|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Logic
Terence Parsons presents a new study of the development and logical
complexity of medieval logic. Basic principles of logic were used
by Aristotle to prove conversion principles and reduce syllogisms.
Medieval logicians expanded Aristotle's notation in several ways,
such as quantifying predicate terms, as in 'No donkey is every
animal', and allowing singular terms to appear in predicate
position, as in 'Not every donkey is Brownie'; with the enlarged
notation come additional logical principles. The resulting system
of logic is able to deal with relational expressions, as in De
Morgan's puzzles about heads of horses. A crucial issue is a
mechanism for dealing with anaphoric pronouns, as in 'Every woman
loves her mother'. Parsons illuminates the ways in which medieval
logic is as rich as contemporary first-order symbolic logic, though
its full potential was not envisaged at the time. Along the way, he
provides a detailed exposition and examination of the theory of
modes of common personal supposition, and the useful principles of
logic included with it. An appendix discusses the artificial signs
introduced in the fifteenth century to alter quantifier scope.
Ordinary language and scientific language enable us to speak about,
in a singular way (using demonstratives and names), what we
recognize not to exist: fictions, the contents of our
hallucinations, abstract objects, and various idealized but
nonexistent objects that our scientific theories are often couched
in terms of. Indeed, references to such nonexistent
items-especially in the case of the application of mathematics to
the sciences-are indispensable. We cannot avoid talking about such
things. Scientific and ordinary languages thus enable us to say
things about Pegasus or about hallucinated objects that are true
(or false), such as "Pegasus was believed by the ancient Greeks to
be a flying horse," or "That elf I'm now hallucinating over there
is wearing blue shoes." Standard contemporary metaphysical views
and semantic analyses of singular idioms on offer in contemporary
philosophy of language have not successfully accommodated these
routine practices of saying true and false things about the
nonexistent while simultaneously honoring the insight that such
things do not exist in any way at all (and have no properties).
That is, philosophers often feel driven to claim that such objects
do exist, or they claim that all our talk isn't genuine truth-apt
talk, but only pretence. This book reconfigures metaphysics (and
the role of metaphysics in semantics) in radical ways that allow
the accommodation of our ordinary ways of speaking of what does not
exist while retaining the absolutely crucial presupposition that
such objects exist in no way at all, have no properties, and so are
not the truth-makers for the truths and falsities that are about
them.
Logical consequence is the relation that obtains between premises
and conclusion(s) in a valid argument. Orthodoxy has it that valid
arguments are necessarily truth-preserving, but this platitude only
raises a number of further questions, such as: how does the truth
of premises guarantee the truth of a conclusion, and what
constraints does validity impose on rational belief? This volume
presents thirteen essays by some of the most important scholars in
the field of philosophical logic. The essays offer ground-breaking
new insights into the nature of logical consequence; the relation
between logic and inference; how the semantics and pragmatics of
natural language bear on logic; the relativity of logic; and the
structural properties of the consequence relation.
Is truth objective or relative? What exists independently of our
minds? This book is about these two questions. The essays in its
pages variously defend and critique answers to each, grapple over
the proper methodology for addressing them, and wonder whether
either question is worth pursuing. In so doing, they carry on a
long and esteemed tradition - for our two questions are among the
oldest of philosophical issues, and have vexed almost every major
philosopher, from Plato, to Kant to Wittgenstein. Fifteen eminent
contributors bring fresh perspectives, renewed energy and original
answers to debates which have been the focus of a tremendous amount
of interest in the last three decades both within philosophy and
the culture at large.
