|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present > Western philosophy, from c 1900 -
Ludwig Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1922) remains
one of the most enigmatic works of twentieth century thought. In
this bold and original new study, Ben Ware argues that
Wittgenstein's early masterpiece is neither an analytic treatise on
language and logic, nor a quasi-mystical work seeking to
communicate 'ineffable' truths. Instead, we come to understand the
Tractatus by grasping it in a twofold sense: first, as a
dialectical work which invites the reader to overcome certain
'illusions of thought'; and second as a modernist work whose
anti-philosophical ambition is intimately tied to its radical
aesthetic character. By placing the Tractatus in the force field of
modernism, Dialectic of the Ladder clears the ground for a new and
challenging exploration of the work's ethical dimension. It also
casts new light upon the cultural, aesthetic and political
significances of Wittgenstein's writing, revealing hitherto
unacknowledged affinities with a host of philosophical and literary
authors, including Hegel, Kierkegaard, Marx, Nietzsche, Adorno,
Benjamin, and Kafka.
Although pain is one of the most fundamental and unique experiences
we undergo in everyday life, it also constitutes one of the most
enigmatic and frustrating subjects for many scientists. This book
provides a detailed analysis of why this issue is grounded in the
nature of pain itself. It also offers a philosophically driven
solution of how we may still approach pain in a theoretically
compelling and practically useful manner. Two main theses are
defended: (i) Pain seems inscrutable because there exists no
property that is commonly shared by all types of pain and that is
at the same time particular to pain, setting it apart from other
bodily sensations. This applies irrespective of whether we consider
the psychological dimensions, neural networks, causal relations or
biological functions of pain. Consequently, it is impossible to
refer to ideal far-reaching and ideal distinct generalizations on
the matter of pain. (ii) Despite this challenge, by focusing on the
resemblance relations that hold across pains, we can generate
scientific progress in explaining, predicting and treating pain. In
doing so, the book aims to provide a clear conceptual basis for
interdisciplinary communication and a useful heuristic for future
research.
This volume examines the question "Do abstract objects exist?",
presenting new work from contributing authors across different
branches of philosophy. The introduction overviews philosophical
debate which considers: what objects qualify as abstract, what do
we mean by the word "exist" and indeed, what evidence should count
in favor or against the thesis that abstract objects exist. Through
subsequent chapters readers will discover the ubiquity of abstract
objects as each philosophical field is considered. Given the
ubiquitous use of expressions that purportedly refer to abstract
objects, we think that it is relevant to attend to the controversy
between those who want to advocate the existence of abstract
objects and those who stand against them. Contributions to this
volume depict positions and debates that directly or indirectly
involve taking one position or other about abstract objects of
different kinds and categories. The volume provides a variety of
samples of how positions for or against abstract objects can be
used in different areas of philosophy in relation to different
matters.
This edited volume offers a new approach to understanding social
conventions by way of Martin Heidegger. It connects the
philosopher's conceptions of the anyone, everydayness, and
authenticity with an analysis and critique of social normativity.
Heidegger's account of the anyone is ambiguous. Some see it as a
good description of human sociality, others think of it as an
important critique of modern mass society. This volume seeks to
understand this ambiguity as reflecting the tension between the
constitutive function of conventions for human action and the
critical aspects of conformism. It argues that Heidegger's anyone
should neither be reduced to its pejorative nor its constitutive
dimension. Rather, the concept could show how power and norms
function. This volume would be of interest to scholars and students
of philosophy and the social sciences who wish to investigate the
social applications of the works of Martin Heidegger.
Frege's puzzle concerning belief reports has been in the middle of
the discussion on semantics and pragmatics of attitude reports: The
intuition behind the opacity does not seem to be consistent with
the thesis of semantic innocence according to which the semantic
value of proper names is nothing but their referent. Main tasks of
this book include providing truth-conditional content of belief
reports. Especially, the focus is on semantic values of proper
names. The key aim is to extend Crimmins's basic idea of semantic
pretense and the introduction of pleonastic entities proposed by
Schiffer. They enable us to capture Frege's puzzle in the analysis
without giving up semantic innocence. To reach this conclusion, two
issues are established. First, based on linguistic evidence, the
frame of belief reports functions adverbially rather than
relationally. Second, the belief ascriptions, on which each belief
report is made, must be analyzed in terms of the
measurement-theoretic analogy.
