|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > General
This book differs from others by rejecting the dualist approach associated in particular with Descartes. It also casts serious doubt on the forms of materialism that now dominate English language philosophy. Drawing in particular on the work of Wittgenstein, a central place is given to the importance of the notion of a human being in our thought about ourselves and others.
There are certain things that can be explained and certain things
that cannot be explained. This book is about the latter. It is a
book about death: how death interrupts and influences the
reflection on the self. It is a book about God: a detailed and
critical discussion on how Kierkegaard and Derrida apply the
concept of God in their philosophical reflections. The most
ground-breaking analysis concerns the famous passage on the self
(A.A) in The Sickness unto Death, where the author combines
logical, rhetorical and dialectical means to establish a new
perspective on Kierkegaard's thinking in general. The Cartesian
doubt then constitutes a common trait for his detailed and rigorous
analysis of Derrida and Kierkegaard on death, madness, faith, and
rationality - showing how they both seek to break up the Hegelian
Aufhebung from within, but still remain dependent on Hegel. After
Kierkegaard and Derrida, the certainty and total uncertainty of
death - and of God as infinite other - gives the self a basic,
though non-foundational, responsibility. The significance of this
responsibility, of this other, of this death, requires sustained
and thorough consideration. Where others mark a conclusion, this
book therefore marks a point of departure: reflecting on oneself at
the graveside of a dead man - thus introducing an Autopsia.
Montaigne is one of the most cross-cultural writers ever - both in
the assimilation of writings from other cultures into his own work
and in the subsequent translations, critical receptions, and
creative adaptations of the Essais by other writers throughout the
world for the last four hundred years. His work is generally
considered as exemplary of the European Renaissance, yet also
demonstrates a remarkable relevance to the literary and
intellectual activity at the present time. However, whereas there
has been an abundance of commentary on Montaigne during the first
centuries after his death, much less attention has been paid to his
impact on writers of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries,
particularly those outside France. This study redresses the
imbalance. By establishing a stylistic and ideological relationship
between Montaigne's work and that of such writers as Emerson,
Nietzsche, Pater, Woolf, and Sollers, we not only gain a greater
appreciation of the richness of the Essays, but also of some of the
roots of modernist and postmodernist writing.
Despite characterizing himself as the antichrist, Nietzsche had
great respect for Jesus and his message and often identified with
his life. His opinion of early Christianity--and particularly of
St. Paul, the single most hated figure in Nietzsche's passionate
career--however, was very different. This volume brings order to
Nietzsche's scattered reflections on Jesus, St. Paul, and the birth
of Christianity by tracing the development of his ideas and
examining the intellectual reality behind his deliberately
confrontational remarks concerning early Christianity's key
players. By analyzing exactly what it is that Nietzsche celebrates
and identifies with in the life and message of Jesus, and
criticizes so harshly in the case of St. Paul, the author provides
fresh insight into the mind and the philosophy of one of the 19th
century's most original thinkers.
Why should the sociologist concern himself with time? asks Franco
Ferrarotti in his latest work. Temporality is, he argues, the
essential fluid dimension in the study of the social. Including
time as a factor in sociological analysis is the only way to
reintroduce the dynamic moment of social reality as a mental
construct into an analytical process otherwise reified by the
limits of quantitative methods. Ultimately, Ferrarotti contends,
the usual way of laying out and proceeding with sociological
analysis must be decisively inverted. This book is challenging
reading for the sociologist and philosopher alike. Why should the
sociologist concern himself with time? asks Franco Ferrarotti in
his latest work. Temporality is, he argues, the essential fluid
dimension in the study of the social. Including time as a factor in
sociological analysis is the only way to reintroduce the dynamic
moment of social reality as a mental construct into an analytical
process otherwise reified by the limits of quantitative methods.
The biographical and autobiographical approaches are also rooted in
time. They elicit a problematic human situation and distinguish
radically between the technical problem, resolvable through the
exact practical application of a given, ideally indifferent, and
interchangable formula, and the human dimension. Ultimately,
Ferrarotti contends, the usual way of laying out and proceeding
with sociological analysis must be decisively inverted. The order
of priorities in the research process now followed in the human
sciences tends to encourage the loss of the sense of the problem
through the crude postulation of technical and human problems as
equivalent. Time, Memory, and Society will be challenging, thought
provoking reading for the sociologist, social theorist, and
philosopher.
