|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
For the Parmenidean monist, there are no distinctions
whatsoever-indeed, distinctions are unintelligible. In The
Parmenidean Ascent, Michael Della Rocca aims to revive this
controversial approach on rationalist grounds. He not only defends
the attribution of such an extreme monism to the pre-Socratic
philosopher Parmenides, but also embraces this extreme monism in
its own right and expands these monistic results to many of the
most crucial areas of philosophy, including being, action,
knowledge, meaning, truth, and metaphysical explanation. On Della
Rocca's account, there is no differentiated being, no
differentiated action, knowledge, or meaning; rather all is being,
just as all is action, all is knowledge, all is meaning. Motivating
this argument is a detailed survey of the failure of leading
positions (both historical and contemporary) to meet a demand for
the explanation of a given phenomenon, together with a powerful,
original version of a Bradleyan argument against the reality of
relations. The result is a rationalist rejection of all
distinctions and a skeptical denial of the intelligibility of
ordinary, relational notions of being, action, knowledge, and
meaning. Della Rocca then turns this analysis on the practice of
philosophy itself. Followed to its conclusion, Parmenidean monism
rejects any distinction between philosophy and the study of its
history. Such a conclusion challenges methods popular in the
practice of philosophy today, including especially the method of
relying on intuitions and common sense as the basis of
philosophical inquiry. The historically-minded and rationalist
approach used throughout the book aims to demonstrate the ultimate
bankruptcy of the prevailing methodology. It promises-on
rationalist grounds-to inspire much soul-searching on the part of
philosophers and to challenge the content and the methods of so
much philosophy both now and in the past.
With Ascent to the Beautiful, William H. F. Altman completes his
five-volume reconstruction of the Reading Order of the Platonic
dialogues. Although published last, this book covers Plato's
elementary dialogues, grappling from the start with F. D. E.
Schleiermacher, who created an enduring prejudice against the works
Plato wrote for beginners. Recognized in antiquity as the place to
begin, Alcibiades Major was banished from the canon but it was not
alone: with the exception of Protagoras and Symposium,
Schleiermacher rejected as inauthentic all seven of the dialogues
this book places between them. In order to prove their
authenticity, Altman illuminates their interconnections and shows
how each prepares the student to move beyond self-interest to
gallantry, and thus from the doctrinal intellectualism Aristotle
found in Protagoras to the emergence of philosophy as intermediate
between wisdom and ignorance in Symposium en route to Diotima's
ascent to the transcendent Beautiful. Based on the hypothesis that
it was his own eminently teachable dialogues that Plato taught-and
bequeathed to posterity as his Academy's eternal curriculum-Ascent
to the Beautiful helps the reader to imagine the Academy as a
school and to find in Plato the brilliant teacher who built on
Homer, Thucydides, and Xenophon.
Scientific and technological texts have not played a significant
role in modern literary criticism. This applies to Classics, too,
despite the fact that a large part of the field's extant texts deal
with questions of medicine, mathematics, and natural philosophy.
Focusing mostly on medical and mathematical texts, this collection
aims at approaching ancient Greek science and its texts from the
cross-disciplinary perspective of authorship. Among the questions
addressed are: What is a scientific author? In what respect does
scientific writing differ from 'literary' writing? How does the
author present himself as an authoritative figure through his text?
What strategies of trust do these authors employ? These and related
questions cannot be discussed within the typical boundaries of
modern academic disciplines, thus most of the sixteen authors, many
of them leading experts in the fields of ancient science, bring a
comparative perspective to their subjects. As a result, the
collection not only offers a new approach to this vast area of
ancient literature, thus effectively discovering new possibilities
for literary criticism, it also reflects on our current forms of
scientific and scholarly written communication.
The study of Roman society and social relations blossomed in the
1970s. By now, we possess a very large literature on the
individuals and groups that constituted the Roman community, and
the various ways in which members of that community interacted.
There simply is, however, no overview that takes into account the
multifarious progress that has been made in the past thirty-odd
years. The purpose of this handbook is twofold. On the one hand, it
synthesizes what has heretofore been accomplished in this field. On
the other hand, it attempts to configure the examination of Roman
social relations in some new ways, and thereby indicates directions
in which the discipline might now proceed.
