|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Topics in philosophy > Metaphysics & ontology
Relationalism about space is a venerable doctrine that is enjoying
renewed attention among philosophers and physicists. Relationalists
deny that space is ontologically prior to matter and seek to ground
all claims about the structure of space in facts about actual and
possible configurations of matter. Thus, many relationalists
maintain that to say that space is infinite is to say that certain
sorts of infinite arrays of material points are possible (even if,
in fact, the world contains only a finite amount of matter).
Gordon Belot investigates the distinctive notion of geometric
possibility that relationalists rely upon. He examines the
prospects for adapting to the geometric case the standard
philosophical accounts of the related notion of physical
possibility, with particular emphasis on Humean, primitivist, and
necessitarian accounts of physical and geometric possibility. This
contribution to the debate concerning the nature of space will be
of interest not only to philosophers and metaphysicians concerned
with space and time, but also to those interested in laws of
nature, modal notions, or more general issues in ontology.
This volume contains a set of state-of-the-art essays by younger
philosophers on various topics in the philosophy of action. Some of
the essays are about the metaphysics of action and agency; some
consider the nature of autonomy and free agency; some explore
conceptual and normative issues, some draw on data from psychology
and psychopathology. But what all of them have in common is that
they address some problem related to our existence as human agents.
The range of topics covered is this collection is broad. This is
intentional. Rather than focus on one narrow topic in the
philosophy of action, this volume brings together papers that,
taken together, introduce readers to some key debates in
contemporary philosophy of action. Readers new to the field should
come away from the volume with a good sense of the state-of-the-art
with respect to current thinking about human action and agency. For
their part, established researchers in the field will find the
essays to be original contributions that substantially advance many
debates about action and agency.
The present book intends to approach the problem of mind, meaning
and consciousness from a non-naturalist or transcendental point of
view. The naturalization of consciousness has reached a dead-end.
There can be no proper solution to the problem of mind within the
naturalist framework. This work intends to reverse this trend and
bring back the long neglected transcendental theory laid down by
Kant and Husserl in the West and Vedanta and Buddhism in India. The
novelty of this approach lies in how we can make an autonomous
space for mind and meaning without denying its connection with the
world. The transcendental theory does not disown the embodied
nature of consciousness, but goes beyond the body in search of
higher meanings and values. The scope of this work extends from
mind and consciousness to the world and brings the world into the
space of mind and meaning with a hope to enchant the world. The
world needs to be retrieved from the stranglehold of scientism and
naturalism. This book will dispel the illusion about naturalism
which has gripped the minds of our generation. The researchers
interested in the philosophy of mind and consciousness can benefit
from this work.
This book focuses on three interdependent challenges related to
managing transitions toward sustainable development, namely (a)
mapping sustainability for global knowledge e-networking, (b)
extending the value chain of knowledge and e-networking, and (c)
engaging in explorations of new methods and venues for further
developing knowledge and e-networking. While each of these
challenges constitutes fundamentally different types of endeavors,
they are highly interconnected. Jointly, they contribute to our
expansion of knowledge and its applications in support of
transitions toward sustainable development.
The central theme of this book revolves around ways of
transcending barriers that impede the use of knowledge and
knowledge networking in transitions toward sustainability. In order
to transcend these barriers, we examine the potential contributions
of innovations in information technologies as well as computation
and representation of attendant complexities. A related theme
addresses new ways of managing information and systematic
observation for the purpose of enhancing the value of knowledge.
Finally, this book shows applications of new methodologies and
related findings that would contribute to our understanding of
sustainablity issues that have not yet been explored. In many ways,
this is a book of theory and of practice; and it is one of methods
as well as policy and performance.
