|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
A compelling and fascinating portrait of the continuing
intellectual tradition of Greek writers and thinkers in the Age of
Rome. In 146 BC, Greece yielded to the military might of the Roman
Republic; sixty years later, when Athens and other Greek
city-states rebelled against Rome, the general Lucius Cornelius
Sulla destroyed the city of Socrates and Plato, laying waste to the
famous Academy where Aristotle had studied. However, the traditions
of Greek cultural life would continue to flourish during the
centuries of Roman rule that followed, in the lives and work of a
distinguished array of philosophers, doctors, scientists,
geographers, travellers and theologians. Charles Freeman's accounts
of such luminaries as the physician Galen, the geographer Ptolemy
and the philosopher Plotinus are interwoven with contextual
'interludes' that showcase a sequence of unjustly neglected and
richly influential lives. Like the author's The Awakening, The
Children of Athena is a cultural history on an epic scale: the
story of a rich and vibrant tradition of Greek intellectual inquiry
across a period of more than five hundred years, from the second
century BC to the start of the fifth century AD.
Plato's Theaetetus and Sophist are two of his most important
dialogues, and are widely read and discussed by philosophers for
what they reveal about his epistemology and particularly his
accounts of belief and knowledge. Although they form part of a
single Platonic project, these dialogues are not usually presented
as a pair, as they are in Christopher Rowe's new and lively
translation. Offering a high standard of accuracy and readability,
the translation reveals the continuity between these dialogues and
others in the Platonic corpus, especially the Republic. The
supporting introduction and notes help the reader to follow the
arguments as they develop, explaining their structure, context and
interpretation. This new edition challenges current scholarly
approaches to Plato's work and will pave the way for fresh
interpretations both of Theaetetus and Sophist and of Plato's
writings in general.
"Pleasure in Aristotle's Ethics" provides an innovative and
crucially important account of the role of pleasure and desire in
Aristotle's ethics. Michael Weinman seeks to overcome common
impasses in the mainstream interpretation of Aristotle's ethical
philosophy through the careful study of Aristotle's account of
pleasure in the human, but not merely human, good, thus presenting
a new way in which we can improve our understanding of Aristotle's
ethics. Weinman asserts that we should read Aristotle's ethical
arguments in the light of his views on the cosmos (the living whole
we call nature) and the never-changing principles informing that
living whole. Weinman shows that what, above all else, emerges from
this new re-reading of the ethical writings is a new understanding
of human desire as the natural stretching ourselves toward
pleasure, which is the good, and which is the good by nature. These
lessons will demonstrate why we must understand the virtues as
unified, why the good described in "Nicomachean Ethics" is both a
human and greater-than-human good, and why the reasoning and
desiring parts of the soul must be understood as companions. The
necessary but as yet unrealised account of pleasure this book
advances is integral to improving our understanding of Aristotle's
ethics. This fascinating book will be of interest to anyone with an
interest in Aristotle's ethical theory and in particular his
"Nicomachean Ethics".
Platonism and Christian Thought in Late Antiquity examines the
various ways in which Christian intellectuals engaged with
Platonism both as a pagan competitor and as a source of
philosophical material useful to the Christian faith. The chapters
are united in their goal to explore transformations that took place
in the reception and interaction process between Platonism and
Christianity in this period. The contributions in this volume
explore the reception of Platonic material in Christian thought,
showing that the transmission of cultural content is always
mediated, and ought to be studied as a transformative process by
way of selection and interpretation. Some chapters also deal with
various aspects of the wider discussion on how Platonic, and
Hellenic, philosophy and early Christian thought related to each
other, examining the differences and common ground between these
traditions. Platonism and Christian Thought in Late Antiquity
offers an insightful and broad ranging study on the subject, which
will be of interest to students of both philosophy and theology in
the Late Antique period, as well as anyone working on the reception
and history of Platonic thought, and the development of Christian
thought.
This book shows how the discussion of Platos' Republic is a comic
mimetic cure for civic and psychic delusion. Plato creates such
pharmaka, or noble lies, for reasons enunciated by Socrates within
the discussion, but this indicates Plato must think his readers are
in the position of needing the catharses such fictions produce.
