|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Western philosophy, c 500 to c 1600
The rehabilitation of Confucian tradition raised new challenges to
Chinese feminist thinkers. Can a Confucian ideal of reciprocity
help women realize their equality? What is the hope for Chinese
women seeking a social ideal of equality given the growing gender
gap in the current economic development of China? Yuan argues
Confucianism cannot help unless it is integrated with feminism. In
this book, Yuan explores why gendered stratifications perpetuated
so deeply in today's China through the influences of Confucian
cultural tradition, but reading early Confucian texts as a
cosmological vision of Ren with Dao and ontological oneness as a
whole that is the unity of heaven, earth, and humanism, we might
reclaim Confucian egalitarian aspects to develop its openness for
gender equity with integration of feminist critical care ethics.
Throughout the book, Yuan provides multiple perspectives of
comparison: relational self vs. power differentials, gender roles
differences vs. political demand for equality, and individual
reciprocity vs. connection based reciprocity, etc. to embrace
inclusive methodology and caring democracy. We see a great hope to
break through stereotypes of binary thinking of Minben (people
oriented) and Minzhu (autonomous democracy), gender division of
labor, reason and emotion, etc. Yuan argues we should integrate
feminist critical thoughts of global justice/care with early
Confucianism, since both traditions emphasize caring relationships
in humanity and interdependency between social individuals within
and beyond their communities in a global scale. Importantly, the
integration enlarges our philosophical visions of how cultural
traditions can be undeniable sources for strengthening contemporary
social ideas of humanity, democracy, equality, and freedom for all.
John Buridan was a fourteenth-century philosopher who enjoyed an
enormous reputation for about two hundred years, was then totally
neglected, and is now being 'rediscovered' through his relevance to
contemporary work in philosophical logic. The final chapter of
Buridan's Sophismata deals with problems about self-reference, and
in particular with the semantic paradoxes. He offers his own
distinctive solution to the well-known 'Liar Paradox' and
introduces a number of other paradoxes that will be unfamiliar to
most logicians. Buridan also moves on from these problems to more
general questions about the nature of propositions, the criteria of
their truth and falsity and the concepts of validity and knowledge.
This edition of that chapter is intended to make Buridan's ideas
and arguments accessible to a wider range of readers. The volume
should interest many philosophers, linguists and logicians, who are
increasingly finding in medieval work striking anticipations of
their own concerns.
The Renaissance is one of the most celebrated periods in European
history. But when did it begin? When did it end? And what did it
include? Traditionally regarded as a revival of classical art and
learning, centred upon fifteenth-century Italy, views of the
Renaissance have changed considerably in recent decades. The
glories of Florence and the art of Raphael and Michelangelo remain
an important element of the Renaissance story, but they are now
only a part of a much wider story which looks beyond an exclusive
focus on high culture, beyond the Italian peninsula, and beyond the
fifteenth century. The Oxford Illustrated History of the
Renaissance tells the cultural history of this broader and longer
Renaissance: from seminal figures such as Dante and Giotto in
thirteenth-century Italy, to the waning of Spain's 'golden age' in
the 1630s, and the closure of the English theatres in 1642, the
date generally taken to mark the end of the English literary
Renaissance. Geographically, the story ranges from Spanish America
to Renaissance Europe's encounter with the Ottomans-and far beyond,
to the more distant cultures of China and Japan. And thematically,
under Gordon Campbell's expert editorial guidance, the volume
covers the whole gamut of Renaissance civilization, with chapters
on humanism and the classical tradition; war and the state;
religion; art and architecture; the performing arts; literature;
craft and technology; science and medicine; and travel and cultural
exchange.
A timely examination of the ways in which sixteenth-century
understandings of the world were framed by classical theory. The
long sixteenth century saw a major shift in European geographical
understanding: in the space of little more than a hundred years
Western Europeans moved to see the world as a place in which all
parts of the sphere were made by God for human exploitation and to
interact with one another. Taking such a scenario as its historical
backdrop, Framing the Early Modern World examines the influence of
Greek and Roman ideas on the formulation of new geographical
theories in sixteenth-century western Europe. While discussions of
inhabitability dominate the geographical literature throughout the
sixteenth century, humanist geographers of the sixteenth century,
trained in Greek and Roman writings, found in them the key
intellectual tools which allowed the oikoumene (the habitable
world) to be redefined as a globally-connected world. In this
world, all parts of the sphere were designed to be in communication
with one another. The coincidence of the Renaissance and the period
of European exploration enabled a new geographical understanding
fashioned as much by classical theory as by early modern empirical
knowledge. Newly discovered lands could then be defined, exploited
and colonized. In this way, the author argues, the seeds of the
modern era of colonization, expansionism and ultimately
globalization were sown. Framing the Early Modern World is a timely
work, contributing to a growing discourse on the origins of
globalization and the roots of modernity.