The book opens with a substantial general introduction that
portrays the current state of the field, indicates some avenues for
further study, and provides the background necessary for the
following chapters. It lays out what is now known about the
historical development of Roman society and the essential
structures of that community. In a second introductory article,
Clifford Ando explains the chronological parameters of the
handbook. The main body of the book is divided into the following
six sections: 1) Mechanisms of Socialization (primary education,
rhetorical education, family, law), 2) Mechanisms of Communication
and Interaction, 3) Communal Contexts for Social Interaction, 4)
Modes of Interpersonal Relations (friendship, patronage,
hospitality, dining, funerals, benefactions, honor), 5) Societies
Within the Roman Community (collegia, cults, Judaism, Christianity,
the army), and 6) Marginalized Persons (slaves, women, children,
prostitutes, actors and gladiators, bandits). The result is a
unique, up-to-date, and comprehensive survey of ancient Roman
society.
In this new study, John Sellars offers a fresh examination of
Marcus Aurelius' Meditations as a work of philosophy by placing it
against the background of the tradition of Stoic philosophy to
which Marcus was committed. The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius is a
perennial bestseller, attracting countless readers drawn to its
unique mix of philosophical reflection and practical advice. The
emperor is usually placed alongside Seneca and Epictetus as one of
three great Roman Stoic authors, but he wears his philosophy
lightly, not feeling the need to state explicitly the ideas
standing behind the reflections that he was writing for himself. As
a consequence, his standing as a philosopher has often been
questioned. Challenging claims that Marcus Aurelius was merely an
eclectic thinker, that the Meditations do not fit the model of a
work of philosophy, that there are no arguments in the work, and
that it only contains superficial moral advice, Sellars shows that
he was in constant dialogue with his Stoic predecessors, engaging
with themes drawn from all three parts of Stoicism: logic, physics,
and ethics. The image of Marcus Aurelius that emerges is of a
committed Stoic, engaging with a wide range of philosophical
topics, motivated by the desire to live a good life. This volume
will be of interest to scholars and students of both Classics and
Philosophy.
'Our greatest blessings come to us by way of mania, provided it is
given us by divine gift,' - says Socrates in Plato's Phaedrus.
Certain forms of alteration of consciousness, considered to be
inspired by supernatural forces, were actively sought in ancient
Greece. Divine mania comprises a fascinating array of diverse
experiences: numerous initiates underwent some kind of alteration
of consciousness during mystery rites; sacred officials and
inquirers attained revelations in major oracular centres;
possession states were actively sought; finally, some thinkers,
such as Pythagoras and Socrates, probably practiced manipulation of
consciousness. These experiences, which could be voluntary or
involuntary, intense or mild, were interpreted as an invasive
divine power within one's mind, or illumination granted by a
super-human being. Greece was unique in its attitude to alteration
of consciousness. From the perspective of individual and public
freedom, the prominent position of the divine mania in Greek
society reflects its acceptance of the inborn human proclivity to
experience alteration of consciousness, interpreted in positive
terms as god-sent. These mental states were treated with cautious
respect, and in contrast to the majority of complex societies,
ancient and modern, were never suppressed or pushed to the cultural
and social periphery.
For anyone approaching the Encheiridion of Epictetus for the first
time, this book provides a comprehensive guide to understanding a
complex philosophical text. Including a full translation and clear
explanatory commentaries, Epictetus’s ‘Encheiridion’
introduces readers to a hugely influential work of Stoic
philosophy. Scott Aikin and William O. Stephens unravel the core
themes of Stoic ethics found within this ancient handbook. Focusing
on the core themes of self-control, seeing things as they are,
living according to nature, owning one’s roles and fulfilling the
responsibilities that those roles entail, the authors elucidate the
extremely challenging ideas in Epictetus’s brisk chapters.
Divided into five distinct parts, this book provides readers with:
- A new translation of the Encheiridion by William O. Stephens. - A
new introduction to ancient Stoicism, its system of concepts, and
the ancient figures who shaped it. - A fresh treatment of the
notorious and counter-intuitive ‘Stoic paradoxes’. - An
accessible overview of the origin and historical context of the
Encheiridion. - Detailed commentaries on each chapter of the
Encheiridion that clarify its recurring themes and highlight their
interconnections. - Careful attention to the presentation of the
arguments embedded in Epictetus’s aphoristic style. - A
thoughtful discussion of serious criticisms of Epictetus’s
Stoicism and replies to these objections. Written with clarity and
authority, Epictetus’s ‘Encheiridion’ provides a foundation
from which readers can understand this important text and engage
with the fundamental questions of Stoic philosophy and ethics. This
guide will aid teachers of Epictetus, students encountering
Stoicism for the first time, and readers seeking a greater
understanding of Stoic ethics.
