|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500 > General
Plato’s Timaeus is unique in Greek Antiquity for presenting the
creation of the world as the work of a divine demiurge. The maker
bestows order on sensible things and imitates the world of the
intellect by using the Forms as models. While the creation-myth of
the Timaeus seems unparalleled, this book argues that it is not the
first of Plato’s dialogues to use artistic language to articulate
the relationship of the objects of the material world to the world
of the intellect. The book adopts an interpretative angle that is
sensitive to the visual and art-historical developments of
Classical Athens to argue that sculpture, revolutionized by the
advent of the lost-wax technique for the production of bronze
statues, lies at the heart of Plato’s conception of the relation
of the human soul and body to the Forms. It shows that, despite the
severe criticism of mimēsis in the Republic, Plato’s use of
artistic language rests on a positive model of mimēsis. Plato was
in fact engaged in a constructive dialogue with material culture
and he found in the technical processes and the cultural semantics
of sculpture and of the art of weaving a valuable way to
conceptualise and communicate complex ideas about humans’
relation to the Forms.
The awe with which Plato regarded the character of 'the great'
Parmenides has extended to the dialogue which he calls by his name.
None of the writings of Plato have been more copiously illustrated,
both in ancient and modern times, and in none of them have the
interpreters been more at variance with one another. Nor is this
surprising. For the Parmenides is more fragmentary and isolated
than any other dialogue, and the design of the writer is not
expressly stated. The date is uncertain; the relation to the other
writings of Plato is also uncertain; the connexion between the two
parts is at first sight extremely obscure; and in the latter of the
two we are left in doubt as to whether Plato is speaking his own
sentiments by the lips of Parmenides, and overthrowing him out of
his own mouth, or whether he is propounding consequences which
would have been admitted by Zeno and Parmenides themselves. The
contradictions which follow from the hypotheses of the one and many
have been regarded by some as transcendental mysteries; by others
as a mere illustration, taken at random, of a new method. They seem
to have been inspired by a sort of dialectical frenzy, such as may
be supposed to have prevailed in the Megarian School (compare
Cratylus, etc.). The criticism on his own doctrine of Ideas has
also been considered, not as a real criticism, but as an exuberance
of the metaphysical imagination which enabled Plato to go beyond
himself.
In this important and highly original book, place, commonality and
judgment provide the framework within which works central to the
Greek philosophical and literary tradition are usefully located and
reinterpreted. Greek life, it can be argued, was defined by the
interconnection of place, commonality and judgment. Similarly
within the Continental philosophical tradition topics such as
place, judgment, law and commonality have had a pervasive
centrality. Works by Jacques Derrida and Giorgio Agamben amongst
others attest to the current exigency of these topics. Yet the ways
in which they are interrelated has been barely discussed within the
context of Ancient Philosophy. The conjecture of this book is that
not only are these terms of genuine philosophical importance in
their own right, but they are also central to Ancient Philosophy.
Andrew Benjamin ultimately therefore aims to underscore the
relevance of Ancient Philosophy for contemporary debates in
Continental Philosophy.
In several of the dialogues of Plato, doubts have arisen among his
interpreters as to which of the various subjects discussed in them
is the main thesis. The speakers have the freedom of conversation;
no severe rules of art restrict them, and sometimes we are inclined
to think, with one of the dramatis personae in the Theaetetus, that
the digressions have the greater interest. Yet in the most
irregular of the dialogues there is also a certain natural growth
or unity; the beginning is not forgotten at the end, and numerous
allusions and references are interspersed, which form the loose
connecting links of the whole. We must not neglect this unity, but
neither must we attempt to confine the Platonic dialogue on the
Procrustean bed of a single idea. (Compare Introduction to the
Phaedrus.) Two tendencies seem to have beset the interpreters of
Plato in this matter. First, they have endeavoured to hang the
dia-logues upon one another by the slightest threads; and have thus
been led to opposite and contradictory assertions respec-ting their
order and sequence. The mantle of Schleiermacher has descended upon
his successors, who have applied his method with the most various
results.
