|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Logic
Used in a variety of courses in various disciplines, Asking the
Right Questions helps students bridge the gap between simply
memorizing or blindly accepting information, and the greater
challenge of critical analysis and synthesis. Specifically, this
concise text teaches students to think critically by exploring the
components of arguments--issues, conclusions, reasons, evidence,
assumptions, language--and on how to spot fallacies and
manipulations and obstacles to critical thinking in both written
and visual communication. It teaches them to respond to alternative
points of view and develop a solid foundation for making personal
choices about what to accept and what to reject.
This edited book focuses on concepts and their applications using
the theory of conceptual spaces, one of today's most central tracks
of cognitive science discourse. It features 15 papers based on
topics presented at the Conceptual Spaces @ Work 2016 conference.
The contributors interweave both theory and applications in their
papers. Among the first mentioned are studies on metatheories,
logical and systemic implications of the theory, as well as
relations between concepts and language. Examples of the latter
include explanatory models of paradigm shifts and evolution in
science as well as dilemmas and issues of health, ethics, and
education. The theory of conceptual spaces overcomes many
translational issues between academic theoretization and practical
applications. The paradigm is mainly associated with structural
explanations, such as categorization and meronomy. However, the
community has also been relating it to relations, functions, and
systems. The book presents work that provides a geometric model for
the representation of human conceptual knowledge that bridges the
symbolic and the sub-conceptual levels of representation. The model
has already proven to have a broad range of applicability beyond
cognitive science and even across a number of disciplines related
to concepts and representation.
This book repairs and revives the Theory of Knowledge research
program of Russell's Principia era. Chapter 1, 'Introduction and
Overview', explains the program's agenda. Inspired by the
non-Fregean logicism of Principia Mathematica, it endorses the
revolution within mathematics presenting it as a study of
relations. The synthetic a priori logic of Principia is the essence
of philosophy considered as a science which exposes the dogmatisms
about abstract particulars and metaphysical necessities that create
prisons that fetter the mind. Incipient in The Problems of
Philosophy, the program's acquaintance epistemology embraced a
multiple-relation theory of belief. It reached an impasse in 1913,
having been itself retrofitted with abstract particular logical
forms to address problems of direction and compositionality. With
its acquaintance epistemology in limbo, Scientific Method in
Philosophy became the sequel to Problems. Chapter 2 explains
Russell's feeling intellectually dishonest. Wittgenstein's demand
that logic exclude nonsense belief played no role. The 1919 neutral
monist era ensued, but Russell found no epistemology for the logic
essential to philosophy. Repairing, Chapters 4-6 solve the impasse.
Reviving, Chapters 3 and 7 vigorously defend the facts about
Principia. Studies of modality and entailment are viable while
Principia remains a universal logic above the civil wars of the
metaphysicians.
Subtle Implications is a defining clarification of the human
experience as presented in the story of the author's life, and
expressed in his 'Theories of Everything. Through his unrelenting
quest to understand and come to terms with life's wide variety of
apparently random events, he developed a methodology we can use to
analyze and understand the madness. At the very least, the author
offers the opportunity to gain the insight and strength needed to
cope with even the worst of life's emotionally crippling crises.
What are the true natures of our physical and spiritual realities?
How did our Universe begin? Why are we here? Why do bad things
happen in our lives? What happens when we die? Do we live again?
Life is not that complicated. Pertinent information and the proper
perspective can help you see life as your own creation. You alone
are responsible for the present state of every facet of your life.
Together we are responsible for every aspect of the world that
greets us every morning. Together we can create a world where a
comfortable life is the rule and not the exception. It is all up to
us
Syllogism is a form of logical argument allowing one to deduce a
consistent conclusion based on a pair of premises having a common
term. Although Aristotle was the first to conceive and develop this
way of reasoning, he left open a lot of conceptual space for
further modifications, improvements and systematizations with
regards to his original syllogistic theory. From its creation until
modern times, syllogism has remained a powerful and compelling
device of deduction and argument, used by a variety of figures and
assuming a variety of forms throughout history. The Aftermath of
Syllogism investigates the key developments in the history of this
peculiar pattern of inference, from Avicenna to Hegel. Taking as
its focus the longue duree of development between the Middle Ages
and the nineteenth century, this book looks at the huge reworking
scientific syllogism underwent over the centuries, as some of the
finest philosophical minds brought it to an unprecedented height of
logical sharpness and sophistication. Bringing together a group of
major international experts in the Aristotelian tradition, The
Aftermath of Syllogism provides a detailed, up to date and critical
evaluation of the history of syllogistic deduction.
