|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Logic
Bertrand Russell, (1872 - 1970) was a British philosopher,
logician, mathematician, historian, and social critic. Russell's
books are excellent for those who have no experience of reading
philosophy. This volume contains many of his most notable works:
The Problems with Philosophy, The Analysis of the Mind, Mysticism
and Logic and other Essays, Political Ideals, The Problem of China,
The Practice and Theory of Bolshevism, Proposed Roads to Freedom,
Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific
Method in Philosophy
The story of Sosipatra of Pergamum (4th century C.E.) as told by
her biographer, Eunapius of Sardis in his Lives of the Philosophers
and Sophists, is a remarkable tale. It is the story of an elite
young girl from the area of Ephesus, who was educated by traveling
oracles (daemons), and who grew up to lead her own philosophy
school on the west coast of Asia Minor. She was also a prophet of
sorts, channeling divine messages to her students, family, and
friends, and foretelling the future. Sosipatra of Pergamum is the
first sustained, book length attempt to tell the story of this
mysterious woman. It presents a rich contextualization of the brief
and highly fictionalized portrait provided by Eunapius. In doing
so, the book explores the cultural and political landscape of late
ancient Asia Minor, especially the areas around Ephesus, Pergamum,
Sardis, and Smyrna. It also discusses moments in Sosipatra's life
for what they reveal more generally about women's lives in Late
Antiquity in the areas of childhood, education, family, household,
motherhood, widowhood, and professional life. Her career sheds
light on late Roman Platonism, its engagement with religion,
ritual, and "magic," and the role of women in this movement. By
thoroughly examining the ancient evidence, Heidi Marx recovers a
hidden yet important figure from the rich intellectual traditions
of the Roman Near East.
This book investigates a number of central problems in the
philosophy of Charles Peirce grouped around the realism of his
semiotics: the issue of how sign systems are developed and used in
the investigation of reality. Thus, it deals with the precise
character of Peirce's realism; with Peirce's special notion of
propositions as signs which, at the same time, denote and describe
the same object. It deals with diagrams as signs which depict more
or less abstract states-of-affairs, facilitating reasoning about
them; with assertions as public claims about the truth of
propositions. It deals with iconicity in logic, the issue of
self-control in reasoning, dependences between phenomena in their
realist descriptions. A number of chapters deal with applied
semiotics: with biosemiotic sign use among pre-human organisms: the
multimedia combination of pictorial and linguistic information in
human semiotic genres like cartoons, posters, poetry, monuments.
All in all, the book makes a strong case for the actual relevance
of Peirce's realist semiotics.
Material objects persist through time and survive change. How do
they manage to do so? What are the underlying facts of persistence?
Do objects persist by being "wholly present" at all moments of time
at which they exist? Or do they persist by having distinct
"temporal segments" confined to the corresponding times? Are
objects three-dimensional entities extended in space, but not in
time? Or are they four-dimensional spacetime "worms"? These are
matters of intense debate, which is now driven by concerns about
two major issues in fundamental ontology: parthood and location. It
is in this context that broadly empirical considerations are
increasingly brought to bear on the debate about persistence.
Persistence and Spacetime pursues this empirically based approach
to the questions. Yuri Balashov begins by setting out major rival
views of persistence -- endurance, perdurance, and exdurance -- in
a spacetime framework and proceeds to investigate the implications
of Einstein's theory of relativity for the debate about
persistence. His overall conclusion -- that relativistic
considerations favour four-dimensionalism over three-dimensionalism
-- is hardly surprising. It is, however, anything but trivial.
Contrary to a common misconception, there is no straightforward
argument from relativity to four-dimensionalism. The issues
involved are complex, and the debate is closely entangled with a
number of other philosophical disputes, including those about the
nature and ontology of time, parts and wholes, material
constitution, causation and properties, and vagueness.
To clarify and facilitate our inquiries we need to define a
disquotational truth predicate that we are directly licensed to
apply not only to our own sentences as we use them now, but also to
other speakers' sentences and our own sentences as we used them in
the past. The conventional wisdom is that there can be no such
truth predicate. For it appears that the only instances of the
disquotational pattern that we are directly licensed to accept are
those that define "is true" for our own sentences as we use them
now. Gary Ebbs shows that this appearance is illusory. He
constructs an account of words that licenses us to rely not only on
formal (spelling-based) identifications of our own words, but also
on our non-deliberative practical identifications of other
speakers' words and of our own words as we used them in the past.
To overturn the conventional wisdom about disquotational truth,
Ebbs argues, we need only combine this account of words with our
disquotational definitions of truth for sentences as we use them
now. The result radically transforms our understanding of truth and
related topics, including anti-individualism, self-knowledge, and
the intersubjectivity of logic.
This volume of newly written chapters on the history and
interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus represents a significant
step beyond the polemical debate between broad interpretive
approaches that has recently characterized the field. Some of the
contributors might count their approach as 'new' or 'resolute',
while others are more 'traditional', but all are here concerned
primarily with understanding in detail the structure of argument
that Wittgenstein presents within the Tractatus, rather than with
its final self-renunciation, or with the character of the
understanding that renunciation might leave behind. The volume
makes a strong case that close investigation, both biographical and
textual, into the composition of the Tractatus, and into the
various influences on it, still has much to yield in revealing the
complexity and fertility of Wittgenstein's early thought. Amongst
these influences Kant and Kierkegaard are considered alongside
Wittgenstein's immediate predecessors in the analytic tradition.