This book presents Heidegger as a thinker of revolution.
Understanding revolution as an occurrence whereby the previously
unforeseeable comes to appear as inevitable, the temporal character
of such an event is explored through Heidegger's discussion of
temporality and historicity. Beginning with his magnum opus, Being
and Time, Heidegger is shown to have undertaken a radical
rethinking of time in terms of human action, understood as
involving both doing and making and as implicated in an interplay
of the opportune moment (kairos) and temporal continuity (chronos).
Developing this theme through his key writings of the early 1930s,
the book shows how Heidegger's analyses of truth and freedom led to
an increasingly dialectical account of time and action culminating
in his phenomenology of the - artistic and political - 'work'. A
context is thus given for Heidegger's political engagement in 1933.
While diagnosing the moral failure of this engagement, the book
defends Heidegger's account of the time of human action and shows
it to foreshadow his later thought of a 'new beginning'.
This collection is an attempt by a diverse range of authors to
reignite interest in C.I. Lewis's work within the pragmatist and
analytic traditions. Although pragmatism has enjoyed a renewed
popularity in the past thirty years, some influential pragmatists
have been overlooked. C. I. Lewis is arguably the most important of
overlooked pragmatists and was highly influential within his own
time period. The volume assembles a wide range of perspectives on
the strengths and weaknesses of Lewis's contributions to
metaphysics, epistemology, semantics, philosophy of science, and
ethics.
Through both an historical and philosophical analysis of the
concept of possibility, we show how including both potentiality and
actuality as part of the real is both compatible with experience
and contributes to solving key problems of fundamental process and
emergence. The book is organized into four main sections that
incorporate our routes to potentiality: (1) potentiality in modern
science [history and philosophy; quantum physics and complexity];
(2) Relational Realism [ontological interpretation of quantum
physics; philosophy and logic]; (3) Process Physics [ontological
interpretation of relativity theory; physics and philosophy]; (4)
on speculative philosophy and physics [limitations and
approximations; process philosophy]. We conclude that certain
fundamental problems in modern physics require complementary
analyses of certain philosophical and metaphysical issues, and that
such scholarship reveals intrinsic features and limits of
determinism, potentiality and emergence that enable, among others,
important progress on the quantum theory of measurement problem and
new understandings of emergence.
"Herbartism in Austrian-Hungarian philosophy" is often an
obligatory reference, but even if quoting Herbart and his school is
frequent, reading them attentively is less evident. Because
Herbartism reached its peak in the second half of the 19th century,
and was effectively institutionalized as "official philosophy" of
the Austro-Hungarian Empire, at least in Prague and Vienna,
criticizing Herbartism often means discussing the "Austrian",
"philosophical" and "institutional" criteria of the object under
consideration. As the history of the Austrian tradition and
theoretical reflections in this field expand, discussion of this
tradition is becoming more and more tight and precise. The
contributors in this volume recall the historical and conceptual
importance of Herbartism in the field of Austrian philosophy, by
addressing several aspects of his specific realism: philosophical,
theoretical, pedagogical, psychological, and aesthetical.
This volume presents political phenomenology as a new specialty in
western philosophical and political thought that is post-classical,
post-Machiavellian, and post-behavioral. It draws on history and
sets the agenda for future explorations of political issues. It
discloses crossroads between ethics and politics and explores
border-crossing issues. All the essays in this volume challenge
existing ideas of politics significantly. As such they open new
ways for further explorations BY future generations of
phenomenologists and non-phenomenologists alike. Moreover, the
comprehensive chronological bibliography is unprecedented and
provides not only an excellent picture of what phenomenologists
have already done but also a guide for the future.
Imagination and Postmodernity addresses the role of the imagination
in philosophy today. By focusing on philosophy at the boundary of
reason with constant reference to Kant s view of the
boundary-limit, it is possible to advance a viable alternative to
deconstructing the imagination. Patrick L. Bourgeois puts forth the
claim that by refocusing the imagination in the postmodern
conversation, a far-reaching contemporary position can be reached
that reestablishes the position of the humanities as central
against the anti-humanism of deconstruction. This work addresses
some of the challenges and problems that emerge in conflicting
positions within contemporary philosophy, including a concentration
on the role of the imagination in the work of Paul Ricoeur in
contrast and in opposition to its role in such postmodern thinkers
as Derrida and Lyotard. This treatment requires going back to the
role of the imagination in the period of Kant and his immediate
followers in order to clarify the various ways of seeing the
imagination then and now, for the role today is anticipated in the
nineteenth century. Finally, this work, as a creative appropriation
of the position of Paul Ricoeur, presents a role for the
imagination today that is more encompassing than most thinkers
allow for.
