|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Western philosophy, c 500 to c 1600
Francisco Suarez was a principal figure in the transition from
scholastic to modern natural law, summing up a long and rich
tradition and providing much material both for adoption and
controversy in the seventeenth century and beyond.Most of the
selections translated in this volume are from "On the Laws and God
the Law-Giver" ("De legibus ac Deo legislatore, " 1612), a work
that is considered one of Suarez's greatest achievements. Working
within the framework originally elaborated by Thomas Aquinas,
Suarez treated humanity as the subject of four different laws,
which together guide human beings toward the ends of which they are
capable. Suarez achieved a double objective in his systematic
account of moral activity. First, he examined and synthesized the
entire scholastic heritage of thinking on this topic, identifying
the key issues of debate and the key authors who had formulated the
different positions most incisively. Second, he went beyond this
heritage of authorities to present a new account of human moral
action and its relationship to the law.Treading a fine line between
those to whom moral directives are purely a matter of reason and
those to whom they are purely a matter of a commanding will, Suarez
attempted to show how both human reason and the command of the
lawgiver dictate the moral space of human action.The Liberty Fund
edition is a revised version of that prepared for the Carnegie
Endowment for International Peace by translators Gwladys L.
Williams, Ammi Brown, and John Waldron, with revisions by Henry
Davis, S. J.Francisco Suarez (1548-1617), a Jesuit priest, was
professor of theology at the University of Salamanca in
Spain.Annabel S. Brett is a Fellow, Tutor, and University Lecturer
in History at Gonville and Caius College, Cambridge.Knud Haakonssen
is Professor of Intellectual History at the University of Sussex,
England.
Die Studie, im Sinne der Intellectual History angelegt,
rekonstruiert und dokumentiert den originaren wie konzeptionellen
Beitrag Leo Loewenthals zur fruhen Kritischen Theorie, wie sie in
den 1930er Jahren von den engsten Mitarbeitern des Instituts fur
Sozialforschung - Max Horkheimer, Theodor W. Adorno, Herbert
Marcuse, Erich Fromm, Friedrich Pollock und Walter Benjamin -
entwickelt und in der Zeitschrift fur Sozialforschung publiziert
wurde. Als verantwortlicher Schriftleiter der Zeitschrift sicherte
Loewenthal dem hier gebotenen Forum fur kritische Sozialforschung
den Fortbestand auch in politisch schwierigen Zeiten. Diese
besondere Rolle Loewenthals schmalert nicht die Bedeutung seiner
theoretischen Beitrage zur Zeitschrift fur Sozialforschung, stehen
sie doch in enger inhaltlicher Beziehung zu den Arbeiten der
anderen Institutsmitglieder und waren wie diese fur die Entwicklung
der Kritischen Theorie unentbehrlich.
Die Beitrage dieses Bandes richten einen umfassenden,
interdisziplinaren Blick auf das Thema des Rationalen und des
Irrationalen im deutschen Sprachraum. Um dem Phanomen naher zu
kommen, werden die Ausdrucksformen dieses Begriffspaares vom
Mittelalter bis in die Gegenwart pluriperspektivisch
herausgearbeitet. Bemerkenswert ist die allgegenwartige Aktualitat
des Themas sowie dessen Vielfalt an Facetten, Bedeutungen und
Auswirkungen. Dabei fungiert das irrational Erscheinende oft als
dasjenige Element, das die Existenz des Rationalen uberhaupt erst
ermoeglicht. Dieses von Nachwuchswissenschaftlern getragene und
herausgegebene Projekt geht zuruck auf einen deutsch-franzoesischen
Workshop, der 2010 an der Universitat Strassburg stattgefunden hat
und die Wechselbeziehungen von Rationalitat und Irrationalitat zum
Thema hatte. Der vorliegende Band wird durch weitere Beitrage zu
diesem Thema erganzt.
The topic of certitude is much debated today. On one side,
commentators such as Charles Krauthammer urge us to achieve "moral
clarity." On the other, those like George Will contend that the
greatest present threat to civilization is an excess of certitude.