This monograph proposes a new (dialogical) way of studying the
different forms of correlational inference, known in the Islamic
jurisprudence as qiyas. According to the authors' view, qiyas
represents an innovative and sophisticated form of dialectical
reasoning that not only provides new epistemological insights into
legal argumentation in general (including legal reasoning in Common
and Civil Law) but also furnishes a fine-grained pattern for
parallel reasoning which can be deployed in a wide range of
problem-solving contexts and does not seem to reduce to the
standard forms of analogical reasoning studied in contemporary
philosophy of science and argumentation theory. After an overview
of the emergence of qiyas and of the work of al-Shirazi penned by
Soufi Youcef, the authors discuss al-Shirazi's classification of
correlational inferences of the occasioning factor (qiyas
al-'illa). The second part of the volume deliberates on the system
of correlational inferences by indication and resemblance (qiyas
al-dalala, qiyas al-shabah). The third part develops the main
theoretical background of the authors' work, namely, the dialogical
approach to Martin-Loef's Constructive Type Theory. The authors
present this in a general form and independently of adaptations
deployed in parts I and II. Part III also includes an appendix on
the relevant notions of Constructive Type Theory, which has been
extracted from an overview written by Ansten Klev. The book
concludes with some brief remarks on contemporary approaches to
analogy in Common and Civil Law and also to parallel reasoning in
general.
This book is a collection of contributions honouring Arnon Avron's
seminal work on the semantics and proof theory of non-classical
logics. It includes presentations of advanced work by some of the
most esteemed scholars working on semantic and proof-theoretical
aspects of computer science logic. Topics in this book include
frameworks for paraconsistent reasoning, foundations of relevance
logics, analysis and characterizations of modal logics and fuzzy
logics, hypersequent calculi and their properties,
non-deterministic semantics, algebraic structures for many-valued
logics, and representations of the mechanization of mathematics.
Avron's foundational and pioneering contributions have been widely
acknowledged and adopted by the scientific community. His research
interests are very broad, spanning over proof theory, automated
reasoning, non-classical logics, foundations of mathematics, and
applications of logic in computer science and artificial
intelligence. This is clearly reflected by the diversity of topics
discussed in the chapters included in this book, all of which
directly relate to Avron's past and present works. This book is of
interest to computer scientists and scholars of formal logic.
This book argues that the primary function of human thinking in
language is to make judgments, which are logical-normative
connections of concepts. Robert Abele points out that this
presupposes cognitive conditions that cannot be accounted for by
empirical-linguistic analyses of language content or social
conditions alone. Judgments rather assume both reason and a unified
subject, and this requires recognition of a Kantian-type of
transcendental dimension to them. Judgments are related to
perception in that both are syntheses, defined as the unity of
representations according to a rule/form. Perceptual syntheses are
simultaneously pre-linguistic and proto-rational, and the
understanding (Kant's Verstand) makes these syntheses conceptually
and thus self-consciously explicit. Abele concludes with a
transcendental critique of postmodernism and what its deflationary
view of ontological categories-such as the unified and reasoning
subject-has done to political thinking. He presents an alternative
that calls for a return to normativity and a recognition of reason,
objectivity, and the universality of principles.