This is a translation of Rossi's account of the art of memory and
the logic of linkage and combination
This is the first volume dedicated to a direct exploration of
Wittgenstein and Plato. It is a compilation of essays by thirteen
authors of diverse geographical provenance, orientation and
philosophical interest.
The volume offers the most complete and detailed view to date on
Wittgenstein and Plato, without being tied to any unilateral
guidelines from either a critical or philosophical perspective. The
authors are scholars of Wittgenstein, but also of Plato and Greek
philosophy. The book is a sort of game of mirrors: Plato in the
mirror of Wittgenstein, and Wittgenstein in the mirror of Plato.
All essays always seek to combine philosophical interest and
philological attention, although, in some essays one interest
prevails over the other.
Despite the preponderance of scholars of Wittgenstein, the volume
seeks to be not only a book on Wittgenstein and Plato, but also,
simultaneously, on Plato and Wittgenstein.
The history of interwar Polish logic, including philosophical
logic, is still a relatively little known area, especially if
compared with the movement's well-documented contemporaries - the
Vienna Circle or the Berlin Circle, for instance. The book aims to
address this lacuna, by presenting the state of the art of research
into this part of the history of analytic philosophy. It comprises
thirteen essays, written by outstanding philosophers and
exemplifying different approaches to the history of philosophy. One
approach focuses on some little known aspects of Polish philosophy
(e.g., Lesniewski's arithmetic, Tarski's geometry, philosophy of
mathematics in interwar Krakow), analyzing it in great detail,
sometimes by using current formal techniques. Another group of
papers looks at the inspiration the Poles got from the founding
fathers of analytic philosophy (Frege, Husserl, Wittgenstein), and
locates Polish philosophy in the larger landscape of European
analytic philosophy. Finally, some contributors pick a topic from
the Polish school (sometimes only mentioned, but not developed by
the Poles), and construct an alternative account which is then
compared with the earlier account. Most of the papers were
presented at a symposium celebrating the 70th birthday of Jan
Wolenski, whose book "Logic and Philosophy of the Lvov-Warsaw
School" has played a substantial role in sparking contemporary
interest in Polish analytic philosophy.
This volume focuses on controversial issues that stem from Philippa
Foot's later writings on natural goodness which are at the center
of contemporary discussions of virtue ethics. The chapters address
questions about how Foot relates judgments of moral goodness to
human nature, how Foot understands happiness, and addresses
objections to her framework from the perspective of empirical
biology. The volume will be of value to any student or scholar with
an interest in virtue ethics and analytic moral philosophy.
Through an engagement with the philosophies of Proust's
contemporaries, Felix Ravaisson, Henri Bergson, and Georg Simmel,
Suzanne Guerlac presents an original reading of Remembrance of
Things Past (A la recherche du temps perdu). Challenging
traditional interpretations, she argues that Proust's magnum opus
is not a melancholic text, but one that records the dynamic time of
change and the complex vitality of the real. Situating Proust's
novel within a modernism of money, and broadening the exploration
through references to cultural events and visual technologies
(commercial photography, photojournalism, pornography, the
regulation of prostitution, the Panama Scandal, and the Dreyfus
Affair), this study reveals that Proust's subject is not the
esthetic recuperation of loss but rather the adventure of living in
time, on both the individual and the social level, at a concrete
historical moment.
One hundred years ago, Russell and Whitehead published their
epoch-making Principia Mathematica (PM), which was initially
conceived as the second volume of Russell's Principles of
Mathematics (PoM) that had appeared ten years before. No other
works can be credited to have had such an impact on the development
of logic and on philosophy in the twentieth century. However, until
now, scholars only focused on the first parts of the books - that
is, on Russell's and Whitehead's theory of logic, set-theory and
arithmetic.
Sebastien Gandon aims at reversing the perspective. His goal is to
give a picture of Russell's logicism based on a detailed reading of
the developments dealing with advanced mathematics - namely
projective geometry and the theory of quantity. This book is not
only the first study ever made of the 'later' portions of PoM and
PM, it also shows how this shift of perspective compels us to
change our view of the logicist program taken as a whole.
