|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy is an annual publication which
includes original articles, which may be of substantial length, on
a wide range of topics in ancient philosophy, and review articles
of major books. Contributors to this volume; Paul A. Vander Waerdt,
Christopher Rowe, Rachel Rue, Paula Gottlieb, Robert Bolton, and
John M. Cooper.
 |
Daodejing
(Hardcover)
Lao zi; Translated by Brook Ziporyn
|
R674
Discovery Miles 6 740
|
Ships in 12 - 19 working days
|
|
Grounded in a lifetime of research and interpretive work and
informed by careful study of recent archaeological discoveries of
alternate versions of the text, Brook Ziporyn, one of the
preeminent explicators of Eastern religions in English, brings us a
revelatory new translation-and a radical reinterpretation-of the
central text of Taoist thought. Ziporyn offers an alternative to
the overly comforting tone of so many translations, revealing
instead the electrifying strangeness and explosively unsettling
philosophical implications of this famously ambiguous work. In
Ziporyn's hands, this is no mere "wisdom book" of anodyne
affirmations or mildly diverting brain-teasers-this pathbreaking
Daodejing will forever change how the text is read and understood
in the West.
 |
Simplicius: On Aristotle Physics 1.5-9
(Hardcover)
Han Baltussen; Translated by Han Baltussen; Edited by Michael Atkinson; Translated by Michael Atkinson; Edited by Michael Share; Translated by …
|
R5,261
Discovery Miles 52 610
|
Ships in 12 - 19 working days
|
|
In the chapters of his 'Physics' commented on here, Aristotle
disagrees with Pre-Socratic philosophers about the basic principles
that explain natural changes. But he finds some agreement among
them that at least two contrary properties must be involved, for
example hot and cold. His own view is that there are two contrary
principles at a more abstract level: the form possessed at the end
of a change and the privation of that form at the beginning. But
there is also a third principle needed to supply continuity - the
matter to which first privation and later form belong. Despite the
apparent disagreements, Simplicius, the Neoplatonist commentator,
wants to emphasise the harmony of all pagan Greek thinkers, as
opposed to Christians, on such a basic matter as first principles.
He therefore presents not only the Pre-Socratics and Aristotle, but
also himself and earlier commentators of different schools as all
in basic agreement.
In this radical reinterpretation of Aristotle's Metaphysics, Walter
E. Wehrle demonstrates that developmental theories of Aristotle are
based on a faulty assumption: that the fifth chapter of Categories
('substance') is an early theory of metaphysics that Aristotle
later abandoned. The ancient commentators unanimously held that the
Categories was semantical and not metaphysical, and so there was no
conflict between it and the Metaphysics proper. They were right,
Wehrle argues: the modern assumption, to the contrary, is based on
a medieval mistake and is perpetuated by the anti-metaphysical
postures of contemporary philosophy. Furthermore, by using the
logico-semantical distinction in Aristotle's works, Wehrle shows
just how the principal 'contradictions' in Metaphysics Books VII
and VIII can be resolved. The result in an interpretation of
Aristotle that challenges mainstream viewpoints, revealing a
supreme philosopher in sharp contrast to the developmentalists'
version.
This book contains nine essays on Lucius Annaeus Seneca,
distinguished Stoic Philosopher, creative writer, and Statesman of
the Neronian Age. As author of epistles, treatises, dialogues,
dramas, and epigrams, he produced a variety of works that enriched
Rome's literary achievement. Like the previous volumes -- Essays on
Seneca (Peter Lang, 1993) and Further Essays on Seneca (Peter Lang,
2001) -- this book presents an in-depth analysis of the Cordoban
Philosopher's thoughts and portrays his erudition, humanitas,
artistry, and deep psychological understanding of the frailties and
strengths of human nature.
First published in 1948, Philosophical Studies presents a
collection of essays written by friends and colleagues of Professor
L. Susan Stebbing in the Aristotelian Society. Most of these essays
do not bear directly on Professor Stebbings' work, but they deal
with problems which she discussed time and again at the Society's
meetings. It explores themes like moral ends and means; reflections
occasioned by ideals and illusions; reason in history; the logic of
elucidation; logic and semantics; philosophy of nature; and
epistemology and the ego-centric predicament. This book is a must
read for students and scholars of Philosophy.
