|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Philosophy of mind
This edited collection provides the first comprehensive volume on
A. J. Ayer's 1936 masterpiece, Language, Truth and Logic. With
eleven original chapters the volume reconsiders the historical and
philosophical significance of Ayer's work, examining its place in
the history of analytic philosophy and its subsequent legacy.
Making use of pioneering research in logical empiricism, the
contributors explore a wide variety of topics, from ethics, values
and religion, to truth, epistemology and philosophy of language.
Among the questions discussed are: How did Ayer preserve or distort
the views and conceptions of logical empiricists? How are Ayer's
arguments different from the ones he aimed at reconstructing? And
which aspects of the book were responsible for its immense impact?
The volume expertly places Language, Truth and Logic in the
intellectual and socio-cultural history of twentieth-century
philosophical thought, providing both introductory and contextual
chapters, as well as specific explorations of a variety of topics
covering the main themes of the book. Providing important insights
of both historical and contemporary significance, this collection
is an essential resource for scholars interested in the legacy of
the Vienna Circle and its effect on ethics and philosophy of mind.
This book presents a theoretical critical appraisal of the
Mechanistic Theory of Human Cognition (MTHC), which is one of the
most popular major theories in the contemporary field of cognitive
science. It analyses and evaluates whether MTHC provides a unifying
account of human cognition and its explanation. The book presents a
systematic investigation of the internal and external consistency
of the theory, as well as a systematic comparison with other
contemporary major theories in the field. In this sense, it
provides a fresh look at more recent major theoretical debates in
this area of scientific research and a rigorous analysis of one of
its most central major theories. Rigorous theoretical work is
integrated with objective consideration of relevant empirical
evidence, making the discussions robust and clear. As a result, the
book shows that MTHC provides a significant theoretical
contribution for the field of cognitive science. The content is
useful for those interested in theoretical and empirical issues
concerning major theories in the contemporary field of cognitive
science.
This book presents a new structural approach to the psychology of
the person, inspired by Kenneth Colby's computer-generated
simulation, PARRY. The simulation was of a paranoid psychological
state, represented in forms of the person's logic and syntax, as
these would be evidenced in personal communication. Harwood Fisher
uses a Structural View to highlight similarities in the logical
form of the linguistic representations of Donald Trump, his avid
followers ("Trumpers"), and the paranoid-referred to as "The Trio."
He demonstrates how the Structural View forms a series of logical
and schematic patterns, similar to the way that content analysis
can bring forth associations meanings, and concepts held in the
text. Such comparisons, Fisher argues, can be used to shed light on
contingencies for presenting, representing, and judging truth.
Specifically, Fisher posits that the major syntactic and logical
patterns that were used to produce the computer-generated
"paranoid" responses in Colby's project can be used to analyze
Donald Trump's rhetoric and his followers' reactions to it.
Ultimately, Fisher offers a new kind of structural approach for the
philosophy of psychology. This novel work will appeal to students
and scholars of social and cognitive psychology, psychology of
personality, psychiatric classification, psycholinguistics,
rhetoric, and computer science.
This is a comprehensive reference guide to current research in
Philosophy of Mind, assembled by an international team of leading
scholars in the discipline. From new questions concerning qualia,
representation, embodiment and cognition to fresh thinking about
the long-standing problems of physicalism, dualism, personal
identity and mental causation, this book is an authoritative guide
to the latest research in the Philosophy of Mind. Across twelve
entries, experts in the field explore the current thinking in one
of the most active areas of interest in philosophy today. To aid
researchers further, the Companion also includes overviews of
perennial problems and new directions in contemporary philosophy of
mind, an extended glossary of terms for quick reference, a detailed
chronology, a guide to research for ongoing study and a
comprehensive bibliography of key classic and contemporary
publications in the philosophy of mind. "The Continuum Companions"
series is a major series of single volume companions to key
research fields in the humanities aimed at postgraduate students,
scholars and libraries. Each companion offers a comprehensive
reference resource giving an overview of key topics, research
areas, new directions and a manageable guide to beginning or
developing research in the field. A distinctive feature of the
series is that each companion provides practical guidance on
advanced study and research in the field, including research
methods and subject-specific resources.
