|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Western philosophy, c 500 to c 1600 > General
William of Ockham (d. 1347) was among the most influential and the
most notorious thinkers of the late Middle Ages. In the
twenty-seven questions translated in this volume, most never before
published in English, he considers a host of theological and
philosophical issues, including the nature of virtue and vice, the
relationship between the intellect and the will, the scope of human
freedom, the possibility of God's creating a better world, the role
of love and hatred in practical reasoning, whether God could
command someone to do wrong, and more. In answering these
questions, Ockham critically engages with the ethical thought of
such predecessors as Aristotle, Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, and John
Duns Scotus. Students and scholars of both philosophy and
historical theology will appreciate the accessible translations and
ample explanatory notes on the text.
The essays in this book discuss a number of the central
metaphysical and ethical themes that engaged the minds of Platonist
philosophers during late Antiquity and the early Middle Ages. One
particular theme is that of the structure of reality, with the
associated questions of the relations between soul and body and
between intelligible and sensible reality, and the existence of
mathematical objects. Other topics relate to evil and beauty,
political life and its purpose, the philosophical search for the
absolute Good, and how one can speak about this Absolute and have
union with it. Going from Plato to Eriugena, the ways in which
Platonist philosophers understood and developed these themes are
analysed and compared.
|
Montaigne
(Paperback)
Stefan Zweig; Translated by Will Stone
1
|
R295
R278
Discovery Miles 2 780
Save R17 (6%)
|
Ships in 12 - 17 working days
|
|
'He who thinks freely for himself, honours all freedom on earth.'
Stefan Zweig was already an emigre-driven from a Europe torn apart
by brutality and totalitarianism-when he found, in a damp cellar, a
copy of Michel de Montaigne's Essais. Montaigne would become
Zweig's last great occupation, helping him make sense of his own
life and his obsessions-with personal freedom, with the sanctity of
the individual. Through his writings on suicide, he would also,
finally, lead Zweig to his death. With the intense psychological
acuity and elegant prose so characteristic of Zweig's fiction, this
account of Montaigne's life asks how we ought to think, and how to
live. It is an intense and wonderful insight into both subject and
biographer.
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy is a annual (from 2000 twice yearly) volume of original articles on all aspects of ancient philosophy. The articles may be of substantial length, and include critical notices of major books. This year's contributions range over a thousand years of philosophy, from the Presocratics to Philoponus. Particularly prominent in the volume are Aristotle and the Stoics. 'standard reading among specialists in ancient philosophy' Brad Inwood, Bryn Mawr Classical Review
The Late Scholastics, writing in Europe in the Baroque and Early
Modern periods, discussed a wide variety of moral questions
relating to political life in times of both peace and war. Is it
ever permissible to bribe voters? Can tax evasion be morally
justified? What are the moral duties of artists? Is it acceptable
to fight in a war one believes to be unjust? May we surrender
innocents to the enemy if it is necessary to save the state? These
questions are no less relevant for philosophers and politicians
today than they were for late scholastic thinkers. By bringing into
play the opinions and arguments of numerous authors, many of them
little known or entirely forgotten, this book is the first to
provide an in-depth treatment of the dynamic and controversial
nature of late scholastic applied moral thinking which demonstrates
its richness and diversity.
In this book, Travis DeCook explores the theological and political
innovations found in early modern accounts of the Bible's origins.
In the charged climate produced by the Reformation and humanist
historicism, writers grappled with the tension between the Bible's
divine and human aspects, and they produced innovative narratives
regarding the agencies and processes through which the Bible came
into existence and was transmitted. DeCook investigates how these
accounts of Scripture's production were taken up beyond the
expected boundaries of biblical study, and were redeployed as the
theological basis for wide-reaching arguments about the proper
ordering of human life. DeCook provides a new, critical perspective
on ideas regarding secularity, secularization, and modernity,
challenging the dominant narratives regarding the Bible's role in
these processes. He shows how these engagements with the Bible's
origins prompt a rethinking of formulations of secularity and
secularization in our own time.