Roy T Cook examines the Yablo paradox-a paradoxical, infinite
sequence of sentences, each of which entails the falsity of all
others later than it in the sequence-with special attention paid to
the idea that this paradox provides us with a semantic paradox that
involves no circularity. The three main chapters of the book focus,
respectively, on three questions that can be (and have been) asked
about the Yablo construction. First we have the Characterization
Problem, which asks what patterns of sentential reference (circular
or not) generate semantic paradoxes. Addressing this problem
requires an interesting and fruitful detour through the theory of
directed graphs, allowing us to draw interesting connections
between philosophical problems and purely mathematical ones. Next
is the Circularity Question, which addresses whether or not the
Yablo paradox is genuinely non-circular. Answering this question is
complicated: although the original formulation of the Yablo paradox
is circular, it turns out that it is not circular in any sense that
can bear the blame for the paradox. Further, formulations of the
paradox using infinitary conjunction provide genuinely non-circular
constructions. Finally, Cook turns his attention to the
Generalizability Question: can the Yabloesque pattern be used to
generate genuinely non-circular variants of other paradoxes, such
as epistemic and set-theoretic paradoxes? Cook argues that although
there are general constructions-unwindings-that transform circular
constructions into Yablo-like sequences, it turns out that these
sorts of constructions are not 'well-behaved' when transferred from
semantic puzzles to puzzles of other sorts. He concludes with a
short discussion of the connections between the Yablo paradox and
the Curry paradox.
Our conception of logical space is the set of distinctions we use
to navigate the world. In The Construction of Logical Space Agustin
Rayo defends the idea that one's conception of logical space is
shaped by one's acceptance or rejection of 'just is'-statements:
statements like 'to be composed of water just is to be composed of
H2O', or 'for the number of the dinosaurs to be zero just is for
there to be no dinosaurs'. The resulting picture is used to
articulate a conception of metaphysical possibility that does not
depend on a reduction of the modal to the non-modal, and to develop
a trivialist philosophy of mathematics, according to which the
truths of pure mathematics have trivial truth-conditions.
In Frege's Conception of Logic Patricia A. Blanchette explores the
relationship between Gottlob Frege's understanding of conceptual
analysis and his understanding of logic. She argues that the
fruitfulness of Frege's conception of logic, and the illuminating
differences between that conception and those more modern views
that have largely supplanted it, are best understood against the
backdrop of a clear account of the role of conceptual analysis in
logical investigation. The first part of the book locates the role
of conceptual analysis in Frege's logicist project. Blanchette
argues that despite a number of difficulties, Frege's use of
analysis in the service of logicism is a powerful and coherent
tool. As a result of coming to grips with his use of that tool, we
can see that there is, despite appearances, no conflict between
Frege's intention to demonstrate the grounds of ordinary arithmetic
and the fact that the numerals of his derived sentences fail to
co-refer with ordinary numerals. In the second part of the book,
Blanchette explores the resulting conception of logic itself, and
some of the straightforward ways in which Frege's conception
differs from its now-familiar descendants. In particular,
Blanchette argues that consistency, as Frege understands it,
differs significantly from the kind of consistency demonstrable via
the construction of models. To appreciate this difference is to
appreciate the extent to which Frege was right in his debate with
Hilbert over consistency- and independence-proofs in geometry. For
similar reasons, modern results such as the completeness of formal
systems and the categoricity of theories do not have for Frege the
same importance they are commonly taken to have by his
post-Tarskian descendants. These differences, together with the
coherence of Frege's position, provide reason for caution with
respect to the appeal to formal systems and their properties in the
treatment of fundamental logical properties and relations.
The central contention of this book is that second-order logic has
a central role to play in laying the foundations of mathematics. In
order to develop the argument fully, the author presents a detailed
development of higher-order logic, including a comprehensive
discussion of its semantics. Professor Shapiro demonstrates the
prevalence of second-order notions in mathematics is practised, and
also the extent to which mathematical concepts can be formulated in
second-order languages . He shows how first-order languages are
insufficient to codify many concepts in contemporary mathematics,
and thus that higher-order logic is needed to fully reflect current
mathematics. Throughout, the emphasis is on discussing the
philosophical and historical issues associated with this subject,
and the implications that they have for foundational studies. For
the most part, the author assumes little more than a familiarity
with logic as might be gained from a beginning graduate course
which includes the incompleteness of arithmetic and the
Lowenheim-Skolem theorems. All those concerned with the foundations
of mathematics will find this a thought-provoking discussion of
some of the central issues in this subject.