This volume investigates what is beyond the Principle of
Non-Contradiction. It features 14 papers on the foundations of
reasoning, including logical systems and philosophical
considerations. Coverage brings together a cluster of issues
centered upon the variety of meanings of consistency,
contradiction, and related notions. Most of the papers, but not
all, are developed around the subtle distinctions between
consistency and non-contradiction, as well as among contradiction,
inconsistency, and triviality, and concern one of the above
mentioned threads of the broadly understood non-contradiction
principle and the related principle of explosion. Some others take
a perspective that is not too far away from such themes, but with
the freedom to tread new paths. Readers should understand the title
of this book in a broad way,because it is not so obvious to deal
with notions like contradictions, consistency, inconsistency, and
triviality. The papers collected here present groundbreaking ideas
related to consistency and inconsistency.
"An Introduction to the History of Philosophical and Formal Logic"
introduces ideas and thinkers central to the development of
philosophical and formal logic. From its Aristotelian origins to
the present-day arguments, logic is broken down into four main time
periods: -Antiquity and the Middle Ages (Aristotle and The Stoics)
-The early modern period (Leibniz, Bolzano, Boole) -High modern
period (Frege, Peano & Russell and Hilbert)-Early 20th century:
(Godel and Tarski) Each new time frame begins with an introductory
overview highlighting themes and points of importance. Chapters
discuss the significance and reception of influential works and
look at historical arguments in the context of contemporary
debates. To support independent study, comprehensive lists of
primary and secondary reading are included at the end of chapters,
along with exercises and discussion questions.By clearly presenting
and explaining the changes to logic across the history of
philosophy, "An Introduction to the History of Philosophical and
Formal Logic" constructs an easy-to-follow narrative. This is an
ideal starting point for students looking to understand the
historical development of logic.
This book is a consideration of Hegel's view on logic and basic
logical concepts such as truth, form, validity, and contradiction,
and aims to assess this view's relevance for contemporary
philosophical logic. The literature on Hegel's logic is fairly
rich. The attention to contemporary philosophical logic places the
present research closer to those works interested in the link
between Hegel's thought and analytical philosophy
(Stekeler-Weithofer 1992 and 2019, Berto 2005, Rockmore 2005,
Redding 2007, Nuzzo 2010 (ed.), Koch 2014, Brandom 2014, 1-15,
Pippin 2016, Moyar 2017, Quante & Mooren 2018 among others). In
this context, one particularity of this book consists in focusing
on something that has been generally underrated in the literature:
the idea that, for Hegel as well as for Aristotle and many other
authors (including Frege), logic is the study of the forms of
truth, i.e. the forms that our thought can (or ought to) assume in
searching for truth. In this light, Hegel's thinking about logic is
a fundamental reference point for anyone interested in a
philosophical foundation of logic.
This volume presents the state of the art in the algebraic
investigation into substructural logics. It features papers from
the workshop AsubL (Algebra & Substructural Logics - Take 6).
Held at the University of Cagliari, Italy, this event is part of
the framework of the Horizon 2020 Project SYSMICS: SYntax meets
Semantics: Methods, Interactions, and Connections in Substructural
logics. Substructural logics are usually formulated as Gentzen
systems that lack one or more structural rules. They have been
intensively studied over the past two decades by logicians of
various persuasions. These researchers include mathematicians,
philosophers, linguists, and computer scientists. Substructural
logics are applicable to the mathematical investigation of such
processes as resource-conscious reasoning, approximate reasoning,
type-theoretical grammar, and other focal notions in computer
science. They also apply to epistemology, economics, and
linguistics. The recourse to algebraic methods -- or, better, the
fecund interplay of algebra and proof theory -- has proved useful
in providing a unifying framework for these investigations. The
AsubL series of conferences, in particular, has played an important
role in these developments. This collection will appeal to students
and researchers with an interest in substructural logics, abstract
algebraic logic, residuated lattices, proof theory, universal
algebra, and logical semantics.
Many commentaries have been devoted to Lewis Carroll's masterpiece,
Alice's Adventures in Wonderland. The interpretations range from
Freudian analysis to speculations about the real-life people who
may have inspired the animal characters.