The opponents of Epicureanism in antiquity, including Cicero,
Plutarch and Lactantius, succeeded in establishing a famous cliche:
the theoretical and practical disinterest of Epicurus and the
Epicureans in political communities. However, this anti-Epicurean
literature did not provide considerations of Epicurean political
theory or the testimonies about Epicurean lifestyle. The purpose of
this book is to shed light on the contribution of Epicurean thought
to political life in the ancient world. Incorporating the most
up-to-date material, including papyri which have been recovered
from Herculaneum, documents of Greek epigraphy and the
prosopography of the Roman Epicureans, this volume will bring to
the foreground new testimonies surrounding the public activities of
the Epicureans. In this way, the reader will learn that Epicurean
political theory is, in fact, a crucial ingredient of its
philosophy. As a result, this connection creates an ongoing
dialogue with the Greek philosophical tradition, revealing the
presence of Plato in the Epicurean philosophy.
What exactly distinguishes the good life? Is it pleasure? Is it
virtue? Is it wisdom? Or is it something else? Each of the ancient
philosophers of Greece and Rome had an answer, because for them it
was the most important question. "Stargazers" takes us into their
lives, depicting their efforts to understand the nature of ultimate
reality and to live a life in accord with that understanding. Thus
transported, we discover also the source of many of our own ideas
concerning the cosmos, God, humankind, and the flourishing life.
"Stargazers" is an invitation to return to the beginning, extended
cordially to all, but most especially to those who have yet to
encounter Plato's "dear delight," philosophy. The quest begins and
ends in wonder, and, along the way, reveals its power to transform
both our perception of the world and our way of living in it.
This book examines the birth of the scientific understanding of
motion. It investigates which logical tools and methodological
principles had to be in place to give a consistent account of
motion, and which mathematical notions were introduced to gain
control over conceptual problems of motion. It shows how the idea
of motion raised two fundamental problems in the 5th and 4th
century BCE: bringing together being and non-being, and bringing
together time and space. The first problem leads to the exclusion
of motion from the realm of rational investigation in Parmenides,
the second to Zeno's paradoxes of motion. Methodological and
logical developments reacting to these puzzles are shown to be
present implicitly in the atomists, and explicitly in Plato who
also employs mathematical structures to make motion intelligible.
With Aristotle we finally see the first outline of the fundamental
framework with which we conceptualise motion today.
This book features many of the leading voices championing the
revival of Neo-Aristotelian Ethical Naturalism (AN) in contemporary
philosophy. It addresses the whole range of issues facing this
research program at present. Coverage in the collection identifies
differentiations, details standpoints, and points out new
perspectives. This volume answers a need: AN is quite new to
contemporary philosophy, despite its deep roots in the history of
philosophy. As yet, there are many unanswered questions regarding
its relation to contemporary views in metaethics. It is certainly
not equivalent to dominant naturalistic approaches to metaethics in
Anglophone philosophy. Indeed, it is not obviously incompatible
with some approaches identified as nonnaturalistic. Further, there
are controversies regarding the views of the first wave of virtue
revivalists. The work of G.E.M. Anscombe and Philippa Foot is
frequently misunderstood, despite the fact that they are important
figures in the contemporary revival. This volume details a robust
approach to ethics by situating it within the context of human
life. It will help readers to better understand how AN raises deep
questions about the relation of action and its evaluation to human
nature. Neo-Aristotelians argue that something like the traditional
cardinal virtues, practical wisdom, temperance, justice and
courage, are qualities that perfect human reason and desire.
A landmark defense of democracy that has been hailed as one of the
most important books of the twentieth century One of the most
important books of the twentieth century, The Open Society and Its
Enemies is an uncompromising defense of liberal democracy and a
powerful attack on the intellectual origins of totalitarianism. An
immediate sensation when it was first published, Karl Popper's
monumental achievement has attained legendary status on both the
Left and Right. Tracing the roots of an authoritarian tradition
represented by Plato, Marx, and Hegel, Popper argues that the
spirit of free, critical inquiry that governs scientific
investigation should also apply to politics. In a new foreword,
George Soros, who was a student of Popper, describes the
"revelation" of first reading the book and how it helped inspire
his philanthropic Open Society Foundations.
By reconstructing it and tracing its vicissitudes, David Conway
rehabilitates a time-honoured conception of philosophy, originating
in Plato and Aristotle, which makes theoretical wisdom its aim.