Socrates' interlocutors must be like us. Since cities are like
souls, and souls come to be as they are through mimesis of desires,
dreams, actions and thought patterns in the city, we should expect
that political theorizing often suffers from madness as well. It
does. Gene Fendt shows how contemporary political (and
psychological) theory still suffers from the same delusion
Socrates' interlocutors reveal in their discussion: a dream of
autarchia called possessive individualism. Plato has good reason to
think that only a mimetic, rather than a rational and
philosophical, cure can work. Against many standard readings, Comic
Cure for Delusional Democracy shows that the Republic itself is a
defense of poetry; that kallipolis cannot be the best city and is
not Socrates' ideal; that there are six forms of regime, not five;
and that the true philosopher should not be unhappy to go back down
into Plato's cave.
This book offers a novel defence of a highly contested
philosophical position: biological natural kind essentialism. This
theory is routinely and explicitly rejected for its purported
inability to be explicated in the context of contemporary
biological science, and its supposed incompatibility with the
process and progress of evolution by natural selection. Christopher
J. Austin challenges these objections, and in conjunction with
contemporary scientific advancements within the field of
evolutionary-developmental biology, the book utilises a
contemporary neo-Aristotelian metaphysics of "dispositional
properties", or causal powers, to provide a theory of essentialism
centred on the developmental architecture of organisms and its role
in the evolutionary process. By defending a novel theory of
Aristotelian biological natural kind essentialism, Essence in the
Age of Evolution represents the fresh and exciting union of
cutting-edge philosophical insight and scientific knowledge.
This book explores the origins of western biopolitics in ancient
Greek political thought. Ojakangas's argues that the conception of
politics as the regulation of the quantity and quality of
population in the name of the security and happiness of the state
and its inhabitants is as old as the western political thought
itself: the politico-philosophical categories of classical thought,
particularly those of Plato and Aristotle, were already
biopolitical categories. In their books on politics, Plato and
Aristotle do not only deal with all the central topics of
biopolitics from the political point of view, but for them these
topics are the very keystone of politics and the art of government.
Yet although the Western understanding of politics was already
biopolitical in classical Greece, the book does not argue that the
history of biopolitics would constitute a continuum from antiquity
to the twentieth century. Instead Ojakangas argues that the birth
of Christianity entailed a crisis of the classical biopolitical
rationality, as the majority of classical biopolitical themes
concerning the government of men and populations faded away or were
outright rejected. It was not until the renaissance of the
classical culture and literature - including the translation of
Plato's and Aristotles political works into Latin - that
biopolitics became topical again in the West. The book will be of
great interest to scholars and students in the field of social and
political studies, social and political theory, moral and political
philosophy, IR theory, intellectual history, classical studies.
In studies of early Christian thought, 'philosophy' is often a
synonym for 'Platonism', or at most for 'Platonism and Stoicism'.
Nevertheless, it was Aristotle who, from the sixth century AD to
the Italian Renaissance, was the dominant Greek voice in Christian,
Muslim and Jewish philosophy. Aristotle and Early Christian Thought
is the first book in English to give a synoptic account of the slow
appropriation of Aristotelian thought in the Christian world from
the second to the sixth century. Concentrating on the great
theological topics - creation, the soul, the Trinity, and
Christology - it makes full use of modern scholarship on the
Peripatetic tradition after Aristotle, explaining the significance
of Neoplatonism as a mediator of Aristotelian logic. While
stressing the fidelity of Christian thinkers to biblical
presuppositions which were not shared by the Greek schools, it also
describes their attempts to overcome the pagan objections to
biblical teachings by a consistent use of Aristotelian principles,
and it follows their application of these principles to matters
which lay outside the purview of Aristotle himself. This volume
offers a valuable study not only for students of Christian theology
in its formative years, but also for anyone seeking an introduction
to the thought of Aristotle and its developments in Late Antiquity.