To address this uncomfortable debate, Susan Schreiner turns to the
intellectuals of early modern Europe, a period when thought was
still fluid and had not yet been reified into the form of
rationality demanded by the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
Schreiner argues that Europe in the sixteenth century was
preoccupied with concerns similar to ours; both the desire for
certainty - especially religious certainty - and warnings against
certainty permeated the earlier era. Digging beneath overt
theological and philosophical problems, she tackles the underlying
fears of the period as she addresses questions of salvation,
authority, the rise of skepticism, the outbreak of religious
violence, the discernment of spirits, and the ambiguous
relationship between appearance and reality. In her examination of
the history of theological polemics and debates (as well as other
genres), Schreiner sheds light on the repeated evaluation of
certainty and the recurring fear of deception. Among the texts she
draws on are Montaigne's Essays, the mystical writings of Teresa of
Avila, the works of Reformation fathers William of Occam, Luther,
Thomas Muntzer, and Thomas More; and the dramas of Shakespeare. The
result is not a book about theology, but rather about the way in
which the concern with certitude determined the theology, polemics
and literature of an age.
Almost all twentieth-century philosophy stresses the immanence of
death in human life-as drive (Freud), as the context of Being
(Heidegger), as the essence of our defining ethics (Levinas), or as
language (de Man, Blanchot). In Death's Following, John Limon makes
use of literary analysis (of Sebald, Bernhard, and Stoppard),
cultural analysis, and autobiography to argue that death is best
conceived as always transcendentally beyond ourselves, neither
immanent nor imminent. Adapting Kierkegaard's variations on the
theme of Abraham's near-sacrifice of Isaac while refocusing the
emphasis onto Isaac, Limon argues that death should be imagined as
if hiding at the end of an inexplicable journey to Moriah. The
point is not to evade or ignore death but to conceive it more
truly, repulsively, and pervasively in its camouflage: for example,
in jokes, in logical puzzles, in bowdlerized folk songs. The first
of Limon's two key concepts is adulthood: the prolonged anti-ritual
for experiencing the full distance on the look of death. His second
is dirtiness, as theorized in a Jewish joke, a logical exemplum,
and T. S. Eliot's "Ash Wednesday": In each case, unseen dirt on
foreheads suggests the invisibility of inferred death. Not
recognizing death immediately or admitting its immanence and
imminence is for Heidegger the defining characteristic of the
"they," humanity in its inauthentic social escapism. But Limon
vouches throughout for the mediocrity of the "they" in its dirty
and ludicrous adulthood. Mediocrity is the privileged position for
previewing death, in Limon's opinion: practice for being forgotten.
In refusing the call of twentieth-century philosophy to face death
courageously, Limon urges the ethical and aesthetic value of
mediocre anti-heroism.
On Power (De Potentia) is one of Aquinas's ''Disputed Questions''
(a systematic series of discussions of specific theological
topics). It is a text which anyone with a serious interest in
Aquinas's thinking will need to read. There is, however, no English
translation of the De Potentia currently in print. A translation
was published in 1932 under the auspices of the English Dominicans,
but is now only available on a CD of translations of Aquineas
coming from the InteLex Corporation. A new translation in book form
is therefore highly desirable. However, the De Potentia is a very
long work indeed (the 1932 translation fills three volumes), and a
full translation would be a difficult publishing proposition as
well as a challenge to any translator. Recognizing this fact, while
wishing to make a solid English version of the De Potentia
available, Fr. Richard Regan has produced this abridgement, which
passes over some of the full text while retaining what seems most
important when it comes to following the flow of Aquinas's thought.
The traditional way of understanding life, as a self-appropriating
and self-organizing process of not ceasing to exist, of taking care
of one's own hunger, is challenged by today's unprecedented
proliferation of discourses and techniques concerning the living
being. This challenge entails questioning the fundamental concepts
of metaphysical thinking, namely, time, finality, and, above all,
being. Garrido argues that today we are in a position to repeat
Nietzsche's assertion that there is no other representation of
"being" than that of "living." But in order to carry out this
deconstruction of ontology, we need to find new ways of asking
"What is life?"
In this study, Garrido establishes the basic elements of the
question concerning life through readings of Aristotle, Nietzsche,
Heidegger, and Derrida; through the discussion of scientific
breakthroughs in thermodynamics and evolutionary and developmental
biology; and through the reexamination of the notion of hunger in
both its metaphysical and its political implications.