This book defends a novel view of mental representation-of how, as
thinkers, we represent the world as being. The book serves as a
response to two problems in the philosophy of mind. One is the
problem of first-personal, or egocentric, belief: how can we have
truly first personal beliefs-beliefs in which we think about
ourselves as ourselves-given that beliefs are supposed to be
attitudes towards propositions and that propositions are supposed
to have their truth values independent of a perspective? The other
problem is how we can think about nonexistents (e.g., Santa Claus)
given the widespread view that thought essentially involves a
relation between a thinker and whatever is being thought about. The
standard responses to this puzzle are either to deny that thought
is essentially relational or to insist that it is possible to stand
in relations to nonexistents. This book offers an error theory to
the problem. The responses from this book arise from the same
commitment: a commitment to treating talk of propositions-as the
things towards which our beliefs are attitudes-as talk of entities
that actually exist and that play a constitutive and explanatory
role in the activity of thought.
While the field of aesthetics has long been dominated by European
philosophy, recent inquiries have expanded the arena to accommodate
different cultures as well as different definitions and meanings.
Aesthetics often establishes the pattern that connects culture
functions in a society. In African and African American societies
it functions as the keeper of the traditions. The African aesthetic
is visible from popular culture to the classical cultures. In all
art forms, including body adornment arts, there emerge symbols,
colors, rhythms, styles, and forms that function as artistic
instruments and cultural histories. While acknowledging African
cultural diversity, the focus here is on the commonalities in the
aesthetic that make an Ibo recognize a Kikuyu and a Jamaican
recognize a Chewa and an African American recognize a Sotho. The
deep structure manifest in African cultures in the diaspora is
proof of the aesthetic continuity. The debate continues over the
exact nature of African aesthetics, and in this volume scholars and
teachers in the fields of African and African American studies
approach the subject from a broad range of disciplines. Dance,
music, art, theatre, and literature are examined in order fully to
appreciate and delineate what the specific qualities and aspects of
an African aesthetic might be. Additionally, theoretical concepts
and issues are discussed in order to define more clearly what is
meant by an African aesthetic. The term African here applies to all
Africans, both continental and diasporan, and encompasses
historically used terms such as Negro, Black, and Afro-American.
This thoughtful and thought-provoking volume will be a valuable
addition to the readings of scholars and students in fields ranging
from African studies to general philosophy and cultural studies.
This book is a study of Aristotle's metaphysics in which the
central argument is that Aristotle's views on substance are a
direct response to Plato's Theory of Forms. The claim is that
Aristotle believes that many of Plato's views are tenable once one
has rejected Plato's notion of separation. There have been many
recent books on Aristotle's theory of substance. This one is
distinct from previous books in several ways: firstly, it offers a
completely new, coherent interpretation of Aristotle's claim that
substances are separate in which substances turn out to be
specimens of natural kinds. Secondly, it covers a broad range of
issues, including Aristotle's criticism of Plato, his views on
numerical sameness and identity, his epistemology and his account
of teleology. There is also a discussion of much of the recent
literature on Aristotle.
1.1. Why the Ontology 0/ Time? The intention that directs this
research consists in an attempt to provide a herme- neutic analysis
ofthe drastic changes, which have occurred in 20th century philoso-
phy, in identifying the new role ascribed to the subject of time
and temporality within the scope ofontology. Afterthe fundamental
works ofE. Husserl, M. Heid- egger. P. Rica:ur. and E. Levinas, it
has been understood that the traditional issue (which could be
traced back to Parmenides) between being and time, between the
eternal and the transient (or historical), must once again be
re-examined. Time it- self is recognized now as the deepest ground
of ontological inquiry, which sets in motion the entire system
offundamental philosophical concepts. This does not mean, of
course, that our understanding of time did not change in the course
of these fundamental transformations. In order to comprehend the
new role oftime within "first philosophy," the concept o/time
itselfis to be subjected to a careful investigation and
interpretation. It is necessary to come back to Aristotle's quest
ions in Physics IV: In what sense can we ascribe being to time
itself. and what is the "nature" of time as (a) being'! In other
words, to understand the role oftime within the scope of ontology
means to develop simultaneously the ontology 0/ time. This is what
the title ofthis work intends to designate. Moreover, my aim is to
dem- onstrate that in a defmite sense the postmodern onto-Iogy is
chrono-Iogy.