The volume results from a seminar sponsored by the 'Foundation for
Intellectual History' at the Herzog August Bibliothek,
WolfenbA1/4ttel, in 1992. Starting with the theory of regressus as
displayed in its most developed form by William Wallace, these
papers enter the vast field of the Renaissance discussion on method
as such in its historical and systematical context. This is
confined neither to the notion of method in the strict sense, nor
to the Renaissance in its exact historical limits, nor yet to the
Aristotelian tradition as a well defined philosophical school, but
requires a new scholarly approach. Thus - besides Galileo,
Zabarella and their circles, which are regarded as being crucial
for the 'emergence of modern science' in the end of the 16th
century - the contributors deal with the ancient and medieval
origins as well as with the early modern continuity of the
Renaissance concepts of method and with 'non-regressive'
methodologies in the various approaches of Renaissance natural
philosophy, including the Lutheran and Calvinist traditions.
The papers collected in this volume fall into three main groups.
Those in the first group are concerned with the origin and early
development of the idea of natural rights. The author argues here
that the idea first grew into existence in the writings of the
12th-century canonists. The articles in the second group discuss
miscellaneous aspects of medieval law and political thought. They
include an overview of modern work on late medieval canon law. The
final group of articles is concerned with the history of papal
infallibility, with especial reference to the tradition of
Franciscan ecclesiology and the contributions of John Peter Olivi
and William of Ockham.
This collection of readings with extensive editorial commentary
brings together key texts of the most influential philosophers of
the medieval era to provide a comprehensive introduction for
students of philosophy.
Features the writings of Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, Boethius, John
Duns Scotus and other leading medieval thinkers
Features several new translations of key thinkers of the medieval
era, including John Buridan and Averroes
Readings are accompanied by expert commentary from the editors, who
are leading scholars in the field
The Book of Causes, highly influential in the medieval university,
was commonly but incorrectly understood to be the completion of
Aristotle's metaphysics. It was Thomas Aquinas who first judged it
to have been abstracted from Proclus's Elements of Theology,
presumably by an unknown Arabic author, who added to it ideas of
his own. The Book of Causes is of particular interest because
themes that appear in it are echoed in the metaphysics of Aquinas:
its treatment of being (esse) as proceeding from the First Creating
Cause; the triadic scheme of being, living, and knowing; and the
general scheme of participation in which "all is in all." Thus, the
Book of Causes provides a historical backdrop for understanding and
appreciating Aquinas's development of these themes in his
metaphysics. Thomas's Commentary on the Book of Causes, composed
during the first half of 1272, is a distinct philosophical work in
its own right. It provides an extended view of his approach to
Neoplatonic thought and functions as a guide to his metaphysics.
Though long neglected and, until now, never translated into
English, it deserves an equal place alongside his commentaries on
Aristotle and Boethius. In addition to the extensive annotation,
bibliography, and thorough introduction, this translation is
accompanied by two valuable appendices. The first provides a
translation of another version of proposition 29 of the Book of
Causes, which was not known to St. Thomas. The second lists
citations of the Book of Causes found in the works of St. Thomas
and cross-references these to a list showing the works, and the
exact location within them, where the citations can be found.
This volume deals with the development of moral and political
philosophy in the medieval West. Professor Nederman is concerned to
trace the continuing influence of classical ideas, but emphasises
that the very diversity and diffuseness of medieval thought shows
that there is no single scheme that can account for the way these
ideas were received, disseminated and reformulated by medieval
ethical and political theorists.
Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics is the text which had the single
greatest influence on Aquinas's ethical writings, and the
historical and philosophical value of Aquinas's appropriation of
this text provokes lively debate. In this volume of new essays,
thirteen distinguished scholars explore how Aquinas receives,
expands on and transforms Aristotle's insights about the
attainability of happiness, the scope of moral virtue, the
foundation of morality and the nature of pleasure. They examine
Aquinas's commentary on the Ethics and his theological writings,
above all the Summa theologiae. Their essays show Aquinas to be a
highly perceptive interpreter, but one who also brings certain
presuppositions to the Ethics and alters key Aristotelian notions
for his own purposes. The result is a rich and nuanced picture of
Aquinas's relation to Aristotle that will be of interest to readers
in moral philosophy, Aquinas studies, the history of theology and
the history of philosophy.
In On Machiavelli: The Search for Glory, Alan Ryan illuminates the
political and philosophical complexities of the often-reviled
godfather of realpolitik. Thought by some to be the founder of
Italian nationalism, regarded by others to be a reviver of the
Roman Republic as a model for the modern Western world, Machiavelli
remains a contentious figure. Often outraging popular opinion with
his insistence on the amoral nature of power, Machiavelli eschewed
the world as it ought to be in favor of a forthright appraisal of
the one that is. Perhaps more than any other thinker, Machiavelli
has suffered from being taken out of context, and Ryan places him
squarely within his own time and the politics of a Renaissance
Italy riven by near-constant warfare among rival city-states and
the papacy.
A well-educated son of Florence, Machiavelli was originally in
charge of the Florentine Republic s militia, but in 1512 the city
fell to papal forces led by Cardinal Giovanni de Medici, who thus
restored the Medici family to power. Machiavelli was accused of
conspiracy, imprisoned, tortured, and eventually exiled from his
beloved Florence, and it was during this period that he produced
his most famous works. While attempting to ingratiate himself to
the Medicis, the historically minded Machiavelli looked to the
imperial ambitions and past glories of the Roman Republic as a
contrast to the perceived failures of his contemporaries.
For Machiavelli, the hunger for power and glory was inextricable
from human nature, and any serious attempt to rule must take this
into account. In his revolutionary The Prince and Discourses both
excerpted here Machiavelli created the first truly modern analysis
of power."
Moses Maimonides (1138-1204) was arguably the single most important
Jewish thinker of the Middle Ages, with an impact on the later
Jewish tradition that was unparalleled by any of his
contemporaries. In this volume of new essays, world-leading
scholars address themes relevant to his philosophical outlook,
including his relationship with his Islamicate surroundings and the
impact of his work on subsequent Jewish and Christian writings, as
well as his reception in twentieth-century scholarship. The essays
also address the nature and aim of Maimonides' philosophical
writing, including its connection with biblical exegesis, and the
philosophical and theological arguments that are central to his
work, such as revelation, ritual, divine providence, and teleology.
Wide-ranging and fully up-to-date, the volume will be highly
valuable for those interested in Jewish history and thought,
medieval philosophy, and religious studies.
Exploring what theologians at the University of Paris in the
thirteenth century understood about the boundary between humans and
animals, this book demonstrates the great variety of ways in which
they held similarity and difference in productive tension.
Analysing key theological works, Ian P. Wei presents extended close
readings of William of Auvergne, the Summa Halensis, Bonaventure,
Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas. These scholars found it useful
to consider animals and humans together, especially with regard to
animal knowledge and behaviour, when discussing issues including
creation, the fall, divine providence, the heavens, angels and
demons, virtues and passions. While they frequently stressed that
animals had been created for use by humans, and sometimes treated
them as tools employed by God to shape human behaviour, animals
were also analytical tools for the theologians themselves. This
study thus reveals how animals became a crucial resource for
generating knowledge of God and the whole of creation.
This volume is a collection of essays on a special theme in
Aristotelian philosophy of mind: the internal senses. The first
part of the volume is devoted to the central question of whether or
not any internal senses exist in Aristotle's philosophy of mind
and, if so, how many and how they are individuated. The provocative
claim of chapter one is that Aristotle recognizes no such internal
sense. His medieval Latin interpreters, on the other hand, very
much thought that Aristotle did introduce a number of internal
senses as shown in the second chapter. The second part of the
volume contains a number of case studies demonstrating the
philosophical background of some of the most influential topics
covered by the internal senses in the Aristotelian tradition and in
contemporary philosophy of mind. The focus of the case studies is
on memory, imagination and estimation. Chapters introduce the
underlying mechanisms of memory and recollection taking its cue
from Aristotle but reaching into early modern philosophy as well as
studying composite imagination in Avicenna's philosophy of mind.