Understanding emotions is becoming ever more valuable in design,
both in terms of what people prefer as well as in relation to how
they behave in relation to it. Approaches to conceptualising
emotions in technology design, how emotions can be operationalised
and how they can be measured are paramount to ascertaining the core
principles of design. Emotions in Technology Design: From
Experience to Ethics provides a multi-dimensional approach to
studying, designing and comprehending emotions in design. It
presents emotions as understood through basic human-technology
research, applied design practice, culture and aesthetics, ethical
approaches to emotional design, and ethics as a cultural framework
for emotions in design experience. Core elements running through
the book are: cognitive science - cognitive-affective theories of
emotions (i.e., Appraisal); culture - the ways in which our minds
are trained to recognise, respond to and influence design; and
ethics - a deep cultural framework of interpretations of good
versus evil. This ethical understanding brings culture and
cognition together to form genuine emotional experience. This book
is essential reading for designers, technology developers, HCI and
cognitive science scholars, educators and students (at both
undergraduate and graduate levels) in terms of emotional design
methods and tools, systematic measurement of emotion in design
experience, cultural theory underpinning how emotions operate in
the production and interaction of design, and how ethics influence
basic (primal) and higher level emotional reactions. The broader
scope equips design practitioners, developers and scholars with
that 'something more' in terms of understanding how emotional
experience of technology can be positioned in relation to cultural
discourse and ethics.
"Philadelphia A Story Sequence in Verse" is a window on the work of
esoteric schools. It portrays a small, representative group of
loving friends who at first naively and later decisively with the
potent ancient knowledge in which they have been instructed engage
in storytelling's highest purpose: to remind and remind and remind
us again to remember and hold ourselves aware of what our busy
minds are always forgetting - the present, where the divine
resides. John Craig, the author, is a poet and teacher who with his
wife Victoria,a native of Phila-delphia,lives in the Sierra
foothills of northern California. They have two grown sons.
This book defends the much-disputed view that emotions are what
Hume referred to as 'original existences': feeling states that have
no intentional or representational properties of their own. In
doing so, the book serves as a valuable counterbalance to the now
mainstream view that emotions are representational mental states.
Beginning with a defence of a feeling theory of emotion, Whiting
opens up a whole new way of thinking about the role and centrality
of emotion in our lives, showing how emotion is key to a proper
understanding of human motivation and the self. Whiting establishes
that emotions as types of bodily feelings serve as the categorical
bases for our behavioural dispositions, including those associated
with moral thought, virtue, and vice. The book concludes by
advancing the idea that emotions make up our intrinsic nature - the
characterisation of what we are like in and of ourselves, when
considered apart from how we are disposed to behave. The conclusion
additionally draws out the implications of the claims made
throughout the book in relation to our understanding of mental
illness and the treatment of emotional disorders.
When instruments are harmoniously joined together, beautiful music
ensues. Just as in a classic symphony, life often occurs in phases,
or movements. In his creative comparison Symphony #1 in a Minor
Key, literary exegete Alan Block shares his philosophies on four
movements reflected in his own life, each loosely modeled on a
different musical form linked to the emotions of a life both fully
lived and joyously celebrated. In the first movement, "Sonata
Allegro," Block juxtaposes biblical stories with personal
experiences as he explores the contradictory nature of what it
means to leave home in search of another home. In the second
movement, representing a slow march to and from the grave, he
focuses his examination on the funerals of three very different
people from a Jewish perspective. In strong contrast, Block
presents a glimpse into his absurd daily world in the third
movement, punctuated by jokes and commentary. Finally, he shares a
celebration of life and hope inspired by the final movement of
Beethoven's Seventh Symphony, encouraging others to be open to the
sublime and realize that none of our worlds is perfect. Symphony #1
in a Minor Key shares one man's reflections as he offers a
fascinating meditation on life, death, and everything in between.