The Cratylus has always been a source of perplexity to the student
of Plato. While in fancy and humour, and perfection of style and
metaphysical originality, this dialogue may be ranked with the best
of the Platonic writings, there has been an uncertainty about the
motive of the piece, which interpreters have hitherto not succeeded
in dispelling. We need not suppose that Plato used words in order
to conceal his thoughts, or that he would have been unintelligible
to an educated contemporary. In the Phaedrus and Euthydemus we also
find a difficulty in determining the precise aim of the author.
Plato wrote satires in the form of dialogues, and his meaning, like
that of other satirical writers, has often slept in the ear of
posterity. Two causes may be assigned for this obscurity: 1st, the
subtlety and allusiveness of this species of composition; 2nd, the
difficulty of reproducing a state of life and literature which has
passed away. A satire is unmeaning unless we can place ourselves
back among the persons and thoughts of the age in which it was
written.
This book develops a new account of Socratic method, based on a
psychological model of Plato's dramatic depiction of Socrates'
character and conduct. Socratic method is seen as a blend of three
types of philosophical discourse: refutation, truth-seeking, and
persuasion. Cain focuses on the persuasive features of the method
since, in her view, it is this aspect of Socrates' method that best
explains the content and the value of the dialectical arguments.
Emphasizing the persuasive aspect of Socratic method helps us
uncover the operative standards of dialectical argumentation in
fifth-century Athens. Cain considers both the sophistic style of
rhetoric and contentious debate in Socrates' time, and Aristotle's
perspective on the techniques of argument and their purposes. An
informal, pragmatic analysis of argumentation appropriate to the
dialectical context is developed. We see that Socrates uses
ambiguity and other strategic fallacies with purposeful play, and
for moral ends. Taking specific examples of refutations from
Plato's dialogues, Cain links the interlocutors' characters and
situations with the dialectical argument that Socrates constructs
to refute them. The merit of this interpretation is that it gives
broad range, depth, and balance to Socrates' argumentative style;
it also maintains a keen sensitivity to the interlocutors'
emotional reactions, moral values, and attitudes. The book
concludes with a discussion of the overall value, purpose, and
success of Socratic method, and draws upon a Platonic/Socratic
conception of the soul and a dialectical type of self-knowledge.
This work offers a radical new interpretation of Augustine and of a
central aspect of medieval thought as a whole.Augustine and Roman
Virtue seeks to correct what the author sees as a fundamental
misapprehension in medieval thought, a misapprehension that fuels
further problems and misunderstandings in the historiography of
philosophy. This misapprehension is the assumption that the
development of certain themes associated with medieval philosophy
is due, primarily if not exclusively, to extra-philosophical
religious commitments rather than philosophical argumentation,
referred to here as the 'sacralization thesis'.Brian Harding
explores this problem through a detailed reading of Augustine's
"City of God" as understood in a Latin context, that is, in
dialogue with Latin writers, such as Cicero, Livy, Sallust and
Seneca. The book seeks to revise a common reading of Augustine's
critique of ancient virtue by focusing on that dialogue, while
showing that his attitude towards those authors is more
sympathetic, and more critical, than one might expect. Harding
argues that the criticisms rest on sympathy and that Augustine's
critique of ancient virtue thinks through and develops certain
trends noticeable in the major figures of Latin philosophy.
The Republic is a dialogue by Plato in which the famous Athenian
philosopher examines the nature of an ideal society. The insights
are profound and timeless. A landmark of Western literature, The
Republic is essential reading for philosophy students.