Further topics include the Latin reception of Avicenna's estimative
faculty and the development of the internal senses as well as
offering an account of the logic of objects of imagination.
The conventional opposition of scholastic Aristotelianism and
humanistic science has been increasingly questioned in recent
years, and in these articles William Wallace aims to demonstrate
that a progressive Aristotelianism in fact provided the foundation
for Galileo's scientific discoveries. The first series of articles
supply much of the documentary evidence that has led the author to
the sources for Galileo's early notebooks: they show how Galileo,
while teaching or preparing to teach at Pisa, actually appropriated
much of his material from Jesuit lectures given at the Collegio
Romano in 1598-90. The next articles then trace a number of key
elements in Galileo's later work, mainly relating to logical
methodology and natural philosophy, back to sources in medieval
Aristotelian thought, notably in the writings of Albert the Great
and Thomas Aquinas. La mise en opposition conventionnelle entre
l'aristotelisme scolastique et la science humaniste a ete de plus
en plus remise en question durant les dernieres annees. Tout au
long de ces articles, William Wallace tente de demontrer que
l'aristotelisme progressif a en fait pourvu le fondement des
decouvertes scientifiques de Galilee. Le premier groupe d'articles
fournit la plupart des preuves documentees qui ont mene l'auteur
aux sources des premiers cahiers de notes de Galilee; on y voit
comment celui-ci, alors qu'il enseignait, ou s'apprAtait A
enseigner A Pise, s'etait en fait approprie quantite de donnees
issues de cours magistraux jesuites qui avaient ete donnes au
Collegio Romano entre 1588 et 90. Les etudes suivantes retracent A
leur tour un certain nombre d'elements-clef des travaux ulterieurs
de Galilee, se rapportant plus particulierement A la methodologie
logique et a la philosophie naturelle, jusqu'A leurs sources dans
la pensee aristotelicienne du Moyen Age, notamment dans les ecrits
d'Albert le Grand et de Thomas d'Aquin.
Peter Adamson presents a lively introduction to six hundred years
of European philosophy, from the beginning of the ninth century to
the end of the fourteenth century. The medieval period is one of
the richest in the history of philosophy, yet one of the least
widely known. Adamson introduces us to some of the greatest
thinkers of the Western intellectual tradition, including Peter
Abelard, Anselm of Canterbury, Thomas Aquinas, John Duns Scotus,
William of Ockham, and Roger Bacon. And the medieval period was
notable for the emergence of great women thinkers, including
Hildegard of Bingen, Marguerite Porete, and Julian of Norwich.
Original ideas and arguments were developed in every branch of
philosophy during this period - not just philosophy of religion and
theology, but metaphysics, philosophy of logic and language, moral
and political theory, psychology, and the foundations of
mathematics and natural science.
'This sentence is false' - is that true? The 'Liar paradox'
embodied in those words exerted a particular fascination on the
logicians of the Western later Middle Ages, and, along with similar
'insoluble' problems, forms the subject of the first group of
articles in this volume. In the following parts Professor Spade
turns to medieval semantic theory, views on the relationship
between language and thought, and to a study of one particular
genre of disputation, that known as 'obligationes'. The focus is on
the Oxford scholastics of the first half of the 14th century, and
it is the name of William of Ockham which dominates these pages - a
thinker with whom Professor Spade finds himself in considerable
philosophical sympathy, and whose work on logic and semantic theory
has a depth and richness that have not always been sufficiently
appreciated.
|
You may like...
Meditations
Marcus Aurelius
Hardcover
R618
Discovery Miles 6 180
|