This Handbook is intended to show the links between the philosophy
written in the Middle Ages and that being done today. Essays by
over twenty medieval specialists, who are also familiar with
contemporary discussions, explore areas in logic and philosophy of
language, metaphysics, epistemology, moral psychology ethics,
aesthetics, political philosophy and philosophy of religion. Each
topic has been chosen because it is of present philosophical
interest, but a more or less similar set of questions was also
discussed in the Middle Ages. No party-line has been set about the
extent of the similarity. Some writers (e.g. Panaccio on
Universals; Cesalli on States of Affairs) argue that there are the
closest continuities. Others (e.g. Thom on Logical Form; Pink on
Freedom of the Will) stress the differences. All, however, share
the aim of providing new analyses of medieval texts and of writing
in a manner that is clear and comprehensible to philosophers who
are not medieval specialists. The Handbook begins with eleven
chapters looking at the history of medieval philosophy period by
period, and region by region. They constitute the fullest, most
wide-ranging and up-to-date chronological survey of medieval
philosophy available. All four traditions - Greek, Latin, Islamic
and Jewish (in Arabic, and in Hebrew) - are considered, and the
Latin tradition is traced from late antiquity through to the
seventeenth century and beyond.
Die Beachtung, welche die Gattung Moralische Wochenschrift bisher
erfahren hat und aktuell erhalt, entspricht bei Weitem nicht ihrem
tatsachlichen Stellenwert in der Aufklarungsepoche als
Multiplikator und Katalysator aufklarerischer Ideen und
Schreibweisen. Die 19 Beitrage dieses Bandes untersuchen
exemplarisch bekanntere und bislang weitgehend unerforschte
Moralische Wochenschriften sowie ihnen nahe stehende Periodika aus
der Zeit zwischen 1720 und 1790. Die Aufsatze werfen nicht nur ein
neues Licht auf die anthropologische, philosophische, theologische,
padagogische, politische und asthetische Positionierung der
Zeitschriften innerhalb der Aufklarungsepoche, sondern zeigen auch
ihre narrativen Verfahren, ihr Verhaltnis zur
literarisch-kulturellen Tradition und zu den regionalen Spezifika
ihres Erscheinungsumfelds auf. Zudem machen sie auf Desiderate der
Wochenschriftenforschung und auf die Unhaltbarkeit weit
verbreiteter Vorurteile gegenuber der Gattung aufmerksam. Der Band
dokumentiert die Ergebnisse einer im Herbst 2011 an der Universitat
Heidelberg veranstalteten Tagung.
Daniel Schwartz examines the views on friendship of the great
medieval philosopher Thomas Aquinas. For Aquinas friendship is the
ideal type of relationship that rational beings should cultivate.
Schwartz argues that Aquinas fundamentally revises some of the main
features of Aristotle's paradigmatic account of friendship so as to
accommodate the case of friendship between radically unequal
beings: man and God. As a result, Aquinas presents a broader view
of friendship than Aristotle's, allowing for a higher extent of
disagreement. lack of mutual understanding, and inequality between
friends.
In this lecture course, Reiner Schurmann develops the idea that, in
between the spiritual Carolingian Renaissance and the secular
humanist Renaissance, there was a distinctive medieval Renaissance
connected with the rediscovery of Aristotle. Focusing on Thomas
Aquinas's ontology and epistemology, William of Ockham's
conceptualism, and Meister Eckhart's speculative mysticism,
Schurmann shows how thought began to break free from religion and
the hierarchies of the feudal, neo-Platonic order and devote its
attention to otherness and singularity. A crucial supplement to
Schurmann's magnum opus Broken Hegemonies, Neo-Aristotelianism and
the Medieval Renaissance will be essential reading for anyone
interested in the rise and fall of Western principles, and thus in
how to think and act today.
Studies of medieval Biblical interpretation usually focus on the
printed literature, neglecting the vast majority of relevant works.
Timothy Bellamah offers a groundbreaking examination of the
exegesis of William of Alton, a thirteenth-century Dominican regent
master at Paris whose commentaries have never previously appeared
in print.
As a near contemporary of Hugh of St. Cher, Bonaventure, Albert the
Great, and Thomas Aquinas, William was an important representative
of university exegesis at a time of rapidly changing methods and
remarkable intellectual development. His commentaries are valuable
resources for understanding Biblical study of the thirteenth
century, in the schoolroom and in the pulpit. Yet study of
William's work has been impeded by the dubious authenticity of
numerous commentaries questionably attributed to him over the
centuries.