This volume presents collected essays - some brand new, some
republished, and others newly translated - on the ancient
commentators on Aristotle and showcases the leading research of the
last three decades. Through the work and scholarship inspired by
Richard Sorabji in his series of translations of the commentators
started in the 1980s, these ancient texts have become a key field
within ancient philosophy. Building on the strength of the series,
which has been hailed as 'a scholarly marvel', 'a truly
breath-taking achievement' and 'one of the great scholarly
achievements of our time' and on the widely praised edited volume
brought out in 1990 (Aristotle Transformed) this new book brings
together critical new scholarship that is a must-read for any
scholar in the field. With a wide range of contributors from across
the globe, the articles look at the commentators themselves,
discussing problems of analysis and interpretation that have arisen
through close study of the texts. Richard Sorabji introduces the
volume and himself contributes two new papers. A key recent area of
research has been into the Arabic, Latin and Hebrew versions of
texts, and several important essays look in depth at these. With
all text translated and transliterated, the volume is accessible to
readers without specialist knowledge of Greek or other languages,
and should reach a wide audience across the disciplines of
Philosophy, Classics and the study of ancient texts.
In this lively and original book, Russell Winslow pursues a new
interpretation of logos in Aristotle. Rather than a reading of
rationality that cleaves human beings from nature, this new
interpretation suggests that, for Aristotle, consistent and
dependable rational arguments reveal a deep dependency upon nature.
To this end, the author shows that a rational account of a being is
in fact subject to the very same principle that governs the
physical motion and generation of a being under inquiry. Among the
many consequences of this argument is a rejection of both of the
prevailing oppositional claims that Aristotle's methodological
procedure of discovery is one resting on either empirical or
conceptual grounds: discovery reveals a more complex structure than
can be grasped by either of these modern modes. Further, Winslow
argues that this interpretation of rational discovery also
contributes to the ethical debates surrounding Aristotle's work,
insofar as an ethical claim is achieved through reason, but is not
thereby conceived as objective. Again, the demand for agreement in
ethical/political decision will be disclosed as superseding in its
complexity both those accounts of ethical decision as subjective
(for example, "emotivist" accounts) and those as objective
("realist" accounts).
The Roman Emperor Marcus Aurelius wrote down his thoughts between
170 and 180. He was a late Stoic Philosopher and this one of the
few examples of this type of literature that exists today. The book
is written as personal notes to himself and his thesis is that one
can obtain inner calm irrespective of outer adversity. The text
considers good and evil, solidarity, adversity and inner freedom.
It is a book that offers wisdom, comfort and inspiration. As well
as the thought, this edition contains a biographical sketch and
summary of the philosophy of Marcus Aurelius, a number of
illustrations and both an index and index of terms.
The magnum opus of Plato's writings that detail out the utopia that
Socrates had thought of when debating with his contemporaries in
ancient Greece. While many people have criticized these views over
the years, these ideas have sparked many ideas of what makes
government work and what does not as well as laying down the
foundations for our own democratic systems in the present day.
Socrates has many things to say about people and society in general
making it a very enlightening piece of work.
The work of Aristotle (384-322 BC) is considered to be one of the
great achievements of the ancient world, and is a foundation of
both Western and Middle Eastern philosophy and science. Although
Aristotle left significant material on almost all branches of
learning, what has survived is a somewhat disorganized collection
of notes and lectures. Moreover, the centuries of interpretation
across various epochs and cultures tend to cloud our understanding
of him. Thomas Kiefer breaks through this cloud of interpretation
and provides an organized account of one key part of Aristotle's
philosophy, namely his theory of knowledge. This theory concerns
what is knowledge, what we can know, and how we can do so. Kiefer's
book is the first work that takes this theory as its sole focus and
reconstructs it systematically. Kiefer's work throughout provides
many new interpretations of key parts of Aristotle's philosophy,
including an unnoticed -but crucial-distinction between knowledge
in general and knowledge for us, the differences between his
semantic and psychological requirements for knowledge, and 'nous',
which is perhaps the most obscure notion in Aristotle's work. He
also concludes with a summary of Aristotle's theory in the terms
and style of contemporary epistemology. Kiefer's work should be of
interest to anyone involved in the history of philosophy or
contemporary epistemology.
|
|