|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
This book investigates some of the central topics of metaphysics in
the philosophical thought of the Maya people of Mesoamerica,
particularly from the Preclassic through Postclassic periods. This
book covers the topics of time, change, identity, and truth,
through comparative investigation integrating Maya texts and
practices-such as Classic Period stelae, Postclassic Codices, and
Colonial-era texts such as the Popol Vuh and the books of Chilam
Balam-and early Chinese philosophy.
In this book, Mary Townsend proposes that, contrary to the current
scholarship on Plato's Republic, Socrates does not in fact set out
to prove the weakness of women. Rather, she argues that close
attention to the drama of the Republic reveals that Plato
dramatizes the reluctance of men to allow women into the public
sphere and offers a deeply aporetic vision of women's nature and
political position-a vision full of concern not only for the human
community, but for the desires of women themselves.
The" Posterior Analytics" contains Aristotle's Philosophy of
Science. In Book 2, Aristotle asks how the scientist discovers what
sort of loss of light constitutes lunar eclipse. The scientist has
to discover that the moon's darkening is due to the earth's shadow.
Once that defining explanation is known the scientist possesses the
full scientific concept of lunar eclipse and can use it to explain
other necessary features of the phenomenon. The present commentary,
arguably misascribed to Philoponus, offers some interpretations of
Aristotle that are unfamiliar nowadays. For example, the scientific
concept of a human is acquired from observing particular humans and
repeatedly receiving impressions in the sense image or percept and
later in the imagination. The impressions received are not only of
particular distinctive characteristics, like paleness, but also of
universal human characteristics, like rationality. Perception can
thus in a sense apprehend universal qualities in the individual as
well as particular ones.
"A history of philosophy in twelve thinkers...The whole performance
combines polyglot philological rigor with supple intellectual
sympathy, and it is all presented...in a spirit of fun...This
bracing and approachable book [shows] that there is life in
philosophy yet." -Times Literary Supplement "Exceptionally
engaging...Geuss has a remarkable knack for putting even familiar
thinkers in a new light." -Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews "Geuss
is something like the consummate teacher, his analyses navigable
and crystal, his guidance on point." -Doug Phillips, Key Reporter
Raymond Geuss explores the ideas of twelve philosophers who broke
dramatically with prevailing wisdom, from Socrates and Plato in the
ancient world to Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, and Adorno. The result is
a striking account of some of the most innovative thinkers in
Western history and an indirect manifesto for how to pursue
philosophy today. Geuss cautions that philosophers' attempts to
break from convention do not necessarily make the world a better
place. Montaigne's ideas may have been benign, but the fate of
those of Hobbes, Hegel, and Nietzsche has been more varied. Yet in
the act of provoking people to think differently, philosophers
remind us that we are not fated to live within the systems of
thought we inherit.
Seneca's Letters to Lucilius are a rich source of information about
ancient Stoicism, an influential work for early modern
philosophers, and a fascinating philosophical document in their own
right. This selection of the letters aims to include those which
are of greatest philosophical interest, especially those which
highlight the debates between Stoics and Platonists or
Aristotelians in the first century AD, and the issue, still
important today, of how technical philosophical enquiry is related
to the various purposes for which philosophy is practised. In
addition to examining the philosophical content of each letter,
Brad Inwood's commentary discusses the literary and historical
background of the letters and to their relationship with other
prose works by Seneca. Seneca is the earliest Stoic author for whom
we have access to a large number of complete works, and these works
were highly influential in later centuries. He was also a
politically influential advisor to the Roman emperor Nero and a
celebrated author of prose and verse. His philosophical acuity and
independence of mind make his works exciting and challenging for
the modern reader. CLARENDON LATER ANCIENT PHILOSOPHERS General
Editors: Jonathan Barnes and A. A. Long This series is designed to
encourage philosophers and students of philosophy to explore the
fertile terrain of later ancient philosophy. The texts range in
date from the first century BC to the fifth century AD, and will
cover all the parts and all the schools of philosophy. Each volume
contains a substantial introduction, an English translation, and a
critical commentary on the philosophical claims and arguments of
the text. The translations aim primarily at accuracy and fidelity;
but they are also readable and accompanied by notes on textual
problems that affect the philosophical interpretation. No knowledge
of Greek or Latin is assumed.