The problem of persistence is as old as the tradition of systematic
ontology. How can we explain that the middle-sized standard objects
of everyday s life are regarded normally as remaining 'the same',
even if they change their properties and their material
constituents? The aim of this edition is to present new arguments,
perspectives, and theoretical backgrounds concerning 'persistence':
There is much more to consider than the classical distinction
between 'endurantism' and 'perdurantism'. The volume includes
contributions authored by S. Barker, P. Dowe, A. Chrudzimski, P.
Grenon, B. Smith, L. Jansen, E.J. Lowe, U. Meixner, K. Miller, E.
Runggaldier, J. Seibt, and E. Tegtmeier."
1. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND The purpose of the book is to develop
internal realism, the metaphysical-episte mological doctrine
initiated by Hilary Putnam (Reason, Truth and History,
"Introduction," Many Faces). In doing so I shall rely - sometimes
quite heavily - on the notion of conceptual scheme. I shall use the
notion in a somewhat idiosyncratic way, which, however, has some
affinities with the ways the notion has been used during its
history. So I shall start by sketching the history of the notion.
This will provide some background, and it will also give
opportunity to raise some of the most important problems I will
have to solve in the later chapters. The story starts with Kant.
Kant thought that the world as we know it, the world of tables,
chairs and hippopotami, is constituted in part by the human mind.
His cen tral argument relied on an analysis of space and time, and
presupposed his famous doctrine that knowledge cannot extend beyond
all possible experience. It is a central property of experience -
he claimed - that it is structured spatially and temporally.
However, for various reasons, space and time cannot be features of
the world, as it is independently of our experience. So he
concluded that they must be the forms of human sensibility, i. e.
necessary ingredients of the way things appear to our senses."
This book introduces the reader to Whitehead's complex and often
misunderstood metaphysics by showing that it deals with questions
about the nature of causation originally raised by the philosophy
of Leibniz. Whitehead's philosophy is an attempt at rehabilitating
Leibniz's theory of monads by recasting it in terms of novel
ontological categories.
Gustav Bergmann (1906-1987) was, arguably, the greatest ontologist
of the twentieth century in pursuing the fundamental questions of
first philosophy as deeply as any philosopher of any time. In 2006
and 2007, international conferences devoted solely to Bergmann s
work were held at the University of Iowa in the USA, Universite de
Provence in France, and Universita degli Studi Roma Tre in Italy.
The papers in this volume were presented at the first of these
conferences, in Iowa City, where Bergmann taught for nearly four
decades after escaping from Europe, following the dissolution of
the Vienna Circle of which he had been the youngest member. There
are nine philosophical papers, reminiscences of three of his
students, and a complete bibliography of his published writings."
This book supports a version of the trope-bundle view of individual
substances matching also with a coherent account of change,
individuation and individual essences. In particular, it is argued
that qualitative individuation and qualitative individual essences
can be tackled within the frames of a trope account. The adoption
of a trope BT together with the individuation of tropes via the
bearer substance might create the feeling of circularity since
tropes and substances seem mutually to individuate each other. The
novel solution to the problem developed here consists in showing
that the individuation of concrete individual substances is
independent, in crucial respects, from the fact that they are
construed as bundles of tropes. Apart from metaphysician
colleagues, the book is recommended for advanced students in
analytic metaphysics.
This book describes issues in modeling unconventional conflict and
suggests a new way to do the modeling. It presents an ontology that
describes the unconventional conflict domain, which allows for
greater ease in modeling unconventional conflict. Supporting
holistic modeling, which means that we can see the entire picture
of what needs to be modeled, the ontology allows us to make
informed decisions about what to model and what to omit. The
unconventional conflict ontology also separates the things we
understand best from the things we understand least. This
separation means that we can perform verification, validation and
accreditation (VV&A) more efficiently and can describe the
competence of the model more accurately. However, before this
message can be presented in its entirety the supporting body of
knowledge has to be explored. For this reason, the book offers
chapters that focus on the description of unconventional conflict
and the analyses that have been performed, modeling, with a
concentration on past efforts at modeling unconventional conflict,
the precursors to the ontology, and VV&A. Unconventional
conflict is a complex, messy thing. It normally involves multiple
actors, with their own conflicting agendas and differing concepts
of legitimate actions. This book will present a useful introduction
for researchers and professionals within the field.
