|
Books > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Philosophy of mind
Stephen Schiffer presents a groundbreaking account of meaning and
belief, and shows how it can illuminate a range of crucial problems
regarding language, mind, knowledge, and ontology. He introduces
the new doctrine of 'pleonastic propositions' to explain what the
things we mean and believe
are. He discusses the relation between semantic and psychological
facts, on the one hand, and physical facts, on the other; vagueness
and indeterminacy; moral truth; conditionals; and the role of
propositional content in information acquisition and explanation.
This radical new treatment of meaning
will command the attention of everyone who works on fundamental
questions about language, and will attract much interest from other
areas of philosophy.
This text develops a philosophical theory of imagination that draws
upon the latest work in psychology. This theory illuminates the use
of imagination in coming to terms with art, its role in enabling us
to live as social beings, and the psychological consequences of
disordered imagination. Currie and Ravenscroft offer a lucid
exploration of the subject for readers in philosophy, psychology
and aesthetics.
Montesquieu and the Spirit of Rome argues that the
eighteenth-century French author Charles-Louis de Secondat, Baron
de La Brede et de Montesquieu (1689-1755) developed a novel,
comprehensive account of Roman history that framed his new
political science and grounded his political teachings. Rome's
legacy in early-modern thought turns on the work of Montesquieu,
and through Rome Montesquieu articulated the strengths and
weaknesses of the modern state-the moderation that can distinguish
it and sources of extremism that must haunt it. This book is the
first to unify Montesquieu's Roman thoughts; it is the first to
reconstruct the Rome that was one of his most powerful legacies in
the 18th and 19th centuries. Montesquieu and the Spirit of Rome
restores Rome to its proper place at the peak of Montesquieu's
thought and Montesquieu's thought to its proper place in the
history of classical study. It treats Montesquieu as what he
claimed to be-a jurist, a poet, a historian, and a political writer
of the first rank, and it revives his hard-nosed defence of
moderation.
Why does the world look to us as it does? Generally speaking, this
question has received two types of answers in the cognitive
sciences in the past fifty or so years. According to the first, the
world looks to us the way it does because we construct it to look
as it does. According to the second, the world looks as it does
primarily because of how the world is. In The Innocent Eye, Nico
Orlandi defends a position that aligns with this second,
world-centered tradition, but that also respects some of the
insights of constructivism. Orlandi develops an embedded
understanding of visual processing according to which, while visual
percepts are representational states, the states and structures
that precede the production of percepts are not representations. If
we study the environmental contingencies in which vision occurs,
and we properly distinguish functional states and features of the
visual apparatus from representational states and features, we
obtain an empirically more plausible, world-centered account.
Orlandi shows that this account accords well with models of vision
in perceptual psychology - such as Natural Scene Statistics and
Bayesian approaches to perception - and outlines some of the ways
in which it differs from recent 'enactive' approaches to vision.
The main difference is that, although the embedded account
recognizes the importance of movement for perception, it does not
appeal to action to uncover the richness of visual stimulation. The
upshot is that constructive models of vision ascribe mental
representations too liberally, ultimately misunderstanding the
notion. Orlandi offers a proposal for what mental representations
are that, following insights from Brentano, James and a number of
contemporary cognitive scientists, appeals to the notions of
de-coupleability and absence to distinguish representations from
mere tracking states.
In Self, Value, and Narrative, Anthony Rudd defends a series of
interrelated claims about the nature of the self. He argues that
the self is not simply a given entity, but a being that constitutes
or shapes itself. But it can only do this non-arbitrarily if it has
a sense of the good by which it can be guided as it chooses to
endorse some of its desires or dispositions and repudiate others.
This means that there is an essentially ethical or evaluative
dimension to selfhood, and one which has an essentially
teleological character. Such self-constitution takes place in
narrative terms, through one's telling-and, more importantly,
living-one's own story. Versions of some or all of these ideas have
been developed by various influential writers (including Frankfurt,
Korsgaard, MacIntyre, Ricoeur, and Taylor) but Rudd develops these
ideas in a way that is importantly different from others familiar
in the literature. He takes his main inspiration from Kierkegaard's
account of the self, and argues (controversially) that this account
belongs in the Platonic rather than the Aristotelian tradition of
teleological thinking. Through close engagement with much
contemporary philosophical work, Rudd presents a convincing case
for an ancient and currently unfashionable view: that the
polarities and tensions that are constitutive of selfhood can only
be reconciled through an orientation of the self as a whole to an
objective Good.
