|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Western philosophy, c 500 to c 1600 > General
In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle suggests that a moral
principle 'does not immediately appear to the man who has been
corrupted by pleasure or pain'. Phantasia in Aristotle's Ethics
investigates his claim and its reception in ancient and medieval
Aristotelian traditions, including Arabic, Greek, Hebrew and Latin.
While contemporary commentators on the Ethics have overlooked
Aristotle's remark, his ancient and medieval interpreters made
substantial contributions towards a clarification of the claim's
meaning and relevance. Even when the hazards of transmission have
left no explicit comments on this particular passage, as is the
case in the Arabic tradition, medieval responders still offer
valuable interpretations of phantasia (appearance) and its role in
ethical deliberation and action. This volume casts light on these
readings, showing how the distant voices from the medieval Arabic,
Greek, Hebrew and Latin Aristotelian traditions still contribute to
contemporary debate concerning phantasia, motivation and
deliberation in Aristotle's Ethics.
By far the best collection of sources to introduce readers to
Renaissance humanism in all its many guises. What distinguishes
this stimulating and useful anthology is the vision behind it: King
shows that Renaissance thinkers had a lot to say, not only about
the ancient world--one of their habitual passions--but also about
the self, how civic experience was configured, the arts, the roles
and contributions of women, the new science, the 'new' world, and
so much more. --Christopher S. Celenza, Johns Hopkins University
Der vorliegende Husserliana-Band enthalt Texte zu "Wahrnehmung
und Aufmerksamkeit" aus den Jahren von etwa 1893 bis 1912. Als
erster Text kommen Teile aus Husserls Vorlesung des Wintersemesters
1904/05 "Hauptstucke aus der Phanomenologie und Theorie der
Erkenntnis" zur Veroffentlichung, in denen Husserl gegenuber den
Logischen Untersuchungen zu einer eigenstandigeren und wesentlich
differenzierteren Untersuchung der Wahrnehmung ansetzt, die im
Sinne einer Theorie bzw. Phanomenologie der Erfahrung - sozusagen
einer Phanomenologie von unten - zunachst ganz unter Absehung von
bedeutungstheoretischen oder logischen Fragestellungen entwickelt
wird. Zur Vorbereitung dieser Vorlesung hat Husserl auf
Abhandlungen zuruckgegriffen, die aus dem Jahr 1898 stammen und die
vermutlich ursprunglich fur eine Fortsetzung der Logischen
Untersuchungen vorgesehen waren. Diese Texte, in denen die
Auseinandersetzung mit Franz Brentano und Carl Stumpf eine grosse
Rolle spielt, werden in den Beilagen zur Vorlesung veroffentlicht.
Des weiteren wird ein umfangreiches Forschungsmanuskript aus dem
Jahr 1909 veroffentlicht, das Husserls Weg zu einem noematisch
orientierten Wahrnehmungsbegriff dokumentiert. Aus dem Jahr 1912
stammt ein Text, der von Husserl als Ausarbeitung zu einer "Schrift
uber Wahrnehmung" gedacht war. In einem aus dem gleichen Jahr
stammenden Forschungsmanuskript setzt sich Husserl mit der
Aufmerksamkeitsthematik unter dem Gesichtspunkt der Stellungnahme
und ihrer moglichen Modifikation auseinander."
This is an introduction the thought of Robert Holcot, a great and
influential but often underappreciated medieval thinker. Holcot was
a Dominican friar who flourished in the 1330's and produced a
diverse body of work including scholastic treatises, biblical
commentaries, and sermons. By viewing the whole of Holcot's corpus,
this book provides a comprehensive account of his thought.
Challenging established characterizations of him as a skeptic or
radical, this book shows Holcot to be primarily concerned with
affirming and supporting the faith of the pious believer. At times,
this manifests itself as a cautious attitude toward absolutists'
claims about the power of natural reason. At other times, Holcot
reaffirms, in Anselmian fashion, the importance of rational effort
in the attempt to understand and live out one's faith. Over the
course of this introduction the authors unpack Holcot's views on
faith and heresy, the divine nature and divine foreknowledge, the
sacraments, Christ, and political philosophy. Likewise, they
examine Holcot's approach to several important medieval literary
genres, including the development of his unique "picture method,"
biblical commentaries, and sermons. In so doing, John Slotemaker
and Jeffrey Witt restore Holcot to his rightful place as one of the
most important thinkers of his time.