Anil Gupta asks one of the key questions in philosophy: what is the
contribution of experience of knowledge? Gupta develops an account
of experience that allows it to inform knowledge while respecting
two constraints - the contribution of experience to knowledge must
be both rational and substantial. He says that these constraints
cannot be met if we make the assumption that experience only
aquaints us with partial truth about the world. Instead he uses
tools from philosophical logic, specifically the logic of
interdependent concepts, to show that a natural account of
experience is available using the interdependence of views and
perceptual judgements. In essence he argues for a reformed
empiricism that embraces experience as conditional.
Are people rational? This question was central to Greek thought;
and has been at the heart of psychology and philosophy for
millennia. This book provides a radical and controversial
reappraisal of conventional wisdom in the psychology of reasoning,
proposing that the Western conception of the mind as a logical
system is flawed at the very outset. It argues that cognition
should be understood in terms of probability theory, the calculus
of uncertain reasoning, rather than in terms of logic, the calculus
of certain reasoning.
Individual objects have potentials: paper has the potential to
burn, an acorn has the potential to turn into a tree, some people
have the potential to run a mile in less than four minutes. Barbara
Vetter provides a systematic investigation into the metaphysics of
such potentials, and an account of metaphysical modality based on
them. In contemporary philosophy, potentials have been recognized
mostly in the form of so-called dispositions: solubility,
fragility, and so on. Vetter takes dispositions as her starting
point, but argues for and develops a more comprehensive conception
of potentiality. She shows how, with this more comprehensive
conception, an account of metaphysical modality can be given that
meets three crucial requirements: (1) Extensional correctness:
providing the right truth-values for statements of possibility and
necessity; (2) formal adequacy: providing the right logic for
metaphysical modality; and (3) semantic utility: providing a
semantics that links ordinary modal language to the metaphysics of
modality. The resulting view of modality is a version of
dispositionalism about modality: it takes modality to be a matter
of the dispositions of individual objects (and, crucially, not of
possible worlds). This approach has a long philosophical tradition
going back to Aristotle, but has been largely neglected in
contemporary philosophy. In recent years, it has become a live
option again due to the rise of anti-Humean, powers-based
metaphysics. The aim of Potentiality is to develop the
dispositionalist view in a way that takes account of contemporary
developments in metaphysics, logic, and semantics.
This book was designed primarily as a textbook; though the author
hopes that it will prove to be of interests to others beside logic
students. Part I of this book covers the fundamentals of the
subject the propositional calculus and the theory of
quantification. Part II deals with the traditional formal logic and
with the developments which have taken that as their
starting-point. Part III deals with modal, three-valued, and
extensional systems.
Colin Howson offers a solution to one of the central, unsolved problems of Western philosophy, the problem of induction. In the mid-eighteenth century David Hume argued that successful prediction tells us nothing about the truth or probable truth of the predicting theory. Howson claims that Hume's argument is correct, and examines what follows about the relation between science and its empirical base.
In Contradiction advocates and defends the view that there are true
contradictions (dialetheism), a view that flies in the face of
orthodoxy in Western philosophy since Aristotle. The book has been
at the center of the controversies surrounding dialetheism ever
since its first publication in
1987. This second edition of the book substantially expands upon
the original in various ways, and also contains the author's
reflections on developments over the last two decades. Further
aspects of dialetheism are discussed in the companion volume, Doubt
Truth to be a Liar, also published by
Oxford University Press in 2006.
Hilbert's Programs & Beyond presents the foundational work of
David Hilbert in a sequence of thematically organized essays. They
first trace the roots of Hilbert's work to the radical
transformation of mathematics in the 19th century and bring out his
pivotal role in creating mathematical logic and proof theory. They
then analyze techniques and results of "classical" proof theory as
well as their dramatic expansion in modern proof theory. This
intellectual experience finally opens horizons for reflection on
the nature of mathematics in the 21st century: Sieg articulates his
position of reductive structuralism and explores mathematical
capacities via computational models.
The book sets out a new logic of rules, developed to demonstrate how such a logic can contribute to the clarification of historical questions about social rules. The authors illustrate applications of this new logic in their extensive treatments of a variety of accounts of social changes, analysing in these examples the content of particular social rules and the course of changes in them.
|
|