Wisdom is equated with possessing a demonstrably correct
understanding of why the world exists and has the broad character
it does. Adherents of this conception maintained the world to be
the demonstrable creation of a divine intelligence in whose
contemplation supreme human happiness resides. Their claims are
defended against various latter day scepticisms.
Shortly after Aristotle's death, ancient philosophy shifted away
from abstract technical issues and focused on the more practical
moral question of how to be happy. While many schools of thought
arose on the subject, Stoicism and Epicureanism dominated the
philosophical landscape for nearly 500 years, often locked in
bitter rivalry with each other. Epicureanism advised pursing
pleasure as a means to happiness, and Stoicism held that true
happiness could only be achieved by accepting one's assigned lot in
life. The lasting impact of these philosophies is seen from that
fact that even today 'Stoic' and 'Epicurean' are household words.
Although the founder of Stoicism was an obscure Greek philosopher
who wrote nothing on the subject, his school consistently attracted
more followers than its Epicurean counterpart. Little, in fact,
survives of early Stoicism, and our knowledge of it comes largely
from a few later Stoics. In this unique book, William O. Stephens
explores the moral philosophy of Epictetus, a former Roman slave
and dynamic Stoic teacher whose writings are the most compelling
defence of ancient Stoicism that exists. Epictetus' philosophy
dramatically captures the spirit of Stoicism by examining our
greatest human disappointments, such as the death of a loved one.
Stephens shows how, for Epictetus, happiness results from focusing
our concern on what is up to us while not worrying about what is
beyond our control. He concludes that the strength of Epictetus'
philosophy lies in his conception of happiness as freedom from
fear, worry, grief, and dependence upon luck.
Marco Sgarbi tells a new history of epistemology from the
Renaissance to Newton through the impact of Aristotelian scientific
doctrines on key figures including Galileo Galilei, Thomas Hobbes,
Rene Descartes, John Locke, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz and Isaac
Newton. This history illuminates the debates philosophers had on
deduction, meditation, regressus, syllogism, experiment and
observation, the certainty of mathematics and the foundations of
scientific knowledge. Sgarbi focuses on the Aristotelian education
key philosophers received, providing a concrete historical
framework through which to read epistemological re-definitions,
developments and transformations over three centuries. The Age of
Epistemology further highlights how Aristotelianism itself changed
over time by absorbing doctrines from other philosophical
traditions and generating a variety of interpretations in the
process.
The significance of Plato's literary style to the content of his
ideas is perhaps one of the central problems in the study of Plato
and Ancient Philosophy as a whole. As Samuel Scolnicov points out
in this collection, many other philosophers have employed literary
techniques to express their ideas, just as many literary authors
have exemplified philosophical ideas in their narratives, but for
no other philosopher does the mode of expression play such a vital
role in their thought as it does for Plato. And yet, even after two
thousand years there is still no consensus about why Plato
expresses his ideas in this distinctive style. Selected from the
first Latin American Area meeting of the International Plato
Society (www.platosociety.org) in Brazil in 2012, the following
collection of essays presents some of the most recent scholarship
from around the world on the wide range of issues related to
Plato's dialogue form. The essays can be divided into three
categories. The first addresses general questions concerning
Plato's literary style. The second concerns the relation of his
style to other genres and traditions in Ancient Greece. And the
third examines Plato's characters and his purpose in using them.
This volume includes twelve studies by international specialists on
Aristotle and his commentators. Among the topics treated are
Aristotle's political philosophy and metaphysics, the ancient and
Byzantine commentators' scholia on Aristotle's logic, philosophy of
language and psychology as well as studies of broader scope on
developmentalism in ancient philosophy and the importance of
studying Late Antiquity.
One difficulty with interpreting Plato is that his philosophical
views are hidden within his dialogues and articulated through his
dramatic characters. Nowhere in the dialogues does Plato the
philosopher speak directly to his readers. One of the fundamental
tenets of Platonism is the assertion that 'virtue is knowledge'.
Yet Socrates and the other characters in the dialogues do not
maintain consistent views on the role of knowledge in virtue. This
book develops a new interpretation of the puzzling claim that
virtue is knowledge, while also providing a reading of the
dialogues as a whole which harmonizes the apparently diverse
statements of their various characters. Michael Cormack examines
dialogues from Plato's early and middle periods, emphasizing the
role knowledge plays in each. The most significant of Plato's
examples of knowledge is the type of knowledge possessed by the
craftsman. Using craft knowledge as a guide, Cormack illustrates
the similarities and differences between craft knowledge and
Plato's concept of moral knowledge - that specific type of
knowledge identified with virtue. While the Platonic conception of
virtue is widely recognized as the apprehension of universal
truths, this book illustrates how the dialogues reveal a number of
distinct degrees of understanding that correspond to distinct
degrees of virtue. The significance of this interpretation is that
Plato has not only revealed the goal of the philosophic life, but
has shown us the path - or the 'stepping stones' as he calls them
in the Republic - that we should follow to reach that goal.