Luke and the Politics of Homeric Imitation: Luke-Acts as Rival to
the Aeneid argues that the author of Luke-Acts composed not a
history but a foundation mythology to rival Vergil's Aeneid by
adopting and ethically emulating the cultural capital of classical
Greek poetry, especially Homer's Iliad and Odyssey and Euripides's
Bacchae. For example, Vergil and, more than a century later, Luke
both imitated Homer's account of Zeus's lying dream to Agamemnon,
Priam's escape from Achilles, and Odysseus's shipwreck and visit to
the netherworld. Both Vergil and Luke, as well as many other
intellectuals in the Roman Empire, engaged the great poetry of the
Greeks to root new social or political realities in the soil of
ancient Hellas, but they also rivaled Homer's gods and heroes to
create new ones that were more moral, powerful, or compassionate.
One might say that the genre of Luke-Acts is an oxymoron: a prose
epic. If this assessment is correct, it holds enormous importance
for understanding Christian origins, in part because one may no
longer appeal to the Acts of the Apostles for reliable historical
information. Luke was not a historian any more than Vergil was,
and, as the Latin bard had done for the Augustine age, he wrote a
fictional portrayal of the kingdom of God and its heroes,
especially Jesus and Paul, who were more powerful, more ethical,
and more compassionate than the gods and heroes of Homer and
Euripides or those of Vergil's Aeneid.
W.K.C. Guthrie has written a survey of the great age of Greek
philosophy - from Thales to Aristotle - which combines
comprehensiveness with brevity. Without pre-supposing a knowledge
of Greek or the Classics, he sets out to explain the ideas of Plato
and Aristotle in the light of their predecessors rather than their
successors, and to describe the characteristic features of the
Greek way of thinking and outlook on the world. Thus The Greek
Philosophers provides excellent background material for the general
reader - as well as providing a firm basis for specialist studies.
The Sceptics is the first comprehensive, up-to-date treatment of
Greek scepticism, from the beginnings of epistemology with
Xenophanes, to the final full development of Pyrrhonism as
presented in the work of Sextus Empiricus. Tracing the evolution of
scepticism from 500 B.C to A.D 200, this clear and rigorous
analysis presents the arguments of the Greek sceptics in their
historical context and provides an in-depth study of the various
strands of the sceptical tradition.
Originally published in 1991, this book focuses on the concept of
virtue, and in particular on the virtue of wisdom or knowledge, as
it is found in the epic poems of Homer, some tragedies of
Sophocles, selected writings of Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoic and
Epicurean philosophers. The key questions discussed are the nature
of the virtues, their relation to each other, and the relation
between the virtues and happiness or well-being. This book provides
the background and interpretative framework to make classical works
on Ethics, such as Plato's Republic and Aristotle's Nicomachean
Ethics, accessible to readers with no training in the classics.
This book studies the pilgrimage of the Ancient World in its search
for moral truth. After a brief examination of the values which
dominated Homeric society and the subsequent aristocracies, the
central portion of the book is an account and analysis of the moral
ideas which illuminated the Greek, Roman and Hebrew worlds during
the classical period. The volume discusses the cardinal virtues,
the place of friendship, Plato's love, philanthropia and the moral
insights of the Jewish prophets and subsequently examines Christian
love.
Plato and the Creation of the Hebrew Bible for the first time
compares the ancient law collections of the Ancient Near East, the
Greeks and the Pentateuch to determine the legal antecedents for
the biblical laws. Following on from his 2006 work, Berossus and
Genesis, Manetho and Exodus, Gmirkin takes up his theory that the
Pentateuch was written around 270 BCE using Greek sources found at
the Great Library of Alexandria, and applies this to an examination
of the biblical law codes. A striking number of legal parallels are
found between the Pentateuch and Athenian laws, and specifically
with those found in Plato's Laws of ca. 350 BCE. Constitutional
features in biblical law, Athenian law, and Plato's Laws also
contain close correspondences. Several genres of biblical law,
including the Decalogue, are shown to have striking parallels with
Greek legal collections, and the synthesis of narrative and legal
content is shown to be compatible with Greek literature. All this
evidence points to direct influence from Greek writings, especially
Plato's Laws, on the biblical legal tradition. Finally, it is
argued that the creation of the Hebrew Bible took place according
to the program found in Plato's Laws for creating a legally
authorized national ethical literature, reinforcing the importance
of this specific Greek text to the authors of the Torah and Hebrew
Bible in the early Hellenistic Era. This study offers a fascinating
analysis of the background to the Pentateuch, and will be of
interest not only to biblical scholars, but also to students of
Plato, ancient law, and Hellenistic literary traditions.
