|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > General
The series provides a forum for innovative, high-quality work in
all fields of analytical philosophy. The volumes in this series are
published in either English or German.
This book treats the critical theory of religion of Max Horkheimer,
Walter Benjamin, Theodor W. Adorno, Friedrich Pollock, Erich Fromm,
Herbert Marcuse, Alfred Sohn-Rethel, J rgen Habermas and other
critical theorists who tried to make sense out of the senseless war
experience by exploring the writings of Immanuel Kant, Friedrich
W.J. Schelling, Georg W.F. Hegel, Artur Schopenhauer, Karl Marx,
Friedrich Nietzsche, and Sigmund Freud.
This book presents a new interpretation of Kanta (TM)s theory of
knowledge that emphasizes the coherence and plausibility of his
doctrine of transcendental idealism. Many interpreters believe that
Kanta (TM)s transcendental idealism is an incoherent theory. Some
have attempted to respond to this charge. Yet, as the author
demonstrates, the interpretations that seek to vindicate Kanta
(TM)s theory continue to be committed to some claims that evoke the
charge of incoherence. One type of claim which does so is connected
to the contradictory notion of subjective necessity. The other type
of claim is related to the supposition that knowledge of the
reality of appearances entails knowledge of the reality of things
in themselves. The interpretation presented in this book does not
involve any of these claims. Part One of this book presents an
analysis of Kanta (TM)s concept of a priori knowledge and of his
response to skepticism about synthetic a priori knowledge that
specifies the content of such knowledge without invoking the notion
of subjective necessity. Part Two presents an account of the
non-spatiotemporality of things in themselves that does not entail
knowledge of the reality of things in themselves. Part Three
presents a new interpretation of transcendental synthesis, the
transcendental "I" and of the role of transcendental
self-consciousness in synthetic a priori knowledge which emphasizes
the originality of Kanta (TM)s account of self-knowledge and
subjectivity. The arguments presented in this book relate Kanta
(TM)s ideas to current debates in epistemology, metaphysics and the
philosophy of mind in a way that underscores their invaluable
relevance to present-day philosophicaldiscourse.
Despite the importance of Leibniz's mature philosophy, his early
work has been relatively neglected. This collection begins with an
overview of his formative years and includes 12 original papers by
internationally-known scholars. The contributions reflect the wide
range of the young Leibniz's philosophical interests and his
interests in related subjects, including law, physics and theology.
Some chapters explore his relationship to other philosophers,
including his teachers in Leipzig and Jena and his Paris friend
Tschirnhaus, as well as Hobbes and Spinoza. Others focus on
particular periods or texts and deal with themes ranging from
ethics and free-will to his philosophically-significant account of
transubstantiation and his early monadology. Some of the topics are
familiar to Leibniz students - harmony, sufficient reason and
possible worlds, for instance - but others are less familiar - for
instance, his attitude to historical truth, millenarianism and the
relation of mathematics to the natural world. The book provides an
introduction to Leibniz's early philosophy and throws light on the
development of some of the doctrines with which he is particularly
associated.
Following the American War of Independence and the French
Revolution, ideas of the 'Natural Rights of Man' (later
distinguished into particular issues like rights of association,
rights of women, slaves, children and animals) were publicly
debated in England. Literary figures like Wollstonecraft, Godwin,
Thelwall, Blake and Wordsworth reflected these struggles in their
poetry and fiction. With the seminal influences of John Locke and
Rousseau, these and many other writers laid for high Romantic
Literature foundations that were not so much aesthetic as moral and
political. This new study by R.S. White provides a reinterpretation
of the Enlightenment as it is currently understood.
In this book, Folke Tersman explores what we can learn about the
nature of moral thinking from moral disagreement. He explains how
diversity of opinion on moral issues undermines the idea that moral
convictions can be objectively valued. Arguments on moral thinking
are often criticized for not being able to explain why there is a
contrast between ethics and other areas in which there is
disagreement, but where one does not give up the idea of an
objective truth, as in the natural sciences. Tersman shows that the
contrast has to do with facts about when, and on what basis, moral
convictions can be correctly attributed to an agent or speaker.
Hermann Cohen's philosophy has now, finally, received the
recognition it deserves. His thought undoubtedly has all the
characteristics of a classic. It faced the great problems of
philosophical tradition, with full critical awareness and at the
same time, with the capacity to open up new, original routes. It
represents one of the last expressions of great systematic
thought.
The papers collected in this volume deal with different aspects
of Cohen's thought, ethical, political, aesthetic and religious
aspectsin particular. However they all represent attempts to follow
the ubiquitous presence of certain important themes in Cohen and
their capacity for containing meanings that cannot be limited to a
single philosophical sphere: themes that are keys to reading unity
of inspiration in his thought, which is more deeply imbedded than
the exterior architectural unity of his work. The search for the
fundamental themes behind Cohen is an important task, if we wish to
see this philosopher as a present-day vital point of reference.