This new edition introduces the reader to the philosophy of early
Christianity in the second to fourth centuries AD, and
contextualizes the philosophical contributions of early Christians
in the framework of the ancient philosophical debates. It examines
the first attempts of Christian thinkers to engage with issues such
as questions of cosmogony and first principles, freedom of choice,
concept formation, and the body-soul relation, as well as later
questions like the status of the divine persons of the Trinity. It
also aims to show that the philosophy of early Christianity is part
of ancient philosophy as a distinct school of thought, being in
constant dialogue with the ancient philosophical schools, such as
Platonism, Aristotelianism, Stoicism, and even Epicureanism and
Scepticism. This book examines in detail the philosophical views of
Christian thinkers such as Justin Martyr, Clement of Alexandria,
Irenaeus, Tertullian, Origen, Basil, and Gregory of Nyssa, and
sheds light in the distinct ways they conceptualized traditional
philosophical issues and made some intriguing contributions. The
book's core chapters survey the central philosophical concerns of
the early Christian thinkers and examines their contributions.
These range across natural philosophy, metaphysics, logic and
epistemology, psychology, and ethics, and include such questions as
how the world came into being, how God relates to the world, the
status of matter, how we can gain knowledge, in what sense humans
have freedom of choice, what the nature of soul is and how it
relates to the body, and how we can attain happiness and salvation.
This revised edition takes into account the recent developments in
the area of later ancient philosophy, especially in the philosophy
of Early Christianity, and integrates them in the relevant
chapters, some of which are now heavily expanded. The Philosophy of
Early Christianity remains a crucial introduction to the subject
for undergraduate and postgraduate students of ancient philosophy
and early Christianity, across the disciplines of classics,
history, and theology.
This book offers a new account of Aristotle's practical philosophy.
Pavlos Kontos argues that Aristotle does not restrict practical
reason to its action-guiding and motivational role; rather,
practical reason remains practical in the full sense of the term
even when its exercise does not immediately concern the guidance of
our present actions. To elucidate why this wider scope of practical
reason is important, Kontos brings into the foreground five
protagonists that have long been overlooked: (a) spectators or
judges who make non-motivational judgments about practical matters
that do not interact with their present deliberations and actions;
(b) legislators who exercise practical reason to establish
constitutions and laws; (c) hopes as an active engagement with
moral luck and its impact on our individual lives; (d) prayers as
legislators' way to deal with the moral luck hovering around the
birth of constitutions and the prospect of a utopia; and (e) people
who are outsiders or marginal cases of the responsibility community
because they are totally deprived of practical reason. Building on
a wide range of interpretations of Aristotle's practical philosophy
(from the ancient commentators to contemporary analytic and
continental philosophers), Kontos offers new insights about
Aristotle's philosophical contribution to the current debates about
radical evil, moral luck, hope, utopia, internalism and
externalism, and the philosophy of law. Aristotle on the Scope of
Practical Reason will appeal to researchers and advanced students
interested in Aristotle's ethics, ancient philosophy, and the
history of practical philosophy.
Lucretius's long shadow falls across the disciplines of literary
history and criticism, philosophy, religious studies, classics,
political philosophy, and the history of science. The best recent
example is Stephen Greenblatt's popular account of the Roman poet's
De Rerum Natura (On the Nature of Things) rediscovery by Poggio
Bracciolini, and of its reception in early modernity, winner of
both a Pulitzer Prize and National Book Award. Despite the poem's
newfound influence and visibility, very little cross-disciplinary
conversation has taken place. This edited collection brings
together essays by distinguished scholars to examine the
relationship between Lucretius and modernity. Key questions weave
this book's ideas and arguments together: What is the relation
between literary form and philosophical argument? How does the text
of De rerum natura allow itself to be used, at different historical
moments and to different ends? What counts as reason for Lucretius?
Together, these essays present a nuanced, skeptical, passionate,
historically sensitive, and complicated account of what is at stake
when we claim Lucretius for modernity.