The observation that our world is signed by a lasting crisis is as
much underwritten as it is questioned. This book offers a new and
provocative thesis by taking recourse to the religious discourse of
Limbo, and by investigating the temporal and spatial structures of
crisis and modernity. Modernity reveals itself to be the state of
perennial crisis, and we all live in an immanentized state of
Limbo.
This book reveals the sense in which our postmodern societies are
characterized by the obscene absence of the intellectual. The
modern intellectual--who had once been associated with humanism and
enlightenment-has in our day been replaced by media stars, talking
heads, and technical experts. At issue is the ongoing crisis of
democracy, under the aegis of the societe du spectacle and its vast
networks of politically-induced idiocy, industrially-produced
biocide, and militarily-provoked genocide. Spectacle fills the
resulting moral and intellectual vacuum with electronic
technologies of control, punishment, and destruction. This
postmodern tyranny reduces intelligence to mechanistic, positivist,
and grammatological models of inquiry, while increasing the
segmentation, fragmentation, and dissolution of human existence.
The apotheosis of the spectacle explains the intellectual void that
lies at the heart of our postmodern decadence; it also accounts for
the need to recuperate the humanist values of enlightenment
promoted by the modern intellectual tradition.
In this thought-provoking book, an internationally acclaimed
scholar writes about the passion for ideology among nineteenth- and
twentieth-century Russian intellectuals and about the development
of sophisticated critiques of ideology by a continuing minority of
Russian thinkers inspired by libertarian humanism. Aileen Kelly
sets the conflict between utopian and anti-utopian traditions in
Russian thought within the context of the shift in European thought
away from faith in universal systems and "grand narratives" of
progress toward an acceptance of the role of chance and contingency
in nature and history. In the current age, as we face the dilemma
of how to prevent the erosion of faith in absolutes and final
solutions from ending in moral nihilism, we have much to learn from
the struggles, failures, and insights of Russian thinkers, Kelly
says. Her essays-some of them tours de force that have appeared
before as well as substantial new studies of Turgenev, Herzen, and
the Signposts debate-illuminate the insights of Russian
intellectuals into the social and political consequences of ideas
of such seminal Western thinkers as Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and
Darwin. Russian Literature and Thought Series
Paul Helm is a distinguished philosopher, with particular interests
in the philosophy of religion. His work covers some of the most
important aspects of the field as it has developed in the last
thirty years with particular contributions to metaphysics,
religious epistemology and philosophical theology. In celebration
of Helm's life's work, Reason in the Service of Faith brings
together a range of his essays which reflect these central concerns
of his thought. Over thirty of Helm's selected essays and four
unpublished articles are gathered into five parts:
Metaphilosophical issues, Action, Change and Personal Identity,
Epistemology, God and Creation, Providence and Prayer. The volume
is prefaced with a short editorial introduction and ends with an
extensive bibliography of Helm's published works. Demonstrating the
important connection between Helm's theological and philosophical
interests across his body of work, this collection is a remarkable
resource for scholars of religion, philosophy and theology.
Nelson Goodman's acceptance and critique of certain methods and
tenets of positivism, his defence of nominalism and phenomenalism,
his formulation of a new riddle of induction, his work on
notational systems, and his analysis of the arts place him at the
forefront of the history and development of American philosophy in
the twentieth-century. However, outside of America, Goodman has
been a rather neglected figure. In this first book-length
introduction to his work Cohnitz and Rossberg assess Goodman's
lasting contribution to philosophy and show that although some of
his views may be now considered unfashionable or unorthodox, there
is much in Goodman's work that is of significance today. The book
begins with the "grue"-paradox, which exemplifies Goodman's way of
dealing with philosophical problems. After this, the unifying
features of Goodman's philosophy are presented - his
constructivism, conventionalism and relativism - followed by an
discussion of his central work, The Structure of Appearance and its
significance in the analytic tradition. The following chapters
present the technical apparatus that underlies his philosophy, his
mereology and semiotics, which provides the background for
discussion of Goodman's aesthetics. The final chapter examines in
greater depth the presuppositions underlying his philosophy.