This book, taking its point of departure from Stanley Cavell's
claim that philosophy and autobiography are dimensions of each
other, aims to explore some of the relations between these forms of
reflection, first by seeking to develop an outline of a philosophy
of autobiography, and then by exploring the issue from the side of
five autobiographical works. Christopher Hamilton argues in the
volume that there are good reasons for thinking that philosophical
texts can be considered autobiographical, and then turns to discuss
the autobiographies of Walter Benjamin, Peter Weiss, Jean-Paul
Sartre, George Orwell, Edmund Gosse and Albert Camus. In discussing
these works, Hamilton explores how they put into question certain
received understandings of what philosophical texts suppose
themselves to be doing, and also how they themselves constitute
philosophical explorations of certain key issues, e.g. the self,
death, religious and ethical consciousness, sensuality, the body.
Throughout, there is an exploration of the ways in which
autobiographies help us in thinking about self-knowledge and
knowledge of others. A final chapter raises some issues concerning
the fact that the five autobiographies discussed here are all texts
dealing with childhood.
This edited book focuses on concepts and their applications using
the theory of conceptual spaces, one of today's most central tracks
of cognitive science discourse. It features 15 papers based on
topics presented at the Conceptual Spaces @ Work 2016 conference.
The contributors interweave both theory and applications in their
papers. Among the first mentioned are studies on metatheories,
logical and systemic implications of the theory, as well as
relations between concepts and language. Examples of the latter
include explanatory models of paradigm shifts and evolution in
science as well as dilemmas and issues of health, ethics, and
education. The theory of conceptual spaces overcomes many
translational issues between academic theoretization and practical
applications. The paradigm is mainly associated with structural
explanations, such as categorization and meronomy. However, the
community has also been relating it to relations, functions, and
systems. The book presents work that provides a geometric model for
the representation of human conceptual knowledge that bridges the
symbolic and the sub-conceptual levels of representation. The model
has already proven to have a broad range of applicability beyond
cognitive science and even across a number of disciplines related
to concepts and representation.
Could robots be genuinely intelligent? Could they be conscious?
Could there be zombies? Prompted by these questions Robert Kirk
introduces the main problems of consciousness and sets out a new
approach to solving them. He starts by discussing behaviourism,
Turing's test of intelligence and Searle's famous Chinese Room
argument, and goes on to examine dualism - the idea that
consciousness requires something beyond the physical - together
with its opposite, physicalism. Probing the idea of zombies, he
concludes they are logically impossible. Having presented the
central problems, he sketches his solution: a version of
functionalism, according to which consciousness consists in the
performance of functions. While there is wide agreement among
philosophers about what the main problems of consciousness are,
there is little agreement on how to go about solving them. With
this powerful case for his version of functionalism, Kirk offers an
engaging introduction to both the problems and a possible solution.
This book is an attempt to make sense of the tension in Nietzsche's
work between the unashamedly egocentric and the apparently
mystical. While scholars have tended to downplay one or other of
these aspects, it is the author's contention that the two are not
only compatible but mutually illuminating. This book demonstrates
Nietzsche's sustained interest in mysticism from the time of The
Birth of Tragedy right through to the end of his productive life.
This book argues against situating Nietzsche's religious thought in
the context of Buddhist or Christian mystical traditions,
demonstrating the inadequacy of attempts to mediate between
Nietzsche and Meister Eckhart and the Bodhisattva ideal of Mahayana
Buddhism. Rather, it is argued that Nietzsche's egoism and
mysticism are best understood in the intellectual context which he
himself avowed, according to which his "ancestors" were Heraclitus,
Empedocles, Spinoza, and Goethe.