Bellamah addresses these complex problems by unearthing evidence of
authorship in each commentary's style and methodology. This inquiry
employs the traits of William's commentaries as criteria for
constituting a list of works that can be reliably attributed to
him, which, in turn, provides a crucial basis for studying his
exegesis. William was a man of his time, but even more than his
contemporaries he was deeply interested in history and the literal
sense, which he understood to be the intention of Scripture's
authors, divine and human. He took a keen interest in Biblical
history and put to use a wide array of procedures for textual,
linguistic, and rhetorical analysis. At the same time, he remained
aware of the spiritual senses and the diverse elements of the
exegetical and theological tradition in which he stood.
Maimonides' Guide for the Perplexed is one of the most discussed
books in Jewish history. Over 800 years after the author's death it
remains disputed with readers seeking secret philosophical messages
behind its explicit teaching, a quest fueled partly by Maimonides'
own statement that certain parts of the Guide are based upon ideas
that conflict with other parts. Many who adhere to an 'esoteric'
reading of the Guide profess to find these contradictions in
Maimonides' metaphysical beliefs. Through close readings of the
Guide, this book addresses the major debates surrounding its secret
doctrine. It argues that perceived contradictions in Maimonides'
accounts of creation and divine attributes can be squared by paying
attention to the various ways in which he presented his arguments.
Furthermore, it shows how a coherent theological view can emerge
from the many layers of the Guide. But Maimonides' clear
declaration that certain matters must be hidden from the masses
cannot be ignored and the kind of inconsistency that is peculiar to
the Guide requires another explanation. It is found in the purpose
Maimonides assigns to the Guide scriptural exegesis. Ezekiel's
Account of the Chariot, treated in one of the most laconic sections
of the Guide, is the subject of the final chapters. They offer a
detailed exposition of Maimonides' interpretation, the deepest
''secret of the Torah, '' which, in Maimonides' works, shares its
name with metaphysics. By connecting the vision with currents in
the wider Islamic world, the chapters show how Maimonides devised a
new method of presentation in order to imitate scripture's
multi-layered manner of communication. He updated what he took to
be the correct interpretation of scripture by writing it in a work
appropriate for his own time and to do so he had to keep the
Torah's most hidden secrets.
This anthology provides a set of distinctive, influential views
that explore the mysteries of human nature from a variety of
perspectives. It can be read on its own, or in conjunction with
Joel Kupperman's text, Theories of Human Nature .
Robert Pasnau traces the developments of metaphysical thinking
through four rich but for the most part neglected centuries of
philosophy, running from the thirteenth century through to the
seventeenth. At no period in the history of philosophy, other than
perhaps our own, have metaphysical problems received the sort of
sustained attention they received during the later Middle Ages, and
never has a whole philosophical tradition come crashing down as
quickly and completely as did scholastic philosophy in the
seventeenth century. The thirty chapters work through various
fundamental metaphysical issues, sometimes focusing more on
scholastic thought, sometimes on the seventeenth century. Pasnau
begins with the first challenges to the classical scholasticism of
Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas, runs through prominent figures like
John Duns Scotus and William Ockham, and ends in the seventeenth
century, with the end of the first stage of developments in
post-scholastic philosophy: on the continent, with Descartes and
Gassendi, and in England, with Boyle and Locke.
If we are to distinguish mere non-being from that which is not, yet
may be, from that which was not, yet could have been, or from that
which will not be, yet could become, we are committed in some way
to grant being to possibilities. The possible is not actual; yet it
is not nothing. What then could it be? What ontological status
could it possess? In Contingency, Time, and Possibility: An Essay
on Aristotle and Duns Scotus, Pascal Massie opens these questions
by combining two approaches: First, an original inquiry that
analyses the notions of chance, fate, event, contradiction, and so
forth, and suggests that the distinction between potency and act
arises from a confrontation with the impossible. Second, a
historical inquiry that focuses on Aristotle and Duns Scotus, two
key figures contributing to a fundamental transformation in the
history of Western ontology; namely, the transition from a
metaphysics of nature (Aristotle) to a metaphysics of the will
(Scotus). In doing so, this book departs from the prevailing
interpretation of the history of modal logic according to which
Scotus rejected the principle of plenitude attributed to Aristotle
and replaced the ancient diachronic theory of possibilities with a
synchronic one, thereby contributing to a "possible world's
semantics." Rather, Massie argues that in its proper ontological
import, the question of possibility concerns the limit between
being and non-being and that this limit must be thought in terms of
temporality. With Scotus, however, a radical shift occurs.