The three early descriptions of analytic action theory sharethe
fundamental premise that physical behavior is characterized as
intentional action by semantic rather than physical features. Hart,
Anscombe, and Melden each cite essential conditions for the
possibility of attributing actions. Their concepts can be
integrated into a model of action whose emphasis lies on the social
dimension of understanding action.
This book takes a fresh look at two of the most controversial
topics in Hobbes's philosophy: morality and sovereignty. It
distinguishes between the two versions of the covenant provided by
Hobbes, one of which establishes a genuine system or morality based
on the golden rule and the other which justifies the absolute power
of the sovereign. The author defends the moral theory through an
examination of the various alternatives, and the theory of
sovereignty by testing it against historical experience.
Henry Sidgwick's The Methods of Ethics has been a central part of
the utilitarian canon since its publication in 1874. This book,
part of the Oxford Guides to Philosophy series, is a consice
companion to Sidgwick's masterpiece, written primarily to aid
advanced undergraduate students and interested general readers in
navigatiing and interpreting the original text. Author David
Phillips connects Sidgwick's work to work in contemporary moral
philosophy and in the history of moral philosophy, paying
particular attention to his relationships with key predecessors,
including Kant and Mill, and with Moore and Ross, his most
influencial successors in the British intuitionist tradition. The
book's first eight chapters end with brief suggestions for further
reading. At the end of the final three chapters there are more
substantial overviews of the secondary literature on the aspects of
Sidgwick's work that have generated the most interest among his
commentators: metaethics and moral epistemology; consequentialism
versus deontology; and egoism and the dualism of practical reason.
The result is an Oxford Guide that will be a helpful resource for
both students and scholars.
Written by a team of leading international scholars, this crucial
period of philosophy is examined from the novel perspective of
themes and lines of thought which cut across authors, disciplines
and national boundaries. This fresh approach will open up new ways
for specialists and students to conceptualise the history of
medieval and Renaissance thought within philosophy, politics,
religious studies and literature. The essays cover concepts and
topics that have become central in the continental tradition. They
also bring major philosophers - Thomas Aquinas, Averroes,
Maimonides and Duns Scotus - into conversation with those not
usually considered canonical - Nicholas of Cusa, Marsilius of
Padua, Gersonides and Moses Almosnino. Medieval and Renaissance
thought is approached with contemporary continental philosophy in
view, highlighting the continued richness and relevance of the work
from this period.
aspirations, the rise of western monasticism was the most note
worthy event of the early centuries. The importance of monasteries
cannot be overstressed as sources of spirituality, learning and
auto nomy in the intensely masculinized, militarized feudal period.
Drawing their members from the highest levels of society, women's
monasteries provided an outlet for the energy and ambition of
strong-willed women, as well as positions of considerable
authority. Even from periods relatively inhospitable to learning of
all kinds, the memory has been preserved of a good number of women
of education. Their often considerable achievements and influence,
however, generally lie outside even an expanded definition of philo
sophy. Among the most notable foremothers of this early period were
several whose efforts signal the possibility of later philosophical
work. Radegund, in the sixth century, established one of the first
Frankish convents, thereby laying the foundations for women's
spiritual and intellectual development. From these beginnings,
women's monasteries increased rapidly in both number and in fluence
both on the continent and in Anglo-Saxon England. Hilda (d. 680) is
well known as the powerful abbsess of the double monastery of
Whitby. She was eager for knowledge, and five Eng lish bishops were
educated under her tutelage. She is also accounted the patron of
Caedmon, the first Anglo-Saxon poet of religious verse. The
Anglo-Saxon nun Lioba was versed in the liberal arts as well as
Scripture and canon law."
This volume presents fourteen of William E. Mann's essays on three
prominent figures in late Patristic and early medieval philosophy:
Augustine, Anselm, and Peter Abelard. The essays explore some of
the quandaries, arguments, and theories presented in their
writings. The essays in this volume complement those to be found in
Mann's God, Modality, and Morality (OUP, 2015). While the essays in
God, Modality, and Morality are primarily essays in philosophical
theology, those found in the present volume are more varied. Some
still deal with issues in philosophical theology. Other essays are
aporetic in nature, discussing cases of philosophical perplexity,
sometimes but not always leaving the cases unresolved. All the
essays display, directly or indirectly, the philosophical influence
that Augustine has had. His Confessions is a rich source for
philosophical puzzlement. Individual essays examine his reflections
on the alleged innocence of infants, which raises questions about
cognitive, emotional, and linguistic development; his juvenile
theft of pears and its relation to moral motivation; and his
struggle with and resolution of the problem of evil. One essay
presents the rudiments of an Augustinian moral theory, rooted in
his understanding of the Sermon on the Mount. Another essay
illustrates the theory by discussing his writings on lying. Mann
argues that Abelard amplified Augustine's moral theory by
emphasizing the crucial role that intention plays in wrongdoing.