This new and updated edition of Christopher Shields and Robert
Pasnau's The Philosophy of Aquinas introduces the Aquinas'
overarching explanatory framework in order to provide the necessary
background to his philosophical investigations across a wide range
of areas: rational theology, metaphysics, philosophy of human
nature, philosophy of mind, and ethical and political theory.
Although not intended to provide a comprehensive evaluation of all
aspects of Aquinas' far-reaching writings, the volume presents a
systematic introduction to the principal areas of his philosophy
and attends no less to Aquinas' methods and argumentative
strategies than to his ultimate conclusions. The authors have
updated the second edition in light of recent scholarship on
Aquinas, while streamlining and refining their presentation of the
key elements of Aquinas' philosophy.
Augustine's Confessions is one of the most significant works of
Western culture. Cast as a long, impassioned conversation with God,
it is intertwined with passages of life-narrative and with key
theological and philosophical insights. It is enduringly popular,
and justly so. The Routledge Guidebook to Augustine's Confessions
is an engaging introduction to this spiritually creative and
intellectually original work. This guidebook is organized by
themes: the importance of language creation and the sensible world
memory, time and the self the afterlife of the Confessions. Written
for readers approaching the Confessions for the first time, this
guidebook addresses the literary, philosophical, historical and
theological complexities of the work in a clear and accessible way.
Excerpts in both Latin and English from this seminal work are
included throughout the book to provide a close examination of both
the autobiographical and theoretical content within the
Confessions.
Nicholas of Cusa (1401-1464), widely considered the most
important original philosopher of the Renaissance, was born in Kues
on the Moselle River. A polymath who studied canon law and became a
cardinal of the Roman Catholic Church, he wrote principally on
speculative theology, philosophy, and church politics. As a
political thinker he is best known for "De concordantia catholica,"
which presented a blueprint for peace in an age of ecclesiastical
discord.
This volume makes most of Nicholas's other writings on Church
and reform available in English for the first time, including legal
tracts arguing the case of Pope Eugenius IV against the
conciliarists, theological examinations of the nature of the
Church, and writings on reform of the papacy and curia. Among the
works translated are an early draft of "De concordantia catholica"
and the "Letter to Rodrigo Sanchez de Arevalo," which discusses the
Church in light of the Cusan idea of "learned ignorance."
Giordano Bruno's notorious public death in 1600, at the hands of the Inquisition in Rome, marked the transition from Renaissance philosophy to the Scientific Revolution of the seventeenth century. This volume presents new translations of Cause, Principle and Unity, in which he challenges Aristotelian accounts of causality and spells out the implications of Copernicanism for a new theory of an infinite universe, as well as two essays on magic, in which he interprets earlier theories about magical events in the light of the unusual powers of natural phenomena.
Aristotle in Aquinas's Theology explores the role of Aristotelian
concepts, principles, and themes in Thomas Aquinas's theology. Each
chapter investigates the significance of Aquinas's theological
reception of Aristotle in a central theological domain: the
Trinity, the angels, soul and body, the Mosaic law, grace, charity,
justice, contemplation and action, Christ, and the sacraments. In
general, the essays focus on the Summa theologiae, but some range
more widely in Aquinas's corpus. For some time, it has above all
been the influence of Aristotle on Aquinas's philosophy that has
been the centre of attention. Perhaps in reaction to philosophical
neo-Thomism, or perhaps because this Aristotelian influence appears
no longer necessary to demonstrate, the role of Aristotle in
Aquinas's theology presently receives less theological attention
than does Aquinas's use of other authorities (whether Scripture or
particular Fathers), especially in domains outside of theological
ethics. Indeed, in some theological circles the influence of
Aristotle upon Aquinas's theology is no longer well understood.
Readers will encounter here the great Aristotelian themes, such as
act and potency, God as pure act, substance and accidents, power
and generation, change and motion, fourfold causality, form and
matter, hylomorphic anthropology, the structure of intellection,
the relationship between knowledge and will, happiness and
friendship, habits and virtues, contemplation and action, politics
and justice, the best form of government, and private property and
the common good. The ten essays in this book engage Aquinas's
reception of Aristotle in his theology from a variety of points of
view: historical, philosophical, and constructively theological.
