relationship between consciousness and intentionality,
and the scope of the explanatory gap. A third theme concerns the
implications of the cognitive phenomenology debate. What are the
implications of the debate for accounts of our introspective access
to conscious thought and for accounts of the very nature of
conscious thought? Cognitive Phenomenology brings the debate to the
forefront of philosophy, and provides a state-of-the-art account of
the issues at stake.
|
|