|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500 > General
Aristotle's Topics is a handbook for dialectic, which can be
understood as a philosophical debate between a questioner and a
respondent. In book 2, Aristotle mainly develops strategies for
making deductions about 'accidents', which are properties that
might or might not belong to a subject (for instance, Socrates has
five fingers, but might have had six), and about properties that
simply belong to a subject without further specification. In the
present commentary, here translated into English for the first
time, Alexander develops a careful study of Aristotle's text. He
preserves objections and replies from other philosophers whose work
is now lost, such as the Stoics. He also offers an invaluable
picture of the tradition of Aristotelian logic down to his time,
including innovative attempts to unify Aristotle's guidance for
dialectic with his general theory of deductive argument (the
syllogism), found in the Analytics. The work will be of interest
not only for its perspective on ancient logic, rhetoric, and
debate, but also for its continuing influence on argument in the
Middle Ages and later.
This book argues against the common view that there are no
essential differences between Plato and the Neoplatonist
philosopher, Plotinus, on the issues of mysticism, epistemology,
and ethics. Beginning by examining the ways in which Plato and
Plotinus claim that it is possible to have an ultimate experience
that answers the most significant philosophical questions, David J.
Yount provides an extended analysis of why we should interpret both
philosophers as mystics. The book then moves on to demonstrate that
both philosophers share a belief in non-discursive knowledge and
the methods to attain it, including dialectic and recollection, and
shows that they do not essentially differ on any significant views
on ethics. Making extensive use of primary and secondary sources,
Plato and Plotinus on Mysticism, Epistemology and Ethics shows the
similarities between the thought of these two philosophers on a
variety of philosophical questions, such as meditation, divination,
wisdom, knowledge, truth, happiness and love.
This volume explores the conceptual terrain defined by the Greek
word eikos: the probable, likely, or reasonable. A term of art in
Greek rhetoric, a defining feature of literary fiction, a seminal
mode of historical, scientific, and philosophical inquiry, eikos
was a way of thinking about the probable and improbable, the
factual and counterfactual, the hypothetical and the real. These
thirteen original and provocative essays examine the plausible
arguments of courtroom speakers and the 'likely stories' of
philosophers, verisimilitude in art and literature, the likelihood
of resemblance in human reproduction, the limits of human knowledge
and the possibilities of ethical and political agency. The first
synthetic study of probabilistic thinking in ancient Greece, the
volume illuminates a fascinating chapter in the history of Western
thought.
Greek tragedy occupies a prominent place in the development of
early Greek thought. However, even within the partial renaissance
of debates about tragedy's roots in the popular thought of archaic
Greece, its potential connection to the early philosophical
tradition remains, with few exceptions, at the periphery of current
interest. This book aims to show that our understanding of
Aeschylus' Oresteia is enhanced by seeing that the trilogy's
treatment of Zeus and Justice (Dike) shares certain concepts,
assumptions, categories of thought, and forms of expression with
the surviving fragments and doxography of certain Presocratic
thinkers (especially Anaximander, Xenophanes, Heraclitus, and
Parmenides). By examining several aspects of the tragic trilogy in
relation to Presocratic debates about theology and cosmic justice,
it shows how such scrutiny may affect our understanding of the
theological 'tension' and metaphysical assumptions underpinning the
Oresteia's dramatic narrative. Ultimately, it argues that Aeschylus
bestows on the experience of human suffering, as it is given in the
contradictory multiplicity of the world, the status of a profound
form of knowledge: a meeting point between the human and divine
spheres.
This book argues that, rather than being conceived merely as a
hindrance, the body contributes constructively in the fashioning of
a Platonic unified self. The Phaedo shows awareness that the
indeterminacy inherent in the body infects the validity of any
scientific argument but also provides the subject of inquiry with
the ability to actualize, to the extent possible, the ideal self.
The Republic locates bodily desires and needs in the tripartite
soul. Achievement of maximal unity is dependent upon successful
training of the rational part of the soul, but the earlier
curriculum of Books 2 and 3, which aims at instilling a
pre-reflectively virtuous disposition in the lower parts of the
soul, is a prerequisite for the advanced studies of Republic 7. In
the Timaeus, the world soul is fashioned out of Being, Sameness,
and Difference: an examination of the Sophist and the Parmenides
reveals that Difference is to be identified with the Timaeus'
Receptacle, the third ontological principle which emerges as the
quasi-material component that provides each individual soul with
the alloplastic capacity for psychological growth and alteration.