Modern literary theory is increasingly looking to philosophy for
its inspiration. After a wave of structural analysis, the growing
influence of deconstruction and hermeneutic readings continues to
bear witness to this. This exciting and important collection, first
published in 1988, reveals the diversity of approaches that mark
the post-structuralist endeavour, and provides a challenge to the
conventional practice of classical studies and ancient philosophy.
This book will be of interest to students of ancient philosophy,
classical studies and literary theory.
This book, originally published in 1991, sets forth the assumptions
about thought and language that made falsehood seem so problematic
to Plato and his contemporaries, and expounds the solution that
Plato finally reached in the Sophist. Free from untranslated Greek,
the book is accessible to all studying ancient Greek philosophy. As
a well-documented case study of a definitive advance in logic,
metaphysics and epistemology, the book will also appeal to
philosophers generally.
Forms, Souls, and Embryos allows readers coming from different
backgrounds to appreciate the depth and originality with which the
Neoplatonists engaged with and responded to a number of
philosophical questions central to human reproduction, including:
What is the causal explanation of the embryo's formation? How and
to what extent are Platonic Forms involved? In what sense is a
fetus 'alive,' and when does it become a human being? Where does
the embryo's soul come from, and how is it connected to its body?
This is the first full-length study in English of this fascinating
subject, and is a must-read for anyone interested in Neoplatonism
or the history of medicine and embryology.
The last several decades have witnessed an explosion of research in
Platonic philosophy. A central focus of his philosophical effort,
Plato's psychology is of interest both in its own right and as
fundamental to his metaphysical and moral theories. This anthology
offers, for the first time, a collection of the best classic and
recent essays on cenral topics of Plato's psychological theory,
including essays on the nature of the soul, studies of the
tripartite soul for which Plato argues in the Republic, and
analyses of his varied arguments for immortality. With a
comprehensive introduction to the major issues of Plato's
psychology and an up-to-date bibliography of work on the relevant
issues, this much-needed text makes the study of Plato's psychology
accessible to scholars in ancient Greek philosophy, classics, and
history of psychology.
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy is a volume of original
articles on all aspects of ancient philosophy. The articles may be
of substantial length, and include critical notices of major books.
From 2000, OSAP is being published not once but twice yearly, to
keep up with the abundance of good material submitted; and it is
being made available in paperback as well as hardback, in response
to demand from scholars wishing to purchase it. This volume, the
first of 2000, features contributors from Britain, America, Europe,
and Japan contributing pieces on Socrates, Plato, Aristotle,
Epicureanism, Pyrrhonism, and the recently discovered papyrus text
of Empedocles.
Syrianus, originally from Alexandria, moved to Athens and became
the head of the Academy there after the death of Plutarch of
Athens. In discussing "Aristotle's 'Metaphysics' 3-4", shows how
metaphysics, as a philosophical science, was conceived by the
Neoplatonic philosopher of Late Antiquity. The questions raised by
Aristotle in "Metaphysics" 3 as to the scope of metaphysics are
answered by Syrianus, who also criticizes the alternative answers
explored by Aristotle.In presenting "Metaphysics" 4, Syrianus
explains in what sense metaphysics deals with 'being as being' and
how this includes the essential attributes of being
(unity/multiplicity, sameness/difference, etc.), showing also that
it comes within the scope of metaphysics to deal with the primary
axioms of scientific thought, in particular the Principle of
Non-Contradiction, for which Syrianus provides arguments additional
to those developed by Aristotle. Syrianus thus reveals how
Aristotelian metaphysics was formalized and transformed by a
philosophy which found its deepest roots in Pythagoras and Plato.
Themistius' treatment of "Books 5-8" of Aristotle's "Physics" shows
this commentator's capacity to identify, isolate and discuss the
core ideas in Aristotle's account of change, his theory of the
continuum, and his doctrine of the unmoved mover. His paraphrase
offered his ancient students, as they will now offer his modern
readers, an opportunity to encounter central features of
Aristotle's physical theory, synthesized and epitomized in a manner
that has always marked Aristotelian exegesis but was raised to a
new level by the innovative method of paraphrase pioneered by
Themistius. Taking selective but telling account of the earlier
Peripatetic tradition (notably Theophrastus and Alexander of
Aphrodisias), this commentator creates a framework that can still
be profitably used by Aristotlian scholars today.