Jon D. Mikalson examines how Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and other
Greek philosophers described, interpreted, criticized, and utilized
the components and concepts of the religion of the people of their
time - practices such as sacrifice, prayer, dedications, and
divination. The chief concepts involved are those of piety and
impiety, and after a thorough analysis of the philosophical texts
Mikalson offers a refined definition of Greek piety, dividing it
into its two constituent elements of proper respect' for the gods
and religious correctness'. He concludes with a demonstration of
the benevolence of the gods in the philosophical tradition, linking
it to the expectation of that benevolence evinced by popular
religion.
The Oxford Translation of Aristotle was originally published in
12 volumes between 1912 and 1954. It is universally recognized as
the standard English version of Aristotle. This revised edition
contains the substance of the original Translation, slightly
emended in light of recent scholarship; three of the original
versions have been replaced by new translations; and a new and
enlarged selection of Fragments has been added. The aim of the
translation remains the same: to make the surviving works of
Aristotle readily accessible to English speaking readers.
After resolving to become a Catholic Christian, Augustine spent a
decade trying to clarify his understanding of 'contemplation,' the
interior presence of God to the soul. That long struggle yielded
his classic account in the Confessions. This study explores
Augustine's developing understanding of contemplation, beginning
with his earliest accounts written before his baptism and ending
with the Confessions. Chapter One examines the pagan monotheism of
the Roman Platonists and the role of contemplation in their
theology. Augustine's pre-baptismal writings are then considered in
Chapter Two, tracking his fundamental break from pagan Platonism.
Chapter Three then turns to Augustine's developing understanding of
contemplation in these pre-baptismal texts. Chapter Four
concentrates on Augustine's thought during the decade after his
baptism in 387, a period that encompasses his monastic life in
Thagaste, and his years first as a presbyter and then as a bishop
in Hippo Regius. This chapter follows the arc of Augustine's
thought through these years of transition and leads into the
Confessions, giving a vantage point to survey its theology of
contemplation. Chapter Five concentrates on the Confessions and
sets its most famous account of contemplation, the vision at Ostia
from Book IX, into a larger polemical context. Augustine's defence
of his transcendental reading of scripture in Confessions XII is
analysed and then used to illuminate the Ostian ascent narrative.
The book concludes with observations on the importance of
Augustine's theology of contemplation to the emergence of Christian
monotheism in late antiquity.
Scholars of classical philosophy have long disputed whether
Aristotle was a dialectical thinker. Most agree that Aristotle
contrasts dialectical reasoning with demonstrative reasoning, where
the former reasons from generally accepted opinions and the latter
reasons from the true and primary. Starting with a grasp on truth,
demonstration never relinquishes it. Starting with opinion, how
could dialectical reasoning ever reach truth, much less the truth
about first principles? Is dialectic then an exercise that
reiterates the prejudices of one's times and at best allows one to
persuade others by appealing to these prejudices, or is it the
royal road to first principles and philosophical wisdom? In From
Puzzles to Principles? May Sim gathers experts to argue both these
positions and offer a variety of interpretive possibilities. The
contributors' thoughtful reflections on the nature and limits of
dialectic should play a crucial role in Aristotelian scholarship.
Kathrin Koslicki offers an analysis of ordinary material objects,
those material objects to which we take ourselves to be committed
in ordinary, scientifically informed discourse. She focuses
particularly on the question of how the parts of such objects are
related to the wholes which they compose.
Many philosophers today find themselves in the grip of an
exceedingly deflationary conception of what it means to be an
object. According to this conception, any plurality of objects, no
matter how disparate or gerrymandered, itself composes an object,
even if the objects in question fail to exhibit interesting
similarities, internal unity, cohesion, or causal interaction
amongst each other.