This installment of the distinguished RUSCH series focuses on two
Peripatetic philosophers of the fourth and third centuries BCE:
namely, Chamaeleon and Praxiphanes, both of whom were associated
with Theophrastus, Aristotle's successor as head of the Peripatetic
School. Chamaeleon and Praxiphanes were intellectuals active in the
political and civic life of the Hellenistic Period. Their scholarly
interests included inter alia ethics, biography, textual criticism,
and linguistics. The work presents new editions of the ancient
source texts for Chamaeleon and Praxiphanes. Each is accompanied by
an apparatus of textual variants and a second apparatus of parallel
texts. In addition, there is a facing translation in English as
well as notes to the translation. There follow ten essays that
clarify material presented in the text translation. The volume
closes with an index listing the ancient sources that are referred
to the preceding essays. This volume continues over thirty years of
tradition in the RUSCH series, edited by William W. Fortenbaugh,
the finest series available in Aristotelian studies.
First published in 1991, The Greatest Happiness Principle traces
the history of the theory of utility, starting with the Bible, and
running through Plato, Aristotle, and Epicurus. It goes on to
discuss the utilitarian theories of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart
Mill in detail, commenting on the latter's view of the Christianity
of his day and his optimal socialist society. The book argues that
the key theory of utility is fundamentally concerned with
happiness, stating that discussions of happiness have been largely
left out of discussions of utility, it also argues utility as a
moral theory, posing the question ultimately, what is happiness?
This collection of essays engages with several topics in
Aristotle's philosophy of mind, some well-known and hotly debated,
some new and yet to be explored. The contributors analyze
Aristotle's arguments and present their cases in ways that invite
contemporary philosophers of mind to consider the potentials-and
pitfalls-of an Aristotelian philosophy of mind. The volume brings
together an international group of renowned Aristotelian scholars
as well as rising stars to cover five main themes: method in the
philosophy of mind, sense perception, mental representation,
intellect, and the metaphysics of mind. The papers collected in
this volume, with their choice of topics and quality of exposition,
show why Aristotle is a philosopher of mind to be studied and
reckoned with in contemporary discussions. Encounters with
Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind will be of interest to scholars and
advanced students of ancient philosophy and philosophy of mind.
This book examines the relationship between athletics and
philosophy in ancient Greece and Rome focused on the connection
between athleticism and virtue. It begins by observing that the
link between athleticism and virtue is older than sport, reaching
back to the athletic feats of kings and pharaohs in early Egypt and
Mesopotamia. It then traces the role of athletics and the Olympic
Games in transforming the idea of aristocracy as something acquired
by birth to something that can be trained. This idea of training
virtue through the techniques and practice of athletics is examined
in relation to Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. Then Roman
spectacles such as chariot racing and gladiator games are studied
in light of the philosophy of Lucretius, Seneca, and Marcus
Aurelius. The concluding chapter connects the book's ancient
observations with contemporary issues such as the use of athletes
as role models, the relationship between money and corruption, the
relative worth of participation and spectatorship, and the role of
females in sport. The author argues that there is a strong link
between sport and philosophy in the ancient world, calling them
offspring of common parents: concern about virtue and the spirit of
free enquiry. This book was previously published as a special issue
of the Ethics and Sport.
Xenophon's Socratic Works demonstrates that Xenophon, a student of
Socrates, military man, and man of letters, is an indispensable
source for our understanding of the life and philosophy of
Socrates. David M. Johnson restores Xenophon's most ambitious
Socratic work, the Memorabilia (Socratic Recollections), to its
original literary context, enabling readers to experience it as
Xenophon's original audience would have, rather than as a pale
imitation of Platonic dialogue. He shows that the Memorabilia,
together with Xenophon's Apology, provides us with our best
evidence for the trial of Socrates, and a comprehensive and
convincing refutation of the historical charges against Socrates.