Washington provides the first systematic critical look at the life
and work of Alain Locke, an important American philosopher, in the
context of a thoroughgoing analysis of the values, ideals,
aspirations, and problems of the Black community. Alain Locke
contributed significantly to the twentieth-century dialogue on
ethics and society. Drawing particularly on the work of William
James and Josiah Royce, Locke was perhaps the first to bring
philosophy to bear on the problems of race relations and social
justice in a multiracial society. He argued that racial problems in
the United States stem from the fact that white Americans hold up
their values as the only controlling and only acceptable model, to
which other groups are forced to conform. First discussing what is
meant by Black philosophy and what its concerns include, the author
examines Locke's philosophic interpretation of Black America's
historical experience, contributions to culture, and struggles for
social justice. He provides a critique of Locke's model of the
political community, with special reference to the work of Hannah
Arendt. Looking at the impact of Locke, DuBois, and others on the
Black community, he discusses their relation to the Black Elite,
their encouragement of Black artists and their positions on
educational issues such as teaching Black history, parity for
Blacks, and school desegregation. Other subjects considered are the
New Negro, the Harlem Renaissance, African art and culture, and
Locke's views in light of changes that have occurred since his
death in 1954. An important work on a philosopher whose insights
are of continuing significance today, this book will be of interest
for Afro-American studies, as well as for courses on American
philosophy and American social and intellectual history.
The six studies comprising this volume deal with some fundamental
issues in early Greek thought: cosmic evaluation in Anaximander,
the theory of opposites from the Pre-Socratics to Plato and
Aristotle, thought experimentation in Pre-Socratic thought, the
origins of Greek Scepticism among the Sophisists, the prehistory of
"Buridan's Ass" speculation, and the role of esthesis in
Aristotle's theory of science. In each case the early discussion
seeks to show how certain ideas bore unexpected fruit during the
subsequent development of philosophical thought.
This book offers a comprehensive and unitary study of the
philosophy of Francis Bacon, with special emphasis on the medical,
ethical and political aspects of his thought. It presents an
original interpretation focused on the material conditions of
nature and human life. In particular, coverage in the book is
organized around the unifying theme of Bacon's notion of appetite,
which is considered in its natural, ethical, medical and political
meanings. The book redefines the notions of experience and
experiment in Bacon's philosophy of nature, shows the important
presence of Stoic themes in his work as well as provides an
original discussion of the relationships between natural magic,
prudence and political realism in his philosophy. Bringing together
scholarly expertise from the history of philosophy, the history of
science and the history of literature, this book presents readers
with a rich and diverse contextualization of Bacon's philosophy.
Shaking up the content and method by which generations of students
had studied Western philosophy, Martin Heidegger sought to ennoble
man’s existence in relation to death. Yet in a time of crisis, he
sought personal advancement, becoming the most prominent German
intellectual to join the Nazis. Hannah Arendt, his brilliant,
beautiful student and young lover, sought to enable a decent
society of human beings in relation to one other. She was
courageous in the time of crisis. Years later, she was even able to
meet Heidegger once again on common ground and to find in his past
behavior an insight into Nazism that would influence her
reflections on “the banality of evil”—a concept that remains
bitterly controversial and profoundly influential to this day. But
how could Arendt have renewed her friendship with Heidegger? And
how has this relationship affected her reputation as a cultural
critic? In Stranger from Abroad, Daniel Maier-Katkin offers a
compassionate portrait that provides much-needed insight into this
relationship. Maier-Katkin creates a detailed and riveting portrait
of Arendt’s rich intellectual and emotional life, shedding light
on the unique bond she shared with her second husband, Heinrich
Blücher, and on her friendships with Mary McCarthy, W. H. Auden,
Karl Jaspers, and Randall Jarrell—all fascinating figures in
their own right. An elegant, accessible introduction to Arendt’s
life and work, Stranger from Abroad makes a powerful and hopeful
case for the lasting relevance of Arendt’s thought.
The wisdom of famous philosophers distilled into practical
takeaways for modern readers For centuries, philosophers have
considered the "big questions" of human life, mulling over
everything from ethics to the definition of reality. Their ideas
and insights are powerful and innovative, but often inaccessible
and far too academic for most readers. In The Philosophy Cure:
Lessons on Living from the Great Philosophers, scholar and expert
on Cartesian philosophy, Laurence Devillairs has stripped away the
convoluted language, translating the core ideas and wisdom of some
of the most prominent philosophers into simple concepts for modern
readers. She skillfully reveals that far from being impractical or
distantly academic, philosophy is, at its heart, a deeply useful
discipline ultimately concerned with what it means to live a good
and fulfilling life. Perfect for readers who are intrigued with
philosophy, but who are uninterested in reading dense academic
texts, The Philosophy Cure reveals the true wisdom of the
best-known philosophers--from Socrates to Kant and Descartes.