Augustine bequeathed to Anselm the notion of "faith seeking
understanding. " Mann argues that this methodological slogan shapes
Anselm's "ontological argument " for God's existence and his
efforts to explicate the doctrine of the Trinity.
The introduction of Greek philosophy into the Muslim world left an indelible mark on Islamic intellectual history. Philosophical discourse became a constant element in even traditionalist Islamic sciences. However, Aristotelian metaphysics gave rise to doctrines about God and the universe that were found highly objectionable by a number of Muslim theologians, among whom the fourteenth-century scholar Ibn Taymiyya stood foremost. Ibn Taymiyya, one of the greatest and most prolific thinkers in medieval Islam, held Greek logic responsible for the `heretical' metaphysical conclusions reached by Islamic philosophers, theologians, mystics, and others. He therefore set out to refute philosophical logic, a task which culminated in one of the most devastating attacks ever levelled against the logical system upheld by the early Greeks, the later commentators, and their Muslim followers. His argument is grounded in an empirical approach that in many respects prefigures the philosophies of the British empiricists. Professor Hallaq's translation, with a substantial introduction and extensive notes, makes this important work available to a wider audience for the first time.
In der Philosophie des spaten 13. Jahrhunderts stellt die
thomasische Lehre von der Selbstbewegung des Willens einen
originellen Versuch dar, die christliche Uberzeugung von der
menschlichen Willenfreiheit den Prinzipien der aristotelischen
Psychologie theoretisch anzupassen. Sie gilt auch als ein Beweis
fur die geistige Offenheit des Thomas, da sie wesentlich bestimmt
ist durch die aktive und ernsthafte Auseinandersetzung mit den
zeitgenossischen voluntaristischen Antagonisten. Yul Kim erortert
in seinem Buch die Bedeutung dieser Lehre mit Blick auf die
Entwicklung der thomasischen Willenstheorie und rekonstruiert den,
von polemischen Debatten gekennzeichneten, geistigen Kontext, aus
dem diese Lehre entstand."
ein wichtiges Anliegen der grossen Konzilien des Spatmittelalters
war die Reform des monastischen Lebens. Ausgehend von der
italienischen Benediktinerabtei Subiaco fanden diese Bestrebungen
besonders in den deutschsprachigen Klostern ein breites Echo. Es
bildeten sich Reformzentren heraus (Melk, Tegernsee, St. Gallen),
in denen die Benedikt-Regel eine neue spirituelle und kulturelle
Kraft entfaltete."
The relationship between the Late Middle Ages and the beginning of
modern times is still acontroversial topic discussed. Some view the
14th and 15th century as a period of decline, others emphasize this
era's formative and innovative role in modern times. Volume 31 of
Miscellanea Mediaevalia takes an interdisciplinary look at this
period while addressing critical, classic evaluations. More than 30
contributions discuss the philosophy of the Late Middle Ages (with
special attention to moral and natural philosophy), scientific
institutions of the Late Middle Ages, the architecture, economic
and legal history, and the spirituality in the Late Middle Ages, as
well as prominent figures such as Jean Gerson and Nicholasof Cusa.
The last twenty years have seen remarkable developments in our
understanding of how the ancient Greek thinkers handled the general
concept of being and its several varieties. The most general
examination of the meaning of the Greek verb 'esti'/'einai'/'on'
both in common usage and in the philosophical literature has been
presented by Charles H. Kahn, most extensively in his 1973 book The
Verb 'Be' in Ancient Greek. These discussions are summarized in
Kahn's contribution to this volume. By and large, they show that
conceptual schemes by means of which philosophers have recently
approached Greek thought have not been very well suited to the way
the concept of being was actually used by the ancients. For one
thing, being in the sense of existence played a very small role in
Greek thinking according to Kahn. Even more importantly, Kahn has
argued that Frege and Russell's thesis that verbs for being, such
as 'esti', are multiply ambiguous is ill suited for the purpose of
appreciating the actual conceptual assumptions of the Greek
thinkers. Frege and Russell claimed that a verb like 'is' or'esti'
is ambiguous between the 'is' of identity, the 'is' of existence,
the copulative 'is', and the generic 'is' (the 'is' of
class-inclusion). At least a couple of generations of scholars have
relied on this thesis and fre quently criticized sundry ancients
for confusing these different senses of 'esti' with each other."
Surveys philosophy from the neo-Platonists to St. Anselm, showing how Greek philosophy took the form in which it was known to its cultural inheritors and how they interpreted it.
|
You may like...
Meditations
Marcus Aurelius
Hardcover
R618
Discovery Miles 6 180
The Antichrist
Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche
Hardcover
R548
Discovery Miles 5 480
|