Johnson's account of Socrates' moral psychology shows how
Xenophon's emphasis on control of the passions can be reconciled
with the intellectualism normally attributed to Socrates. Chapters
on Xenophon's Symposium and Oeconomicus (Estate Manager) reveal how
Xenophon used all the literary tools of Socratic dialogue to defend
Socratic sexual morality (Symposium) and debate the merits and
limits of conventional elite values (Oeconomicus). Throughout the
book, Johnson argues that Xenophon's portrait of Socrates is rich
and coherent, and largely compatible with the better-known portrait
of Socrates in Plato. Xenophon aimed not to provide a rival
portrait of Socrates, Johnson shows, but to supplement and clarify
what others had said about Socrates. Xenophon's Socratic Works,
thus, provides readers with a far firmer basis for reconstruction
of the trial of Socrates, a key moment in the history of Athenian
democracy, and for our understanding of Socrates' seminal impact on
Greek philosophy. This volume introduces Xenophon's Socratic works
to a wide range of readers, from undergraduate students
encountering Socrates or ancient philosophy for the first time to
scholars with interests in Socrates or ancient philosophy more
broadly. It is also an important resource for readers interested in
Socratic dialogue as a literary form, the trial of Socrates, Greek
sexual morality (the central topic of Xenophon's Symposium), or
Greek social history (for which the Oeconomicus is a key text).
At the crisis of his Republic, Plato asks us to imagine what could
possibly motivate a philosopher to return to the Cave voluntarily
for the benefit of others and at the expense of her own personal
happiness. This book shows how Plato has prepared us, his students,
to recognize that the sun-like Idea of the Good is an infinitely
greater object of serious philosophical concern than what is merely
good for me, and thus why neither Plato nor his Socrates are
eudaemonists, as Aristotle unquestionably was. With the
transcendent Idea of Beauty having been made manifest through
Socrates and Diotima, the dialogues between Symposium and
Republic-Lysis, Euthydemus, Laches, Charmides, Gorgias, Theages,
Meno, and Cleitophon- prepare the reader to make the final leap
into Platonism, a soul-stirring idealism that presupposes the
student's inborn awareness that there is nothing just, noble, or
beautiful about maximizing one's own good. While perfectly capable
of making the majority of his readers believe that he endorses the
harmless claim that it is advantageous to be just and thus that we
will always fare well by doing well, Plato trains his best students
to recognize the deliberate fallacies and shortcuts that underwrite
these claims, and thus to look beyond their own happiness by the
time they reach the Allegory of the Cave, the culmination of a
carefully prepared Ascent to the Good.
Pyrrhonian Buddhism reconstructs the path to enlightenment shared
both by early Buddhists and the ancient Greek sceptics inspired by
Pyrrho of Elis, who may have had extended contacts with Buddhists
when he accompanied Alexander the Great to India in the third
century BCE. This volume explores striking parallels between early
Buddhism and Pyrrhonian scepticism, suggesting their virtual
identity. Both movements saw beliefs-fictions mistaken for
truths-as the principal source of human suffering. Both practiced
suspension of judgment about beliefs to obtain release from
suffering, and to achieve enlightenment, which the Buddhists called
bodhi and the Pyrrhonists called ataraxia. And both came to
understand the structure of human experience without belief, which
the Buddhists called dependent origination and the Pyrrhonists
described as phenomenalistic atomism. This book is intended for the
general reader, as well as historians, classicists, Buddhist
scholars, philosophers, and practitioners of spiritual techniques.
This book critically examines the recent discussions of powers and
powers-based accounts of causation. The author then develops an
original view of powers-based causation that aims to be compatible
with the theories and findings of natural science. Recently, there
has been a dramatic revival of realist approaches to properties and
causation, which focus on the relevance of Aristotelian metaphysics
and the notion of powers for a scientifically informed view of
causation. In this book, R.D. Ingthorsson argues that one central
feature of powers-based accounts of causation is arguably
incompatible with what is today recognised as fact in the sciences,
notably that all interactions are thoroughly reciprocal.