These essays bring together forty years of work in ontology.
Intentionality, negation, universals, bare particulars, tropes,
general facts, relations, the myth of the 'myth of the given', are
among the topics covered. Bergmann, Quine, Sellars, Russell,
Wittgenstein, Hume, Bradley, Hochberg, Dummett, Frege, Plato, are
among the philosophers discussed. The essays criticize non-Humean
notions of cause; they criticize the notion that besides simple
atomic facts there are also negative facts and general facts. They
defend a realism of properties as universals, against nominalism;
bare particulars; a (qualified) realism with regard to logical
form; a Russellian account of relations; and an account of minds
and intentionality, which is opposed to materialism, but is also a
form of (methodological) behaviourism. In general, the ontology is
one of logical atomism and empiricist throughout, rooted in a
Principle of Acquaintance.
Jan Patocka's contribution to phenomenology and the philosophy of
history mean that he is considered one of the most important
philosophers of the 20th century. Yet, his writing is not widely
available in English and the Anglophone world remains rather
unfamiliar with his work. In this new book of essential Patocka
texts, of which the majority have been translated from the original
Czech for the first time, readers will experience a general
introduction to the key tenets of his philosophy. This includes his
thoughts on the relationship between philosophy and political
engagement which strike at the heart of contemporary debates about
freedom, political participation and responsibility and a truly
pressing issue for modern Europe, what exactly constitutes a
European identity? In this important collection, Patocka provides
an original vision of the relationship between self, world, and
history that will benefit students, philosophers and those who are
interested in the ideals that underpin our democracies.
Naturalism is the reigning creed in analytic philosophy.
Naturalists claim that natural science provides a complete account
of all forms of existence. According to the naturalistic credo
there are no aspects of human existence which transcend methods and
explanations of science. Our concepts of the self, the mind,
subjectivity, human freedom or responsibility is to be defined in
terms of established sciences. The aim of the present volume is to
draw the balance of naturalism s success so far. Unlike other
volumes it does not contain a collection of papers which
unanimously reject naturalism. Naturalists and anti-naturalists
alike unfold their positions discussing the success or failure of
naturalistic approaches. "How successful is naturalism? shows where
the lines of agreement and disagreement between naturalists and
their critics are to be located in contemporary philosophical
discussion. With contributions of Rudder Lynne Baker, Johannes
Brandl, Helmut Fink, Ulrich Frey, Georg Gasser & Matthias
Stefan, Peter S.M. Hacker, Winfried Loffler, Nancey Murphy, Josef
Quitterer, Michael Rea, Thomas Sukopp, Konrad Talmont-Kaminski and
Gerd Vollmer."
When we ask whether something exists, we expect a yes or no answer,
not a further query about what kind of existence, how much of it,
whether we mean existence for you or existence for me, or whether
we are asking about some property which it might have. In this
book, this simple requirement is defended and pursued into its
various and sometimes surprising implications. In the course of
this pursuit, such questions arise as `Do appearances exist?' `Do
unknowable things exist?' `Do past and future exist?' `Does God
necessarily exist?' This novel and non-technical approach to
important philosophical questions will be of interest to senior
students of philosophy and, indeed, to all general readers with
philosophical interests.
Graham Priest presents an original exploration of philosophical
questions concerning the one and the many. He covers a wide range
of issues in metaphysics-including unity, identity, grounding,
mereology, universals, being, intentionality, and nothingness-and
deploys the techniques of paraconsistent logic in order to offer a
radically new treatment of unity. Priest brings together traditions
of Western and Asian thought that are usually kept separate in
academic philosophy: he draws on ideas from Plato, Heidegger, and
Nagarjuna, among other philosophers.
|
You may like...
Truth and Realism
Patrick Greenough, Michael P Lynch
Hardcover
R3,863
Discovery Miles 38 630
|