Putnam is one of the most influential philosophers of recent times,
and his authority stretches far beyond the confines of the
discipline. However, there is a considerable challenge in
presenting his work both accurately and accessibly. This is due to
the width and diversity of his published writings and to his
frequent spells of radical re-thinking. But if we are to understand
how and why philosophy is developing as it is, we need to attend to
Putnam's whole career. He has had a dramatic influence on theories
of meaning, semantic content, and the nature of mental phenomena,
on interpretations of quantum mechanics, theory-change, logic and
mathematics, and on what shape we should desire for future
philosophy. By presenting the whole of his career within its
historical context, de Gaynesford discovers a basic unity in his
work, achieved through repeated engagements with a small set of
hard problems. By foregrounding this integrity, the book offers an
account of his philosophy that is both true to Putnam and helpful
to readers of his work.
One of the most influential philosophers and cultural theorists
of the twentieth century, Theodor Adorno poses a considerable
challenge to students. His works can often seem obscure and
impenetrable, particularly for those with little knowledge of the
philosophical traditions on which he draws. Adorno: A Guide for the
Perplexed is an engaging and accessible account of his thought that
does not patronise or short-change the reader. Those new to Adorno
- and those who have struggled to make headway with his work - will
find this an invaluable resource: clearly written, comprehensive
and specifically focused on just what makes Adorno difficult to
read and understand.
This book offers an examination of Levinas 's philosophy of
religion in light of his ethics and anthropology. It provides
critical perspectives on Levinas by relating his work to that of
Heidegger, Ricoeur, Rorty, Derrida and Vattimo. The focus of
interpretation is the hermeneutics of kenosis: the subject 's
ability to be open towards the other to the point where man can be
seen as a place of God.
In the last decades, Ingvar Johansson has made a formidable
contribution to the development of philosophy in general and
perhaps especially to the development of metaphysics. This volume
consists of original papers written by 50 philosophers from all
over the world in honour of Ingvar Johansson to celebrate his 70th
birthday. The papers cover traditional issues in metaphysics and
the philosophy of mind, applied ethics and applied metaphysics, the
nature of human rights, the philosophy of economics and sports.
Some of the papers study the philosophy of Ingvar Johansson. All of
them studies subjects which he has shown an interest in. The
variety of subjects covered, testifies to the extraordinary wide
range of issues his thought has had a bearing on.
Heidegger holds that our age is dominated by the ambition of reason
to possess the world. And he sees in Leibniz the man who formulated
the theorem of our modern age: nothing happens without a reason. He
calls this attitude `calculating thought' and opposes to it a kind
of thought aimed at preserving the essence of things, which he
calls `meditating thought'. Cristin's book ascribes great
importance to this polarity of thinking for the future of
contemporary philosophy, and thus compares the basic ideas of the
two thinkers. Leibniz announces the conquest of reason; Heidegger
denounces the dangers of reason. Their diversity becomes manifest
in the difference between the idea of reason and the image of the
path. But is Leibniz's thought really only `calculating'? And do we
not perhaps also encounter the traces of reason along Heidegger's
path? With these questions in mind we may begin to redefine the
relation between the two thinkers and between two different
conceptions of reason and philosophy. The hypothesis is advanced
that Heidegger's harsh judgment of Leibniz may be mitigated, but it
also becomes clear that Heidegger's rewriting of the code of reason
is an integral part of our age, in which many signs point to new
loci of rationality. With his original interpretation, aware of the
risks he is taking, Renato Cristin offers a new guide to the
understanding of reason: he shows forth Leibniz as one who defends
the thought of being in the unity of monadology, and Heidegger as a
thinker who preserves the sign of reason in his meditating thought.