The themes explored range across the breadth of Wittgenstein's
book, and include his accounts of ethics and aesthetics, as well as
issues in metaphysics and the philosophy of mind, and aspects of
the logical framework of his account of representation. The
contrast of saying and showing, and Wittgenstein's attitude to the
inexpressible, is of central importance to many of the
contributions. By approaching this concern through the various
first-level issues that give rise to it, rather than from
entrenched schematic positions, the contributors demonstrate the
possibility of a more inclusive, constructive and fruitful mode of
engagement with Wittgenstein's text and with each other.
When instruments are harmoniously joined together, beautiful music
ensues. Just as in a classic symphony, life often occurs in phases,
or movements. In his creative comparison Symphony #1 in a Minor
Key, literary exegete Alan Block shares his philosophies on four
movements reflected in his own life, each loosely modeled on a
different musical form linked to the emotions of a life both fully
lived and joyously celebrated. In the first movement, "Sonata
Allegro," Block juxtaposes biblical stories with personal
experiences as he explores the contradictory nature of what it
means to leave home in search of another home. In the second
movement, representing a slow march to and from the grave, he
focuses his examination on the funerals of three very different
people from a Jewish perspective. In strong contrast, Block
presents a glimpse into his absurd daily world in the third
movement, punctuated by jokes and commentary. Finally, he shares a
celebration of life and hope inspired by the final movement of
Beethoven's Seventh Symphony, encouraging others to be open to the
sublime and realize that none of our worlds is perfect. Symphony #1
in a Minor Key shares one man's reflections as he offers a
fascinating meditation on life, death, and everything in between.
Is the point of belief and assertion invariably to think or say
something true? Is the truth of a belief or assertion absolute, or
is it only relative to human interests? Most philosophers think it
incoherent to profess to believe something but not think it true,
or to say that some of the things we believe are only relatively
true. Common sense disagrees. It sees many opinions, such as those
about matters of taste, as neither true nor false; it takes it as
obvious that some of the truth is relative. Mark Richard's
accessible book argues that when it comes to truth, common sense is
right, philosophical orthodoxy wrong. The first half of the book
examines connections between the performative aspects of talk (what
we do when we speak), our emotions and evaluations, and the
conditions under which talk and thought qualifies as true or false.
It argues that the performative and expressive sometimes trump the
semantic, making truth and falsity the wrong dimension of
evaluation for belief or assertion. Among the topics taken up are:
racial slurs and other epithets; relations between logic and truth;
the status of moral and ethical talk; vagueness and the liar
paradox. The book's second half defends the idea that much of
everyday thought and talk is only relatively true or false. Truth
is inevitably relative, given that we cannot work out in advance
how our concepts will apply to the world. Richard explains what it
is for truth to be relative, rebuts standard objections to
relativism, and argues that relativism is consistent with the idea
that one view can be objectively better than another. The book
concludes with an account of matters of taste and of how it is
possible for divergent views of such matters to be equally valid,
even if not true or false. When Truth Gives Out will be of interest
not only to philosophers who work on language, ethics, knowledge,
or logic, but to any thoughtful person who has wondered what it is,
or isn't, for something to be true.
Used in a variety of courses in various disciplines, Asking the
Right Questions helps students bridge the gap between simply
memorizing or blindly accepting information, and the greater
challenge of critical analysis and synthesis. Specifically, this
concise text teaches students to think critically by exploring the
components of arguments--issues, conclusions, reasons, evidence,
assumptions, language--and on how to spot fallacies and
manipulations and obstacles to critical thinking in both written
and visual communication. It teaches them to respond to alternative
points of view and develop a solid foundation for making personal
choices about what to accept and what to reject.
Our experience of objects (and consequently our theorizing about
them) is very rich. We perceive objects as possessing individuation
conditions. They appear to have boundaries in space and time, for
example, and they appear to move independently of a background of
other objects or a landscape. In Ontology Without Boundaries Jody
Azzouni undertakes an analysis of our concept of object, and shows
what about that notion is truly due to the world and what about it
is a projection onto the world of our senses and thinking. Location
and individuation conditions are our product: there is no echo of
them in the world. Features, the ways that objects seem to be,
aren't projections. Azzouni shows how the resulting austere
metaphysics tames a host of ancient philosophical problems about
constitution ("Ship of Theseus," "Sorities"), as well as
contemporary puzzles about reductionism. In addition, it's shown
that the same sorts of individuation conditions for properties,
which philosophers use to distinguish between various kinds of odd
abstracta-universals, tropes, and so on, are also projections.
Accompanying our notion of an object is a background logic that
makes cogent ontological debate about anything from Platonic
objects to Bigfoot. Contemporary views about this background logic
("quantifier variance") make ontological debate incoherent. Azzouni
shows how a neutral interpretation of quantifiers and quantifier
domains makes sense of both philosophical and pre-philosophical
ontological debates. Azzouni also shows how the same apparatus
makes sense of our speaking about a host of items-Mickey Mouse,
unicorns, Martians-that nearly all of us deny exist. It's allowed
by what Azzouni shows about the background logic of our ontological
debates, as well as the semantics of the language of those debates
that we can disagree over the existence of things, like unicorns,
without that background logic and semantics forcing ontological
commitments onto speakers that they don't have.
|
You may like...
Formal Logic
Prior
Hardcover
R2,110
R1,287
Discovery Miles 12 870
Truth and Realism
Patrick Greenough, Michael P Lynch
Hardcover
R3,641
Discovery Miles 36 410
|