What is consciousness and why is it so philosophically and
scientifically puzzling? For many years philosophers approached
this question assuming a standard physicalist framework, on which
consciousness can be explained by contemporary physics, biology,
neuroscience and cognitive science. This book is a debate between
two philosophers who are united in their rejection this kind of
"standard" physicalism- but who differ sharply in what lesson to
draw from this. Amy Kind defends dualism 2.0, a thoroughly modern
version of dualism (the theory that there are two fundamentally
different kinds of things in the world, those that are physical and
those that are mental) decoupled from any religious or
non-scientific connotations. Daniel Stoljar defends non-standard
physicalism, a kind of physicalism different from both the standard
version and dualism 2.0. The book presents a cutting-edge
assessment of the philosophy of consciousness, and a glimpse at
what the future study of this area might bring. Key Features
Outlines the different things people mean by 'consciousness' and
provides an account of what consciousness is Reviews the key
arguments for thinking that consciousness is incompatible with
physicalism Explores and provides a defense of contrasting
responses to those arguments, with a special focus on responses
that reject the standard physicalist framework Provides an account
of the basic aims of the science of consciousness Written in a
lively and accessibly style Includes a comprehensive glossary
This book examines what seems to be the basic challenge in
neuroscience today: understanding how experience generated by the
human brain is related to the physical world we live in. The 25
short chapters present the argument and evidence that brains
address this problem on a wholly trial and error basis. The goal is
to encourage neuroscientists, computer scientists, philosophers,
and other interested readers to consider this concept of neural
function and its implications, not least of which is the conclusion
that brains don't "compute."
Plato’s Timaeus is unique in Greek Antiquity for presenting the
creation of the world as the work of a divine demiurge. The maker
bestows order on sensible things and imitates the world of the
intellect by using the Forms as models. While the creation-myth of
the Timaeus seems unparalleled, this book argues that it is not the
first of Plato’s dialogues to use artistic language to articulate
the relationship of the objects of the material world to the world
of the intellect. The book adopts an interpretative angle that is
sensitive to the visual and art-historical developments of
Classical Athens to argue that sculpture, revolutionized by the
advent of the lost-wax technique for the production of bronze
statues, lies at the heart of Plato’s conception of the relation
of the human soul and body to the Forms. It shows that, despite the
severe criticism of mimēsis in the Republic, Plato’s use of
artistic language rests on a positive model of mimēsis. Plato was
in fact engaged in a constructive dialogue with material culture
and he found in the technical processes and the cultural semantics
of sculpture and of the art of weaving a valuable way to
conceptualise and communicate complex ideas about humans’
relation to the Forms.
This book shows how persecution is a condition that binds each in
an ethical obligation to the other. Persecution is functionally
defined here as an impinging, affective relation that is not
mediated by reason. It focuses on the works and personal lives of
Emmanuel Levinas-a phenomenological ethicist who understood
persecution as an ontological condition for human existence-and
Sigmund Freud, the inventor of psychoanalysis who proposed that a
demanding superego is a persecuting psychological mechanism that
enables one to sadistically enjoy moral injunctions. Scholarship on
the work of Freud and Levinas remains critical about their
objectivity, but this book uses the phenomenological method to
bracket this concern with objective truth and instead reconstruct
their historical biographies to evaluate their hyperbolically
opposing claims. By doing so, it is suggested that moral actions
and relations of persecution in their personal lives illuminate the
epistemic limits that they argued contribute to the psychological
and ontological necessity of persecuting behaviors. Object
relations and intersubjective approaches in psychoanalysis
successfully incorporate meaningful elements from both of their
theoretical works, which is used to develop an intentionality of
search that is sensitive to an unknowable, relational, and
existentially vulnerable ethical subjectivity. Details from Freud's
and Levinas' works and lives, on the proclivity to use persecution
to achieve moral ends, provide significant ethical warnings, and
the author uses them as a strategy for developing the reader's
intentionality of search, to reflect on when they may use
persecuting means for moral ends. The interdisciplinary nature of
this research monograph is intended for academics, scholars, and
researchers who are interested in psychoanalysis, moral philosophy,
and phenomenology. Comparisons between various psychoanalytic
frameworks and Levinas' ethic will also interest scholars who work
on the relation between psychoanalysis and The Other. Levinas
scholars will value the convergences between his ethics and Freud's
moral skepticism; likewise, readers will be interested in the
extension of Levinas' intentionality of search. The book is useful
for undergraduate or graduate courses on literary criticism and
critical theories worldwide.
|
|