In this unique approach to interpreting Alice, the fruit of ten
years of research, Dr. Bernard M. Patten shows that Charles
Lutwidge Dodgson, aka Lewis Carroll, fused his passion for logic,
mathematics, and games with his love of words and nonsense stories
to produce a multifaceted, intricately structured work of
literature. Patten provides a chapter-by-chapter skeleton key to
Alice, which meticulously demonstrates how its various episodes
reveal Dodgson's profound knowledge of the rules of clear thinking,
informal and formal logic, symbolic logic, and human nature.
As Patten makes clear, Alice's Adventures in Wonderland, far from
being just an entertaining children's book, is more complex and
deeply reflective of Dodgson's character than it may seem. By
making an effort to understand its deeper layers, both children and
adults may profit from this masterful tale by learning to think
better and, along the way, having fun.
Sortal concepts are at the center of certain logical discussions
and have played a significant role in solutions to particular
problems in philosophy. Apart from logic and philosophy, the study
of sortal concepts has found its place in specific fields of
psychology, such as the theory of infant cognitive development and
the theory of human perception. In this monograph, different formal
logics for sortal concepts and sortal-related logical notions (such
as sortal identity and first-order sortal quantification) are
characterized. Most of these logics are intensional in nature and
possess, in addition, a bidimensional character. That is, they
simultaneously represent two different logical dimensions. In most
cases, the dimensions are those of time and natural necessity, and,
in other cases, those of time and epistemic necessity. Another
feature of the logics in question concerns second-order
quantification over sortal concepts, a logical notion that is also
represented in the logics. Some of the logics adopt a constant
domain interpretation, others a varying domain interpretation of
such quantification. Two of the above bidimensional logics are
philosophically grounded on predication sortalism, that is, on the
philosophical view that predication necessarily requires sortal
concepts. Another bidimensional logic constitutes a logic for
complex sortal predicates. These three sorts of logics are among
the important novelties of this work since logics with similar
features have not been developed up to now, and they might be
instrumental for the solution of philosophically significant
problems regarding sortal predicates. The book assumes a modern
variant of conceptualism as a philosophical background. For this
reason, the approach to sortal predicates is in terms of sortal
concepts. Concepts, in general, are here understood as
intersubjective realizable cognitive capacities. The proper
features of sortal concepts are determined by an analysis of the
main features of sortal predicates. Posterior to this analysis, the
sortal-related logical notions represented in the above logics are
discussed. There is also a discussion on the extent to which the
set-theoretic formal semantic systems of the book capture different
aspects of the conceptualist approach to sortals. These different
semantic frameworks are also related to realist and nominalist
approaches to sortal predicates, and possible modifications to them
are considered that might represent those alternative approaches.
This is a guide to the thought and ideas of Gottlob Frege, one of
the most important but also perplexing figures in the history of
analytic philosophy. Gottlob Frege is regarded as one of the
founders of modern logic and analytic philosophy, indeed as the
greatest innovator in logic since Aristotle. His groundbreaking
work identified many of the basic conceptions and distinctions that
later came to dominate analytic philosophy. The literature on him
is legion and ever-growing in complexity, representing a
considerable challenge to the non-expert. The details of his logic,
which have come into focus in recent research, are particularly
difficult to grasp, although they are crucial to the development of
his grand project, the reduction of arithmetic to logic, and the
associated philosophical innovations. This book offers a lucid and
accessible introduction to Frege's logic, taking the reader
directly to the core of his philosophy, and ultimately to some of
the most pertinent issues in contemporary philosophy of language,
logic, mathematics, and the mind. "Continuum's Guides for the
Perplexed" are clear, concise and accessible introductions to
thinkers, writers and subjects that students and readers can find
especially challenging - or indeed downright bewildering.
Concentrating specifically on what it is that makes the subject
difficult to grasp, these books explain and explore key themes and
ideas, guiding the reader towards a thorough understanding of
demanding material.