"The World Unclaimed" argues that Heidegger's critique of modern
epistemology in "Being and Time" is seriously flawed. Heidegger
believes he has done away with epistemological problems concerning
the external world by showing that the world is an existential
structure of Dasein. However, the author argues that Heidegger
fails to make good his claim that he has "rescued" the phenomenon
of the world, which he believes the tradition of philosophy has
bypassed. Heidegger fails not only to reclaim the world but also to
acknowledge its loss. Alweiss thus calls into question Heidegger's
claim that ontology is more fundamental than epistemology.
"The World Unclaimed" develops its powerful critique of Being and
Time by arguing for a return to Husserl. It draws on Husserl's
insight that it is the moving and sensing body that discloses how
we are already familiar with the world. Kinaesthesia provides a key
for understanding our relation to the world. The author thus
suggests that thinkers in the vein of Husserl and Kant -who, for
Heidegger, epitomize the tradition of modern philosophy by
returning to a "worldless subject"- may provide us with the
resources to reclaim the phenomenon of the world that "Being and
Time" sets out to salvage.
Alweiss's fresh and innovative study demonstrates that it is
possible to overcome epistemological skepticism without ever losing
sight of the phenomenon of the world. Moreover, Alweiss challenges
us to reconsider the relation between Husserl and Heidegger by
providing a forceful defense of Husserl's critique of cognition.
In this brief and accessible introduction, Russell guides the
reader through his famous 1910 distinction between "knowledge by
acquaintance and knowledge by description" and introduces important
theories of Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Hume, Locke, Kant, Hegel
and others. He lays the foundation for philosophical inquiry for
general readers and scholars.There are sixteen chapters: Appearance
and Reality, The Existence of Matter, The Nature of Matter,
Idealism, Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description,
On Induction, On Our Knowledge Of General Principles, How A Priori
Knowledge Is Possible, The World of Universals, On Our Knowledge of
Universals, On Intuitive Knowledge, Truth and Falsehood, Knowledge,
Error, and Probable Opinion, The Limits of Philosophical Knowledge,
The Value of Philosophy. Russell also provides a short
supplementary reading list.
What are the implications of philosophical pragmatism for
international relations theory and foreign policy practice?
According to John Ryder, "a foreign policy built on pragmatist
principles is neither naive nor dangerous. In fact, it is very much
what both the U.S. and the world are currently in need of." Close
observers of Barack Obama's foreign policy statements have also
raised the possibility of a distinctly pragmatist approach to
international relations. Absent from the three dominant theoretical
perspectives in the field-realism, idealism and constructivism-is
any mention of pragmatism, except in the very limited,
instrumentalist sense of choosing appropriate foreign policy tools
to achieve proposed policy objectives. The key commitments of any
international relations approach in the pragmatist tradition could
include a flexible approach to crafting policy ends, theory
integrally related to practice, a concern for both the normative
and explanatory dimensions of international relations research, and
policy means treated as hypotheses for experimental testing.
Following the example of classic pragmatists such as John Dewey and
neo-pragmatists like Richard Rorty, international relations
scholars and foreign policy practitioners would have to forgo grand
theories, instead embracing a situationally-specific approach to
understanding and addressing emerging global problems.
Unfortunately, commentary on the relationship between philosophical
pragmatism and international relations has been limited. The
authors in Philosophical Pragmatism and International Relations
remedies this lacuna by exploring ways in which philosophical
pragmatism, both classic and contemporary, can inform international
relations theory and foreign policy practice today.
A comprehensive and accessible overview of, and introduction to,
the work of one of the twentieth century's most influential
philosophers, Martin Heidegger, by one of the world's foremost
Heidegger scholars. Martin Heidegger's work is pivotal in the
history of modern European philosophy. The New Heidegger presents a
comprehensive and stimulating overview of, and introduction to, the
work of one of the most influential and controversial philosophers
of our time. Heidegger has had an extraordinary impact on
contemporary philosophical and extra-philosophical life: on
deconstruction, hermeneutics, ontology, technology and
techno-science, art and architecture, politics, psychotherapy, and
ecology. The New Heidegger takes a thematic approach to Heidegger's
work, covering not only the seminal Being and Time, but also
Heidegger's lesser-known works. Lively, clear and succinct, the
book requires no prior knowledge of Heidegger and is an essential
resource for anyone studying or teaching the work of this major
modern philosopher.
|
|