What is "A Law of Nature"? It's a question that's vexed
philosophers and scientists ever since Descartes first coined the
term. Fr. Andrew Younan explores it in this insightful book. After
carefully reviewing the positions of Humeans and Anti-Humeans, he
employs the philosophy of Aristotle and Aquinas to argue for an
essentialist understanding. His study leads him back to the
beginnings of modern science and then forward to quantum mechanics.
The philosophical account of how the laws of nature arise from
observed regularities in the world is followed by a theological
discussion of the nature and action of the Lawgiver."-from the
foreword by Michael J. Dodds, OP To borrow a phrase from Galileo:
What does it mean that the story of the creation is "written in the
language of mathematics?" This book is an attempt to understand the
natural world, its consistency, and the ontology of what we call
laws of nature, with a special focus on their mathematical
expression. It does this by arguing in favor of the Essentialist
interpretation over that of the Humean and Anti-Humean accounts. It
re-examines and critiques Descartes' notion of laws of nature
following from God's activity in the world as mover of extended
bodies, as well as Hume's arguments against causality and
induction. It then presents an Aristotelian-Thomistic account of
laws of nature based on mathematical abstraction, necessity, and
teleology, finally offering a definition for laws of nature within
this framework.
This book is avowedly written in what has been rather patronizingly
called "the affable spirit of compromise or conciliation" between
science and religion. Its key thesis is that these two enterprises
can-and should be-seen as complementary in addressing different
albeit interrelated questions: on the one side the nature of the
natural world and our place in it, and on the other how we should
proceed and act so as to capitalize on the opportunities that our
place in the world affords to us for shaping our lives in a
meaningful and satisfying way. How the world works is the crux of
the one enterprise and how we are to live is that of the other.
A major contribution to Descartes studies, this book provides a
panorama of cutting-edge scholarship ranging widely over
Descartes's own primary concerns: metaphysics, physics, and its
applications. It is at once a tool for scholars and--steering clear
of technical Cartesian science--an accessible resource that will
delight nonspecialists. The contributors include Edwin Curley,
Willis Doney, Alan Gabbey, Daniel Garber, Marjorie Grene, Gary
Hatfield, Marleen Rozemond, John Schuster, Dennis Sepper, Stephen
Voss, Stephen Wagner, Margaret Welson, Jean Marie Beyssade,
Michelle Beyssade, Michel Henry, Evert van Leeuwen, Jean-Luc
Marion, Genevieve Rodis-Lewis, and Jean-Pierre Seris. Combining new
textual sensitivity with attentiveness to history, they represent
the best established scholars and most exciting new voices,
including both English speaking and newly-translated writers. Part
I examines the foundations of Descartes's philosophy: Cartesian
certainty; the phenomenology of the cogito and its modulations in
the passions; and the defensibility and comprehensibility of the
Cartesian God. The second part examines Descartes's groundbreaking
metaphysics: mind's distinctness from and interaction with body;
imagination; perception; and language. Part III examines Cartesian
science: the revolutionary rhetoric of the Rules and the Discourse;
the metaphysical foundations of physics; the interplay of
rationalism and empiricism; the mechanics and human biology that
flow from Descartes's physics.
The act of thought-thought as an act-would precede the thought
thinking or becoming conscious of an act. The notion of act
involves a violence essentially: the violence of transitivity,
lacking in the transcendence of thought. . . Totality and Infinity
The work of Emmanuel Levinas revolves around two preoccupations.
First, his philosophical project can be described as the
construction of a formal ethics, grounded upon the transcendence of
the other human being and a subject's spontaneous responsibility
toward that other. Second, Levinas has written extensively on, and
as a member of, the cultural and textual life of Judaism. These two
concerns are intertwined. Their relation, however, is one of
considerable complexity. Levinas' philosophical project stems
directly from his situation as a Jewish thinker in the twentieth
century and takes its particular form from his study of the Torah
and the Talmud. It is, indeed, a hermeneutics of biblical
experience. If inspired by Judaism, Levinas' ethics are not eo ipso
confessional. What his ethics takes from Judaism, rather, is a
particular way of conceiving transcendence and the other human
being. It owes to the philosophy of Franz Rosenzweig and Martin
Buber a logos of the world and of the holy, which acknowledges
their incom mensurability without positing one as fallen and the
other as supernal."
|
|