Reference is a central topic in philosophy of language, and has
been the main focus of discussion about how language relates to the
world. R. M. Sainsbury sets out a new approach to the concept,
which promises to bring to an end some long-standing debates in
semantic theory. There is a single category of referring
expressions, all of which deserve essentially the same kind of
semantic treatment. Included in this category are both singular and
plural referring expressions ('Aristotle', 'The Pleiades'), complex
and non-complex referring expressions ('The President of the USA in
1970', 'Nixon'), and empty and non-empty referring expressions
('Vulcan', 'Neptune'). Referring expressions are to be described
semantically by a reference condition, rather than by being
associated with a referent. In arguing for these theses,
Sainsbury's book promises to end the fruitless oscillation between
Millian and descriptivist views. Millian views insist that every
name has a referent, and find it hard to give a good account of
names which appear not to have referents, or at least are not known
to do so, like ones introduced through error ('Vulcan'), ones where
it is disputed whether they have a bearer ('Patanjali') and ones
used in fiction. Descriptivist theories require that each name be
associated with some body of information. These theories fly in the
face of the fact names are useful precisely because there is often
no overlap of information among speakers and hearers. The
alternative position for which the book argues is firmly
non-descriptivist, though it also does not require a referent. A
much broader view can be taken of which expressions are referring
expressions: not just names and pronouns used demonstratively, but
also some complex expressions and some anaphoric uses of pronouns.
Sainsbury's approach brings reference into line with truth: no one
would think that a semantic theory should associate a sentence with
a truth value, but it is commonly held that a semantic theory
should associate a sentence with a truth condition, a condition
which an arbitrary state of the world would have to satisfy in
order to make the sentence true. The right analogy is that a
semantic theory should associate a referring expression with a
reference condition, a condition which an arbitrary object would
have to satisfy in order to be the expression's referent. Lucid and
accessible, and written with a minimum of technicality, Sainsbury's
book also includes a useful historical survey. It will be of
interest to those working in logic, mind, and metaphysics as well
as essential reading for philosophers of language.
This book offers insight into the nature of meaningful discourse.
It presents an argument of great intellectual scope written by an
author with more than four decades of experience. Readers will gain
a deeper understanding into three theories of the logos: analytic,
dialectical, and oceanic. The author first introduces and contrasts
these three theories. He then assesses them with respect to their
basic parameters: necessity, truth, negation, infinity, as well as
their use in mathematics. Analytic Aristotelian logic has
traditionally claimed uniqueness, most recently in its Fregean and
post-Fregean variants. Dialectical logic was first proposed by
Hegel. The account presented here cuts through the dense, often
incomprehensible Hegelian text. Oceanic logic was never identified
as such, but the author gives numerous examples of its use from the
history of philosophy. The final chapter addresses the plurality of
the three theories and of how we should deal with it. The author
first worked in analytic logic in the 1970s and 1980s, first
researched dialectical logic in the 1990s, and discovered oceanic
logic in the 2000s. This book represents the culmination of
reflections that have lasted an entire scholarly career.
This book collects a renowned scholar's essays from the past five
decades and reflects two main concerns: an approach to logic that
stresses argumentation, reasoning, and critical thinking and that
is informal, empirical, naturalistic, practical, applied, concrete,
and historical; and an interest in Galileo's life and thought-his
scientific achievements, Inquisition trial, and methodological
lessons in light of his iconic status as "father of modern
science." These republished essays include many hard to find
articles, out of print works, and chapters which are not available
online. The collection provides an excellent resource of the
author's lifelong dedication to the subject. Thus, the book
contains critical analyses of some key Galilean arguments about the
laws of falling bodies and the Copernican hypothesis of the earth's
motion. There is also a group of chapters in which Galileo's
argumentation is compared and contrasted with that of other figures
such as Socrates, Karl Marx, Giordano Bruno, and his musicologist
father Vincenzo Galilei. The chapters on Galileo's trial illustrate
an approach to the science-vs-religion issue which Finocchiaro
labels "para-clerical" and conceptualizes in terms of a judicious
consideration of arguments for and against Galileo and the Church.
Other essays examine argumentation about Galileo's life and thought
by the major Galilean scholars of recent decades. The book will be
of interest to scholars in philosophy, logic, philosophy of
science, history of science, history of religion, philosophy of
religion, argumentation, rhetoric, and communication studies.
|
|