Possibilities are understood in terms of will, creation,
omnipotence, and transcending freedom. As such, they belong to the
realm of what is supremely actual (i.e., superabundant activity).
What used to be understood as a lesser degree of being (the quasi
non-being of uninformed matter and mere possibilities) becomes the
mark of omnipotence.
Moses Maimonides (1137/38-1204), scholar, physician, and
philosopher, was the most influential Jewish thinker of the Middle
Ages. In this magisterial biography, Herbert Davidson provides an
exhaustive guide to Maimonides' life and works. After considering
Maimonides' upbringing and education, Davidson expounds all of his
many writings in exhaustive detail, with separate chapters on
rabbinic, philosophical, and medical texts. Moses Maimonides has
been recognized as the standard work on a towering figure of
Western intellectual history.
Archbishop of Canterbury from 1272 until his death in 1279, the
Dominican friar Robert Kildwardby has long been known primarily for
his participation in the Oxford Prohibitions of 1277, but his
contributions spread far wider. A central figure in the Late Middle
Ages, Kilwardby was one of the earliest commentators of the work of
Aristotle, as well as an unwavering proponent of Augustinian
thought and a believer of the plurality of forms. Although he was a
prominent thinker of the time, key areas of his philosophical
thought remain unexamined in contemporary scholarship. Jose Filipe
Silva here offers the first book-length analysis of Kilwardby's
full body of work, which is essential in understanding both the
reception of Aristotle in the Latin West and the developments of
later medieval philosophy. Beginning with his early philosophical
commitments, Silva tracks Kilwardby's life and academic thought,
including his theories on knowledge, moral happiness, and the
nature of the soul, along with his attempts to reconcile
Augustinian and Aristotelian thought. Ultimately, Robert Kilwardby
offers a comprehensive overview of an unsung scholar, solidifying
his philosophical legacy as one of the most influential authors of
the Late Middle Ages.
Nel suo pionieristico lavoro Conditions in Koenigsberg and the
Making of Kant's Philosophy, Giorgio Tonelli lamentava l'assenza di
un'indagine approfondita sul contesto intellettuale di Koenigsberg
e sull'eventuale influenza che esso esercito su alcuni aspetti del
pensiero di Kant. Questo libro vuole colmare questa lacuna
prestando particolare attenzione alla tradizione aristotelica, alla
Schulphilosophie, e alla corrente dell'eclettismo, che dominarono
l'ambiente regiomontano sino all'avvento della filosofia critica
kantiana. Il lavoro mostra come dai fallimenti dei progetti logici
e metafisici precritici, legati alle influenze ricevute
dall'ambiente di Koenigsberg, Kant abbia tratto le idee e gli
spunti per la stesura della Kritik der reinen Vernunft.
Born in Saxony in 1096, Hugh became an Augustinian monk and in 1115
moved to the monastery of Saint Victor, Paris, where he spent the
remainder of his life, eventually becoming the head of the school
there. His writings cover the whole range of arts and sacred
science taught in his day. Paul Rorem offers a basic introduction
to Hugh's theology, through a comprehensive survey of his works. He
argues that Hugh is best understood as a teacher of theology, and
that his numerous and varied writings are best appreciated as a
comprehensive pedagogical program of theological education and
spiritual formation. Drawing his evidence not only from Hugh's own
descriptions of his work but from the earliest manuscript
traditions of his writings, Rorem organizes and presents his corpus
within a tri-part framework. Upon a foundation of training in the
liberal arts and history, a structure of doctrine is built up,
which is finally adorned with moral formation. Within this scheme
of organization, Rorem treats each of Hugh's major works (and many
minor ones) in its appropriate place, orienting the reader briefly
yet accurately to its contents, as well as its location in Hugh's
overarching program of theological pedagogy.
|
|