Ingthorsson's powerful particulars view of causation accommodates
for the reciprocity of interactions. It also draws out the
consequences of that view for issue of causal necessity and offers
a way to understand the constitution and persistence of compound
objects as causal phenomena. Furthermore, Ingthorsson argues that
compound entities, so understood, are just as much processes as
they are substances. A Powerful Particulars View of Causation will
be of great interest to scholars and advanced students working in
metaphysics, philosophy of science, and neo-Aristotelian
philosophy, while also being accessible for a general audience. The
Open Access version of this book, available at
http://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/9781003094241, has been made
available under a Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial-No
Derivatives 4.0 license.
This is the first volume of essays devoted to Aristotelian formal
causation and its relevance for contemporary metaphysics and
philosophy of science. The essays trace the historical development
of formal causation and demonstrate its relevance for contemporary
issues, such as causation, explanation, laws of nature, functions,
essence, modality, and metaphysical grounding. The introduction to
the volume covers the history of theories of formal causation and
points out why we need a theory of formal causation in contemporary
philosophy. Part I is concerned with scholastic approaches to
formal causation, while Part II presents four contemporary
approaches to formal causation. The three chapters in Part III
explore various notions of dependence and their relevance to formal
causation. Part IV, finally, discusses formal causation in biology
and cognitive sciences. Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on Formal
Causation will be of interest to advanced graduate students and
researchers working on contemporary Aristotelian approaches to
metaphysics and philosophy of science. This volume includes
contributions by Jose Tomas Alvarado, Christopher J. Austin,
Giacomo Giannini, Jani Hakkarainen, Ludger Jansen, Markku Keinanen,
Gyula Klima, James G. Lennox, Stephen Mumford, David S. Oderberg,
Michele Paolini Paoletti, Sandeep Prasada, Petter Sandstad,
Wolfgang Sattler, Benjamin Schnieder, Matthew Tugby, and Jonas
Werner.
Die Bibliotheca Teubneriana, gegrundet 1849, ist die weltweit
alteste, traditionsreichste und umfangreichste Editionsreihe
griechischer und lateinischer Literatur von der Antike bis zur
Neuzeit. Pro Jahr erscheinen 4-5 neue Editionen. Samtliche Ausgaben
werden durch eine lateinische oder englische Praefatio erganzt. Die
wissenschaftliche Betreuung der Reihe obliegt einem Team
anerkannter Philologen: Gian Biagio Conte (Scuola Normale Superiore
di Pisa) Marcus Deufert (Universitat Leipzig) James Diggle
(University of Cambridge) Donald J. Mastronarde (University of
California, Berkeley) Franco Montanari (Universita di Genova)
Heinz-Gunther Nesselrath (Georg-August-Universitat Goettingen)
Oliver Primavesi (Ludwig-Maximilians Universitat Munchen) Michael
D. Reeve (University of Cambridge) Richard J. Tarrant (Harvard
University) Vergriffene Titel werden als Print-on-Demand-Nachdrucke
wieder verfugbar gemacht. Zudem werden alle Neuerscheinungen der
Bibliotheca Teubneriana parallel zur gedruckten Ausgabe auch als
eBook angeboten. Die alteren Bande werden sukzessive ebenfalls als
eBook bereitgestellt. Falls Sie einen vergriffenen Titel bestellen
moechten, der noch nicht als Print-on-Demand angeboten wird,
schreiben Sie uns an: [email protected] Samtliche in
der Bibliotheca Teubneriana erschienenen Editionen lateinischer
Texte sind in der Datenbank BTL Online elektronisch verfugbar.
Ancient and Medieval Philosophy Series 2, No. 37The
Stadsbibliotheek of Brugge houses a manuscript (ms. 510, f.
227ra-237vb) that holds a short logical text on the
Syncategoremata. In this manuscript the text is ascribed to Henry
of Ghent, who was a leading thinker of the second half of the
thirteenth century. If Henry wrote the text, he had much more
technical knowledge of logic and semantics than is often imagined.
The text was influenced by the logical works of Peter of Spain."
|
You may like...
The Stranded
Sarah Daniels
Paperback
R215
R170
Discovery Miles 1 700
Wonderfully Made
Tshwanelo Serumola
Paperback
(1)
R160
R145
Discovery Miles 1 450
|