‘Why else does slippery Fortune change So much, and punishment more fit For crime oppress the innocent?’ Written in prison before his brutal execution in AD 524, Boethius’s The Consolation of Philosophy is a conversation between the ailing prisoner and his ‘nurse’ Philosophy, whose instruction restores him to health and brings him to enlightenment. Boethius was an eminent public figure who had risen to great political heights in the court of King Theodoric when he was implicated in conspiracy and condemned to death. Although a Christian, it was to the pagan Greek philosophers that he turned for inspiration following his abrupt fall from grace. With great clarity of thought and philosophical brilliance, Boethius adopted the classical model of the dialogue to debate the vagaries of Fortune, and to explore the nature of happiness, good and evil, fate and free will. Victor Watts’s English translation makes The Consolation of Philosophy accessible to the modern reader while losing nothing of its poetic artistry and breadth of vision. This edition includes an introduction discussing Boethius’s life and writings, a bibliography, glossary and notes.
Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy showcases the best scholarly
research in this flourishing field. The series covers all aspects
of medieval philosophy, including the Latin, Arabic, and Hebrew
traditions, and runs from the end of antiquity into the
Renaissance. It publishes new work by leading scholars in the
field, and combines historical scholarship with philosophical
acuteness. The papers will address a wide range of topics, from
political philosophy to ethics, and logic to metaphysics. OSMP is
an essential resource for anyone working in the area.
Graciela De Pierris presents a novel interpretation of the
relationship between skepticism and naturalism in Hume's
epistemology, and a new appraisal of Hume's place within early
modern thought. Whereas a dominant trend in recent Hume scholarship
maintains that there are no skeptical arguments concerning
causation and induction in Book I, Part III of the Treatise,
Graciela De Pierris presents a detailed reading of the skeptical
argument she finds there and how this argument initiates a train of
skeptical reasoning that begins in Part III and culminates in Part
IV. This reasoning is framed by Hume's version of the modern theory
of ideas developed by Descartes and Locke. The skeptical
implications of this theory, however, do not arise, as in
traditional interpretations of Hume's skepticism, from the 'veil of
perception.' They arise from Hume's elaboration of a
presentational-phenomenological model of ultimate evidence,
according to which there is always a justificatory gap between what
is or has been immediately presented to the mind and any ideas that
go beyond it. This happens, paradigmatically, in the
causal-inductive inference, and, as De Pierris argues, in
demonstrative inference as well. Yet, in spite of his firm
commitment to radical skepticism, Hume also accepts the
naturalistic standpoint of science and common life, and he does so,
on the novel interpretation presented here, because of an equally
firm commitment to Newtonian science in general and the Newtonian
inductive method in particular. Hume defends the Newtonian method
(against the mechanical philosophy) while simultaneously rejecting
all attempts (including those of the Newtonians) to find a place
for the supernatural within our understanding of nature.
It is commonly supposed that certain elements of medieval
philosophy are uncharacteristically preserved in modern
philosophical thought through the idea that mental phenomena are
distinguished from physical phenomena by their intentionality,
their intrinsic directedness toward some object. The many
exceptions to this presumption, however, threaten its viability.
This volume explores the intricacies and varieties of the
conceptual relationships medieval thinkers developed among
intentionality, cognition, and mental representation. Ranging from
Aquinas, Scotus, Ockham, and Buridan through less-familiar writers,
the collection sheds new light on the various strands that run
between medieval and modern thought and bring us to a number of
fundamental questions in the philosophy of mind as it is conceived
today.
Thomas Aquinas is widely recognized as one of history's most
significant Christian theologians and one of the most powerful
philosophical minds of the western tradition. But what has often
not been sufficiently attended to is the fact that he carried out
his theological and philosophical labours as a part of his vocation
as a Dominican friar, dedicated to a life of preaching and the care
of souls. Fererick Christian Bauerschmidt places Aquinas's thought
within the context of that vocation, and argues that his views on
issues of God, creation, Christology, soteriology, and the
Christian life are both shaped by and in service to the distinctive
goals of the Dominicans. What Aquinas says concerning both matters
of faith and matters of reason, as well as his understanding of the
relationship between the two, are illuminated by the particular
Dominican call to serve God through handing on to others through
preaching and teaching the fruits of one's own theological
reflection.