This commitment to initially counterintuitive objects follows from
the belief that no principled set of criteria is available by means
of which to distinguish intuitively gerrymandered objects from
commonsensical ones; the project of this book is to persuade the
reader that systematic principles can be found by means of which
composition can be restricted, and hence that we need not embrace
this deflationary approach to the question of what it means to be
an object.
To this end, a more full-blooded neo-Aristotelian account of
parthood and composition is developed according to which objects
are structured wholes: it is integral to the existence and identity
of an object, on this conception, that its parts exhibit a certain
manner of arrangement. This structure-based conception of parthood
and composition is explored in detail, along with some of its
historical precursors as well as some of its contemporary
competitors.
This anthology brings together texts of significance for the
conceptualisation of human dignity as a constitutional principle in
Europe from the earliest evidence until 1965. It divides into four
parts, respectively presenting the ancient, the medieval, the early
modern and the modern sources. As far as human dignity is a
constitutional principle, its history follows closely that of the
constitution of states. However, various traditions of human
dignity, understanding it to rely on features unrelated to the
state, combine in the background to reflect the substance of the
idea. The introductions to texts, chapters and parts narrates this
history in relation to the texts presented to reflect it. The aim
is to provide for scholars and students of law, philosophy,
political science and theology a collection of texts documenting
the history of the concept of human dignity that is sufficiently
comprehensive to contextualise the various understandings of it. A
structured bibliography accompanies the work.
This volume is the first systematic study of Seneca's interaction
with earlier literature of a variety of genres and traditions. It
examines this interaction and engagement in his prose works,
offering interpretative readings that are at once groundbreaking
and stimulating to further study. Focusing on the Dialogues, the
Naturales quaestiones, and the Moral Epistles, the volume includes
multi- perspectival studies of Seneca's interaction with all the
great Latin epics (Lucretius, Vergil and Ovid), and discussions of
how Seneca's philosophical thought is informed by Hellenistic
doxography, forensic rhetoric and declamation, the Homeric
tradition, Euripidean tragedy and Greco-Roman mythology. The
studies analyzes the philosophy behind Seneca's incorporating exact
quotations from earlier tradition (including his criteria of
selectivity) and Seneca's interaction with ideas, trends and
techniques from different sources, in order to elucidate his
philosophical ideas and underscore his original contribution to the
discussion of established philosophical traditions. They also
provide a fresh interpretation of moral issues with particular
application to the Roman worldview as fashioned by the mos maiorum.
The volume, finally, features detailed discussion of the ways in
which Seneca, the author of philosophical prose, puts forward his
stance towards poetics and figures himself as a poet.
Intertextuality in Seneca's Philosophical Writings will be of
interest not only to those working on Seneca's philosophical works,
but also to anyone working on Latin literature and intertextuality
in the ancient world.
This book addresses the problem of fully explaining Socrates'
motives for philosophic interlocution in Plato's dialogues. Why,
for instance, does Socrates talk to many philosophically immature
and seemingly incapable interlocutors? Are his motives in these
cases moral, prudential, erotic, pedagogic, or intellectual? In any
one case, can Socrates' reasons for engaging an unlikely
interlocutor be explained fully on the grounds of intellectual
self-interest (i.e., the promise of advancing his own wisdom)? Or
does his activity, including his self-presentation and staging of
his death, require additional motives for adequate explanation?
Finally, how, if at all, does our conception of Socrates' motives
help illuminate our understanding of the life of reason as Plato
presents it? By inviting a multitude of authors to contribute their
thoughts on these question-all of whom share a commitment to close
reading, but by no means agree on the meaning of Plato's
dialogues-this book provides the reader with an excellent map of
the terrain of these problems and aims to help the student of Plato
clarify the tensions involved, showing especially how each major
stance on Socrates entails problematic assumptions that prompt
further critical reflection.
|
You may like...
Republic
Plato
Paperback
R95
R76
Discovery Miles 760
|