In Plato's Socrates on Socrates: Socratic Self-Disclosure and the
Public Practice of Philosophy, Anne-Marie Schultz analyzes the
philosophical and political implications of Plato's presentation of
Socrates' self-disclosive speech in four dialogues: Theaetetus,
Symposium, Apology, and Phaedo. Schultz argues that these moments
of Socratic self-disclosure show that Plato's presentation of
"Socrates the narrator" is much more pervasive than the secondary
literature typically acknowledges. Despite the pervasive appearance
of a Socrates who describes his own experience throughout the
dialogues, Socratic autobiographical self-disclosure has received
surprisingly little scholarly attention. Plato's use of narrative,
particularly his trope of "Socrates the narrator," is often
subsumed into discussions of the dramatic nature of the dialogues
more generally rather than studied in its own right. Schultz shows
how these carefully crafted narrative remarks add to the richness
and profundity of the Platonic texts on multiple levels. To
illustrate how these embedded Socratic narratives contribute to the
portrait of Socrates as a public philosopher in Plato's dialogues,
the author also examines Socratic self-disclosive practices in the
works of bell hooks, Kathy Khang, and Ta-Neishi Coates, and even
practices the art of Socratic self-disclosure herself.
Plato and the Creation of the Hebrew Bible for the first time
compares the ancient law collections of the Ancient Near East, the
Greeks and the Pentateuch to determine the legal antecedents for
the biblical laws. Following on from his 2006 work, Berossus and
Genesis, Manetho and Exodus, Gmirkin takes up his theory that the
Pentateuch was written around 270 BCE using Greek sources found at
the Great Library of Alexandria, and applies this to an examination
of the biblical law codes. A striking number of legal parallels are
found between the Pentateuch and Athenian laws, and specifically
with those found in Plato's Laws of ca. 350 BCE. Constitutional
features in biblical law, Athenian law, and Plato's Laws also
contain close correspondences. Several genres of biblical law,
including the Decalogue, are shown to have striking parallels with
Greek legal collections, and the synthesis of narrative and legal
content is shown to be compatible with Greek literature. All this
evidence points to direct influence from Greek writings, especially
Plato's Laws, on the biblical legal tradition. Finally, it is
argued that the creation of the Hebrew Bible took place according
to the program found in Plato's Laws for creating a legally
authorized national ethical literature, reinforcing the importance
of this specific Greek text to the authors of the Torah and Hebrew
Bible in the early Hellenistic Era. This study offers a fascinating
analysis of the background to the Pentateuch, and will be of
interest not only to biblical scholars, but also to students of
Plato, ancient law, and Hellenistic literary traditions.
The Oxford Handbooks series is a major new initiative in academic
publishing. Each volume offers an authoritative and
state-of-the-art survey of current thinking and research in a
particular area. Specially commissioned essays from leading
international figures in the discipline give critical examinations
of the progress and direction of debates. Oxford Handbooks provide
scholars and graduate students with compelling new perspectives
upon a wide range of subjects in the humanities and social
sciences.
Plato is the best known, and continues to be the most widely
studied, of all the ancient Greek philosophers. The twenty-one
newly commissioned articles in the Oxford Handbook of Plato provide
in-depth and up-to-date discussions of a variety of topics and
dialogues. The result is a useful state-of-the-art reference to the
man many consider the most important philosophical thinker in
history.
Each article is an original contribution from a leading scholar,
and they all serve several functions at once: they survey the lay
of the land; express and develop the authors' own views; and
situate those views within a range of alternatives.
This Handbook contains chapters on metaphysics, epistemology,
love, language, ethics, politics, art and education. Individual
chapters are are devoted to each of the following dialogues: the
Republic, Parmenides, Theaetetus, Sophist, Timaeus, and Philebus.
There are also chapters on Plato and the dialogue form; on Plato in
his time and place; on the history of the Platonic corpus; on
Aristotle's criticism of Plato, and on Plato and Platonism.
|
You may like...
Oor Die Kole
Martelize Brink
Paperback
(1)
R495
R464
Discovery Miles 4 640
|