Five hundred years before “Jabberwocky” and Tender Buttons,
writers were already preoccupied with the question of nonsense. But
even as the prevalence in medieval texts of gibberish, babble,
birdsong, and allusions to bare voice has come into view in recent
years, an impression persists that these phenomena are exceptions
that prove the rule of the period’s theologically motivated
commitment to the kernel of meaning over and against the shell of
the mere letter. This book shows that, to the contrary, the
foundational object of study of medieval linguistic thought was vox
non-significativa, the utterance insofar as it means nothing
whatsoever, and that this fact was not lost on medieval writers of
various kinds. In a series of close and unorthodox readings of
works by Priscian, Boethius, Augustine, Walter Burley, Geoffrey
Chaucer, and the anonymous authors of the Cloud of Unknowing and
St. Erkenwald, it inquires into the way that a number of
fourteenth-century writers recognized possibilities inherent in the
accounts of language transmitted to them from antiquity and
transformed those accounts into new ideas, forms, and practices of
non-signification. Retrieving a premodern hermeneutics of obscurity
in order to provide materials for an archeology of the category of
the literary, Medieval Nonsense shows how these medieval linguistic
textbooks, mystical treatises, and poems were engineered in such a
way as to arrest the faculty of interpretation and force it to
focus on the extinguishing of sense that occurs in the encounter
with language itself.
Five hundred years before "Jabberwocky" and Tender Buttons, writers
were already preoccupied with the question of nonsense. But even as
the prevalence in medieval texts of gibberish, babble, birdsong,
and allusions to bare voice has come into view in recent years, an
impression persists that these phenomena are exceptions that prove
the rule of the period's theologically motivated commitment to the
kernel of meaning over and against the shell of the mere letter.
This book shows that, to the contrary, the foundational object of
study of medieval linguistic thought was vox non-significativa, the
utterance insofar as it means nothing whatsoever, and that this
fact was not lost on medieval writers of various kinds. In a series
of close and unorthodox readings of works by Priscian, Boethius,
Augustine, Walter Burley, Geoffrey Chaucer, and the anonymous
authors of the Cloud of Unknowing and St. Erkenwald, it inquires
into the way that a number of fourteenth-century writers recognized
possibilities inherent in the accounts of language transmitted to
them from antiquity and transformed those accounts into new ideas,
forms, and practices of non-signification. Retrieving a premodern
hermeneutics of obscurity in order to provide materials for an
archeology of the category of the literary, Medieval Nonsense shows
how these medieval linguistic textbooks, mystical treatises, and
poems were engineered in such a way as to arrest the faculty of
interpretation and force it to focus on the extinguishing of sense
that occurs in the encounter with language itself.
Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy showcases the best scholarly
research in this flourishing field. The series covers all aspects
of medieval philosophy, including the Latin, Arabic, and Hebrew
traditions, and runs from the end of antiquity into the
Renaissance. It publishes new work by leading scholars in the
field, and combines historical scholarship with philosophical
acuteness. The papers will address a wide range of topics, from
political philosophy to ethics, and logic to metaphysics. OSMP is
an essential resource for anyone working in the area.
Descartes and the First Cartesians adopts the perspective that we
should not approach Rene Descartes as a solitary thinker, but as a
philosopher who constructs a dialogue with his contemporaries, so
as to engage them and elements of his society into his
philosophical enterprise. Roger Ariew argues that an important
aspect of this engagement concerns the endeavor to establish
Cartesian philosophy in the Schools, that is, to replace Aristotle
as the authority there. Descartes wrote the Principles of
Philosophy as something of a rival to Scholastic textbooks,
initially conceiving the project as a comparison of his philosophy
and that of the Scholastics. Still, what Descartes produced was
inadequate for the task. The topics of Scholastic textbooks ranged
more broadly than those of Descartes; they usually had
quadripartite arrangements mirroring the structure of the
collegiate curriculum, divided as they typically were into logic,
ethics, physics, and metaphysics. But Descartes produced at best
only what could be called a general metaphysics and a partial
physics. These deficiencies in the Cartesian program and in its
aspiration to replace Scholastic philosophy in the schools caused
the Cartesians to rush in to fill the voids. The attempt to publish
a Cartesian textbook that would mirror what was taught in the
schools began in the 1650s with Jacques Du Roure and culminated in
the 1690s with Pierre-Sylvain Regis and Antoine Le Grand. Ariew's
original account thus considers the reception of Descartes' work,
and establishes the significance of his philosophical enterprise in
relation to the textbooks of the first Cartesians and in contrast
with late Scholastic textbooks.
|
You may like...
Meditations
Marcus Aurelius
Hardcover
R618
Discovery Miles 6 180
|