This book presents a thorough study and an up to date anthology of
Plato's Protagoras. International authors' papers contribute to the
task of understanding how Plato introduced and negotiated a new
type of intellectual practice - called philosophy - and the
strategies that this involved. They explore Plato's dialogue,
looking at questions of how philosophy and sophistry relate, both
on a methodological and on a thematic level. While many of the
contributing authors argue for a sharp distinction between
sophistry and philosophy, this is contested by others. Readers may
consider the distinctions between philosophy and traditional forms
of poetry and sophistry through these papers. Questions for
readers' attention include: To what extent is Socrates' preferred
mode of discourse, and his short questions and answers, superior to
Protagoras' method of sophistic teaching? And why does Plato make
Socrates and Protagoras reverse positions as it comes to virtue and
its teachability? This book will appeal to graduates and
researchers with an interest in the origins of philosophy,
classical philosophy and historical philosophy.
How to live a better life. One of the most important books on Western philosophy - a powerful and inspirational guide for the complicated world of today
Few ancient works have been as influential as the MEDITATIONS of Marcus Aurelius. Filled with wisdom, practical guidance, and profound understanding of human behaviour, it remains one of the greatest works of spiritual and ethical reflection ever written. Marcus's insights and advice - on everything from living in the world to coping with adversity and interacting with others - have made the MEDITATIONS required reading for statesmen and philosophers alike, while generations of ordinary readers have responded to the straightforward intimacy of his style.
In Gregory Hays's translation Marcus's thoughts speak with a new immediacy. Never before have Marcus's insights been so directly and powerfully presented.
A new approach to understanding the relationship between
Aristotle's political philosophy and the natural law tradition.
"Aristotle and Natural Law" offers an important new examination of
Aristotle's political thought and its relationship to the natural
law tradition. The book challenges recent alternative
interpretations of Aristotle and argues that Aristotle's ethics is
most usefully seen as a particular type of natural law theory. Tony
Burns shows that the type of natural law theory to which Aristotle
subscribes is an unusual one because it does not allow for the
possibility that individuals might appeal to natural law in order
to critically evaluate existing laws and institutions. Rather its
function is to provide legitimacy for existing laws and conventions
by providing them with a philosophical justification from the
standpoint of Aristotle's metaphysics. Burns claims that this way
of thinking about natural law can be traced in the writings of a
number of thinkers in the history of philosophy, from Aquinas
through to Hegel, but argues that because this tradition begins
with Aristotle it is appropriate to describe it as 'the
Aristotelian natural law tradition'. "Continuum Studies in Ancient
Philosophy" presents cutting edge scholarship in the history of
ancient philosophy. The wholly original arguments, perspectives and
research findings in titles in this series make it an important and
stimulating resource for students and academics from across the
fields of Philosophy and Classical Studies.
Chinese and Greek ethics remain influential in modern philosophy,
yet it is unclear how they can be compared to one another. This
volume, following its predecssor 'How should one live?' (DeGruyter
2011), is a contribution to comparative ethics, loosely centered on
the concepts of life and the good life. Methods of comparing ethics
are treated in three introductory chapters (R.A.H.King, Ralph
Weber, G.E.R. Lloyd), followed by chapters on core issues in each
of the traditions: human nature (David Wong, Guo Yi), ghosts (Paul
Goldin), happiness (Christoph Harbsmeier), pleasure (Michael
Nylan), qi (Elisabeth Hsu & Zhang Ruqing), cosmic life and
individual life (Dennis Schilling), the concept of mind (William
Charlton), knowledge and happiness (Joerg Hardy), filial piety
(Richard Stalley), the soul (Hua-kuei Ho), and deliberation (Thomas
Buchheim). The volume closes with three essays in comparison -
Mencius and the Stoics (R.A.H. King), equanimity (Lee Yearley),
autonomy and the good life (Lisa Raphals). An index locorum each
for Chinese and Greco-Roman authors, and a general index complete
the volume.