John T. Hogan's The Tragedy of the Athenian Ideal in Thucydides and
Plato assesses the roles of Pericles, Alcibiades, and Nicias in
Athens' defeat in Thucydides' Peloponnesian War. Comparing
Thucydides' presentation of political leadership with ideas in
Plato's Statesman as well as Laches, Charmides, Meno, Symposium,
Republic, Phaedo, Sophist, and Laws, it concludes that Plato and
Thucydides reveal Pericles as lacking the political discipline
(sophrosune) to plan a successful war against Sparta. Hogan argues
that in his presentation of the collapse in the Corcyraean
revolution of moral standards in political discourse, Thucydides
shows how revolution destroys the morality implied in basic
personal and political language. This reveals a general collapse in
underlying prudential measurements needed for sound moral judgment.
Furthermore, Hogan argues that the Statesman's outline of the
political leader serves as a paradigm for understanding the
weaknesses of Pericles, Alcibiades, and Nicias in terms that
parallel Thucydides' direct and implied conclusions, which in
Pericles' case he highlights with dramatic irony. Hogan shows that
Pericles failed both to develop a sufficiently robust practice of
Athenian democratic rule and to set up a viable system for
succession.
Roslyn Weiss contends that, contrary to prevailing notions, Plato's Crito does not show an allegiance between Socrates and the state that condemned him. Weiss argues that Socrates considers the laws of the state to be more concerned with creating deference than justice, and asserts that, by submitting to his judgement, Socrates acts from a personal sense of justice rather than a set of imposed rules.
Throughout the history of philosophy, skepticism has posed one of
the central challenges of epistemology. Opponents of
skepticism--including externalists, contextualists,
foundationalists, and coherentists--have focussed largely on one
particular variety of skepticism, often called Cartesian or
Academic skepticism, which makes the radical claim that nobody can
know anything. However, this version of skepticism is something of
a straw man, since virtually no philosopher endorses this radical
skeptical claim. The only skeptical view that has been truly
held--by Sextus, Montaigne, Hume, Wittgenstein, and, most recently,
Robert Fogelin--has been Pyrrohnian skepticism. Pyrrhonian skeptics
do not assert Cartesian skepticism, but neither do they deny it.
The Pyrrhonian skeptics' doubts run so deep that they suspend
belief even about Cartesian skepticism and its denial. Nonetheless,
some Pyrrhonians argue that they can still hold "common beliefs of
everyday life" and can even claim to know some truths in an
everyday way.
This edited volume presents previously unpublished articles on this
subject by a strikingly impressive group of philosophers, who
engage with both historical and contemporary versions of Pyrrhonian
skepticism. Among them are Gisela Striker, Janet Broughton, Don
Garrett, Ken Winkler, Hans Sluga, Ernest Sosa, Michael Williams,
Barry Stroud, Robert Fogelin, and Roy Sorensen. This volume is
thematically unified and will interest a broad spectrum of scholars
in epistemology and the history of philosophy.
Throughout history philosophers have sought to define, understand,
and delineate concepts important to human well-being. One such
concept is "knowledge." Many philosophers believed that absolute,
certain knowledge, is possible--that the physical world and ideas
formulated about it could be given solid foundation unaffected by
the varieties of mere opinion.
Sextus Empiricus stands as an example of the "skeptic" school of
thought whose members believed that knowledge was either
unattainable or, if a genuine possibility, the conditions necessary
to achieve it were next to impossible to satisfy. In other words,
in the absence of complete knowledge, one must make do with the
information provided by an imperfect world and conveyed to the mind
through sense impressions that can often deceive us. Throughout his
life Sextus Empiricus entered into intellectual combat with those
who confidently claimed to possess indubitable knowledge. For
skeptics, the best one can hope to achieve is a reasonable
suspension of judgment--remaining ever mindful that claims to
knowledge require careful scrutiny, thoughtful analysis, and
critical review if we are to prevent ourselves and others from
plunging headlong into mistaken notions.
|
You may like...
Meditations
Marcus Aurelius
Paperback
R131
Discovery Miles 1 310
Republic
Plato
Paperback
R95
R85
Discovery Miles 850
|