Merleau-Ponty in contemporary perspective: this was the theme of
the conference at the Institute of Philosophy, Katholieke
Universiteit Leuven (K. U. L. ) from 29 November to 1 December
1991. Thirty years after Merleau Ponty's untimely death, it seemed
appropriate to bring together scholars from Europe and from the
United States of America to reappraise his philosophy. In fact, a
significant body of scholarship has emerged which would seem to
attest to the continuing importance of his thought for a variety of
disciplines within the humanities, the social sciences, and the
philosophy of nature. In the present volume, Gary Brent Madison
addresses the issue whether Merleau-Ponty can be considered to be a
classical philosopher. The fact that his work is one of the
highlights of the phenomenological tradition and is of continuing
inspiration for researchers in various domains seems to justify
that claim. Yet, it is the feeling of many of the contributors to
this volume that the so-called "second Merleau-Ponty" is still not
really known. The unfinished state of The Visible and the Invisible
and the cryptic condition of many of the "Working Notes" may be
responsible for that. More research should be done, to uncover "the
unsaid" of Merleau-Ponty. lowe to a remark of Paul Ricoeur in his
introduction to the work of G. B. Madison, La Phenomenologie de
Merleau-Ponty. Une recherche des limites de la conscience (Paris,
Klincksieck, 1973, p."
The book about John Michell (1724-93) has two parts. The first and
longest part is biographical, an account of Michell's home setting
(Nottinghamshire in England), the clerical world in which he grew
up (Church of England), the university (Cambridge) where he studied
and taught, and the scientific activities he made the center of his
life. The second part is a complete edition of his known letters.
Half of his letters have not been previously published; the other
half are brought together in one place for the first time. The
letters touch on all aspects of his career, and because they are in
his words, they help bring the subject to life. His publications
were not many, a slim book on magnets and magnetism, one paper on
geology, two papers on astronomy, and a few brief papers on other
topics, but they were enough to leave a mark on several sciences.
He has been called a geologist, an astronomer, and a physicist,
which he was, though we best remember him as a natural philosopher,
as one who investigated physical nature broadly. His scientific
contribution is not easy to summarize. Arguably he had the broadest
competence of any British natural philosopher of the eighteenth
century: equally skilled in experiment and observation,
mathematical theory, and instruments, his field of inquiry was the
universe. From the structure of the heavens through the structure
of the Earth to the forces of the elementary particles of matter,
he carried out original and far-reaching researches on the workings
of nature.
Descartes's Principles 0. / Philosophy is his longest and most
ambitious work; it is the only work in which he attempted to
actually deduce scientific knowledge from Cartesian metaphysics, as
he repeatedly claimed was possible. Whatever the success of this
attempt, there can be no doubt that it was enormously influential.
Cartesian celestial mechanics held sway for well over a century,
and some of the best minds of that period, including Leibniz,
Malebranche, Euler, and the Bernoullis, attempted to modify and
quantify the Cartesian theory of vortices into an acceptable
alternative to Newton's theory of universal gravitation. Thus, the
Principles is not only of inherent and historical interest
philosophically but is also a seminal document in the history of
science and of 17th Century thought. Principles of Philosophy was
first published in Latin, in 1644. In 1647, a French translation,
done by the Abbe Claude Picot and containing a great deal of
additional material and a number of alterations in the original
text, was published with Descartes's enthusiastic approval. Unlike
some English translations of portions of the Principles, this
translation uses the Latin text as its primary source; however, a
good deal of additional material from Picot's translation has been
included. There are several reasons for this. First, there is good
evidence that Descartes himself was responsible for some of the
additional material, including, of course, the Preface to the
French translation.
As a founding father of Existentialism, Karl Jaspers has been seen
as a twentieth-century successor to Nietzsche and Kierkegaard; as
an exponent of reason, he has been seen as an heir of Kant. But
studies tracing influences upon his thought or placing him in the
context of Existentialism have not dealt with Jasper's concern with
the political realm and how we think in it and about it. In this
study Elisabeth Young-Bruehl explicates Jasper's practical
philosophizing, his search for ways in which we can orient
ourselves toward our world and its political questions. Political
freedom and freedom for philosophizing, for critical thinking, were
of a piece for Jaspers, and Young-Bruehl makes the dynamic unity of
these two freedoms the subject of her book. What was important for
Jaspers was not a systematic set of philosophical concepts but the
activity of philosophizing, a mode of thinking that could
illuminate the origins and implications of such unprecedented
phenomena as nuclear weapons and totalitarian regimes. Young-Bruehl
shows how Jaspers aimed at responsibility to the diversity of the
world and attempted to formulate criteria for judgment conducive to
responsible thought and action.
|
You may like...
Kant's Thinker
Patricia Kitcher
Hardcover
R3,206
Discovery Miles 32 060
|