Lucretius' philosophical epic De Rerum Natura (On the Nature of
Things) is a lengthy didactic and narrative celebration of the
universe and, in particular, the world of nature and creation in
which humanity finds its abode. This earliest surviving full scale
epic poem from ancient Rome was of immense influence and
significance to the development of the Latin epic tradition, and
continues to challenge and haunt its readers to the present day. A
Reading of Lucretius' De Rerum Natura offers a comprehensive
commentary on this great work of Roman poetry and philosophy. Lee
Fratantuono reveals Lucretius to be a poet with deep and abiding
interest in the nature of the Roman identity as the children of
both Venus (through Aeneas) and Mars (through Romulus); the
consequences (both positive and negative) of descent from the
immortal powers of love and war are explored in vivid epic
narrative, as the poet progresses from his invocation to the mother
of the children of Aeneas through to the burning funeral pyres of
the plague at Athens. Lucretius' epic offers the possibility of
serenity and peaceful reflection on the mysteries of the nature of
the world, even as it shatters any hope of immortality through its
bleak vision of post mortem oblivion. And in the process of
defining what it means both to be human and Roman, Lucretius offers
a horrifying vision of the perils of excessive devotion both to the
gods and our fellow men, a commentary on the nature of pietas that
would serve as a warning for Virgil in his later depiction of the
Trojan Aeneas.
Plotinus' mysticism of henosis, unification with the One, is a
highly controversial topic in Plotinian scholarship. This book
presents a careful reading of the Enneads and suggests that
Plotinus' mysticism be understood as mystical teaching that offers
practical guidance concerning henosis. It is further argued that a
rational interpretation thereof should be based on Plotinus'
metaphysics, according to which the One transcends all beings but
is immanent in them. The main thesis of this book is that Plotinus'
mystical teaching does not help man attain henosis on his own, but
serves to remind man that he fails to attain henosis because it
already pertains to his original condition. Plotinus' mysticism
seeks to change man's misconception about henosis, rather than his
finite nature.
This is the only commentary on Aristotle's theological work,
Metaphysics, Book 12, to survive from the first six centuries CE -
the heyday of ancient Greek commentary on Aristotle. Though the
Greek text itself is lost, a full English translation is presented
here for the first time, based on Arabic versions of the Greek and
a Hebrew version of the Arabic. In his commentary Themistius offers
an extensive re-working of Aristotle, confirming that the first
principle of the universe is indeed Aristotle's God as intellect,
not the intelligibles thought by God. The identity of intellect
with intelligibles had been omitted by Aristotle in Metaphysics 12,
but is suggested in his Physics 3.3 and On the Soul 3, and later by
Plotinus. Laid out here in an accessible translation and
accompanied by extensive commentary notes, introduction and
indexes, the work will be of interest for students and scholars of
Neoplatonist philosophy, ancient metaphysics, and textual
transmission.
This book combines the mainstream liberal arguments for religious
tolerance with arguments from religious traditions in India to
offer insights into appropriate attitudes toward religious 'others'
from the perspective of the devout. The respective chapters address
the relationship between religions from a comparative perspective,
helping readers understand the meaning of religion and the
opportunities for interreligious dialogue in the works of
contemporary Indian philosophers such as Gandhi and Ramakrishna
Paramhansa. It also examines various religious traditions from a
philosophical viewpoint in order to reassess religious discussions
on how to respond to differing and different religious others.
Given its comprehensive coverage, the book is of interest to
scholars working in the areas of anthropology, philosophy, cultural
and religious diversity, and history of religion.
Confronting the scientific revolution's dismissal of Aristotle's
physics and epistemology, Nathan R. Colaner revives this
foundational philosopher's work to expose within it the
underpinnings of modern philosophers' most common intuitions about
knowledge. After Aristotle's picture of reality had been judged
obsolete by the physics of the scientific revolution, modern
Western epistemologists fumbled along with doctrines that had
little to do with everyday life. These included Descartes' notion
of the evil genius, Hume's claim that we can't know anything that
we are not presently observing, and Kant's rescue of knowledge in
the context of idealism. In Aristotle on Knowledge of Nature and
Modern Skepticism, Colaner articulates a notion of knowledge that
is characteristically Aristotelian without being dependent on his
metaphysics. Simultaneously, Colaner places Aristotle in dialogue
with modern thinkers to create a bridge between classical and
modern philosophy and reinstate Aristotle's prominence in the
discipline of epistemology.
|
You may like...
Gloria
Sam Smith
CD
R187
R167
Discovery Miles 1 670
Holy Fvck
Demi Lovato
CD
R414
Discovery Miles 4 140
Higher Truth
Chris Cornell
CD
(1)
R143
Discovery Miles 1 430
Show Your Bones
Yeah Yeah Yeahs, Squeak E. Clean, …
CD
(1)
R57
Discovery Miles 570
|