HarperCollins is proud to present its incredible range of
best-loved, essential classics. Our life is what our thoughts make
it The extraordinary writings of Marcus Aurelius (AD 121-180), the
only Roman emperor to have also been a stoic philosopher, have for
centuries been praised for their wisdom, insight and guidance by
leaders and great thinkers alike. Never intended for publication,
Meditations are the personal notes born from a man who studied his
unique position of power as emperor while trying to uphold inner
balance in the chaotic world around him. Boldly challenging many of
our biggest questions, Aurelius wrestles with the divided self,
considering the complexities of human nature, rationality and moral
virtue, affirming its place as one of the most timeless,
significant works of philosophy to date.
Within the contemporary philosophical debates over the nature of
perception, the question of whether perception has content in the
first place recently has become a focus of discussion. The most
common view is that it does, but a number of philosophers have
questioned this claim. The issue immediately raises a number of
related questions. What does it mean to say that perception has
content? Does perception have more than one kind of content? Does
perceptual content derive from the content of beliefs or judgments?
Should perceptual content be understood in terms of accuracy
conditions? Is naive realism compatible with holding that
perception has content? This volume brings together philosophers
representing many different perspectives to address these and other
central questions in the philosophy of perception.
This is an open access title available under the terms of a CC
BY-NC-ND 4.0 International licence. It is free to read at Oxford
Scholarship Online and offered as a free PDF download from OUP and
selected open access locations. Why did such highly abstract ideas
as truth, knowledge, or justice become so important to us? What was
the point of coming to think in these terms? In The Practical
Origins of Ideas Matthieu Queloz presents a philosophical method
designed to answer such questions: the method of pragmatic
genealogy. Pragmatic genealogies are partly fictional, partly
historical narratives exploring what might have driven us to
develop certain ideas in order to discover what these do for us.
The book uncovers an under-appreciated tradition of pragmatic
genealogy which cuts across the analytic-continental divide,
running from the state-of-nature stories of David Hume and the
early genealogies of Friedrich Nietzsche to recent work in analytic
philosophy by Edward Craig, Bernard Williams, and Miranda Fricker.
However, these genealogies combine fictionalizing and historicizing
in ways that even philosophers sympathetic to the use of
state-of-nature fictions or real history have found puzzling. To
make sense of why both fictionalizing and historicizing are called
for, this book offers a systematic account of pragmatic genealogies
as dynamic models serving to reverse-engineer the points of ideas
in relation not only to near-universal human needs, but also to
socio-historically situated needs. This allows the method to offer
us explanation without reduction and to help us understand what led
our ideas to shed the traces of their practical origins. Far from
being normatively inert, moreover, pragmatic genealogy can affect
the space of reasons, guiding attempts to improve our conceptual
repertoire by helping us determine whether and when our ideas are
worth having.
David Icke has been writing books for decades warning that current events were coming. He has faced ridicule and abuse for saying that the end of human freedom was being planned, how, and by whom.
David Icke’s The Biggest Secret, first published in 1998, has been called the "Rosetta Stone" of the conspiracy movement for the way it exposes how the pieces fit and the nature of the force behind human control.
The Trap is the "Rosetta Stone" of illusory reality and opens the door to freedom in its greatest sense.
Read this book and the "world" will never look the same again. The veil of illusion shall be swept aside and the amazing truth this has kept from us shall set you free.
At the intersection between psychoanalysis (Freudian and Lacanian)
and philosophy, this book is a glimpse into the life of patients,
into desire and love, and into the fate of the relationship between
men and women.
The philosopher Abu Nasr al-Farabi (c. 870-c. 950 CE) is a key
Arabic intermediary figure. He knew Aristotle, and in particular
Aristotle's logic, through Greek Neoplatonist interpretations
translated into Arabic via Syriac and possibly Persian. For
example, he revised a general description of Aristotle's logic by
the 6th century Paul the Persian, and further influenced famous
later philosophers and theologians writing in Arabic in the 11th to
12th centuries: Avicenna, Al-Ghazali, Avempace and Averroes.
Averroes' reports on Farabi were subsequently transmitted to the
West in Latin translation. This book is an abridgement of
Aristotle's Prior Analytics, rather than a commentary on successive
passages. In it Farabi discusses Aristotle's invention, the
syllogism, and aims to codify the deductively valid arguments in
all disciplines. He describes Aristotle's categorical syllogisms in
detail; these are syllogisms with premises such as 'Every A is a B'
and 'No A is a B'. He adds a discussion of how categorical
syllogisms can codify arguments by induction from known examples or
by analogy, and also some kinds of theological argument from
perceived facts to conclusions lying beyond perception. He also
describes post-Aristotelian hypothetical syllogisms, which draw
conclusions from premises such as 'If P then Q' and 'Either P or
Q'. His treatment of categorical syllogisms is one of the first to
recognise logically productive pairs of premises by using
'conditions of productivity', a device that had appeared in the
Greek Philoponus in 6th century Alexandria.
|
|