|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy
Excursions with Thoreau is a major new exploration of Thoreau's
writing and thought that is philosophical yet sensitive to the
literary and religious. Edward F. Mooney's excursions through
passages from Walden, Cape Cod, and his late essay "Walking" reveal
Thoreau as a miraculous writer, artist, and religious adept. Of
course Thoreau remains the familiar political activist and
environmental philosopher, but in these fifteen excursions we
discover new terrain. Among the notable themes that emerge are
Thoreau's grappling with underlying affliction; his pursuit of
wonder as ameliorating affliction; his use of the enigmatic image
of "a child of the mist"; his exalting "sympathy with intelligence"
over plain knowledge; and his preferring "befitting reverie"-not
argument-as the way to be carried to better, cleaner perceptions of
reality. Mooney's aim is bring alive Thoreau's moments of reverie
and insight, and to frame his philosophy as poetic and episodic
rather than discursive and systematic.
In archaic societies myths were believed to tell true stories -
stories about the ultimate origin of reality. For us, on the
contrary, the term 'myth' denotes a false belief. Between the
archaic notion of myth and ours stands Plato's. This 2009 volume is
a collection of ten studies by eminent scholars that focus on the
ways in which some of Plato's most famous myths are interwoven with
his philosophy. The myths discussed include the eschatological
myths of the Gorgias, the Phaedo, the Republic and Laws 10, the
central myths of the Phaedrus and the Statesman, and the so-called
myth of the Noble Lie from the Republic. The mythical character of
the Timaeus cosmology is also amply discussed. The volume also
contains seventeen rare Renaissance illustrations of Platonic
myths. The contributors argue that in Plato myth and philosophy are
tightly bound together, despite Plato's occasional claim that they
are opposed modes of discourse.
Antonia Lolordo presents an original interpretation of John Locke's
conception of moral agency-one that has implications both for his
metaphysics and for the foundations of his political theory. Locke
denies that species boundaries exist independently of human
convention, holds that the human mind may be either an immaterial
substance or a material one to which God has superadded the power
of thought, and insists that animals possess the ability to
perceive, will, and even reason-indeed, in some cases to reason
better than humans. Thus, he eliminates any sharp distinction
between humans and the rest of the animal kingdom. However, in his
ethical and political work Locke assumes that there is a sharp
distinction between moral agents and other beings. He thus needs to
be able to delineate the set of moral agents precisely, without
relying on the sort of metaphysical and physical facts his
predecessors appealed to. Lolordo argues that for Locke, to be a
moral agent is simply to be free, rational, and a person.
Interpreting the Lockean metaphysics of moral agency in this way
helps us to understand both Locke's over-arching philosophical
project and the details of his accounts of liberty, personhood, and
rationality.
From the early 1790s until after the turn of the century, a very
productive but also controversial exchange took place between
Reinhold and Fichte. Though many key aspects of post-Kantian
philosophy were discussed, the philosophical confrontation between
Reinhold and Fichte is most instructive for the understanding of
post-Kantian philosophy. The exchange started when Fichte published
his verdict on Reinhold's Elementarphilosophie and disapproved of
its fundamental principle. In 1794 Fichte challenged Reinhold by
presenting his Wissenschaftslehre. Reinhold was not convinced of
Fichte's foundation of philosophy at first, but announced that he
accepted the Wissenschaftslehre in 1797. While Reinhold and Fichte
officially collaborated in the following three years, tensions
concerning fundamental questions were still present. When Reinhold
adopted Rational Realism, his relation to Fichte deteriorated and
the exchange between the two finally ended. The contributions in
the present collection focus on the central systematic issues at
the different stages of the confrontation between Fichte and
Reinhold, thereby illuminating questions that are essential to the
understanding of the evolution of post-Kantian German philosophy.
This book aims to explain the decline of the later Wittgensteinian
tradition in analytic philosophy during the second half of the
twentieth century. Throughout the 1950s, Oxford was the center of
analytic philosophy and Wittgenstein - the later Wittgenstein - the
most influential contemporary thinker within that philosophical
tradition. Wittgenstein's methods and ideas were widely accepted,
with everything seeming to point to the Wittgensteinian paradigm
having a similar impact on the philosophical scenes of all English
speaking countries. However, this was not to be the case. By the
1980s, albeit still important, Wittgenstein was considered as a
somewhat marginal thinker. What occurred within the history of
analytic philosophy to produce such a decline? This book expertly
traces the early reception of Wittgenstein in the United States,
the shift in the humanities to a tradition rooted in the natural
sciences, and the economic crisis of the mid-1970s, to reveal the
factors that contributed to the eventual hostility towards the
later Wittgensteinian tradition.
Paul Ricoeur (1913-2005) was one of the most prolific and
influential French philosophers of the Twentieth Century. In his
enormous corpus of work he engaged with literature, history,
historiography, politics, theology and ethics, while debating
'truth' and ethical solutions to life in the face of widespread and
growing suspicion about whether such a search is either possible or
worthwhile.In Ricoeur and the Hermeneutics of Suspicion, Alison
Scott-Baumann takes a thematic approach that explores Ricoeur's
lifelong struggle to be both iconoclastic and yet hopeful, and
avoid the slippery slope to relativism. Through an examination of
the 'hermeneutics of suspicion', the book reveals strong
continuities throughout his work, as well as significant
discontinuities, such as the marked way in which he later distanced
himself from the 'hermeneutics of suspicion' and his development of
new devices in its place, while seeking a hermeneutics of recovery.
Scott-Baumann offers a highly original analysis of the hermeneutics
of suspicion that will be useful to the fields of philosophy,
literature, theology and postmodern social theory.
Now available in English for the first time, Norwegian philosopher
Arne Naess's meditation on the art of living is an exhortation to
preserve the environment and biodiversity. As Naess approaches his
ninetieth year, he offers a bright and bold perspective on the
power of feelings to move us away from ecological and cultural
degradation toward sound, future-focused policy and action. Naess
acknowledges the powerlessness of the intellect without the heart,
and, like Thoreau before him, he rejects the Cartesian notion of
mind-body separation. He advocates instead for the integration of
reason and emotion-a combination Naess believes will inspire us to
make changes for the better. Playful and serious, this is a
guidebook for finding our way on a planet wrecked by the harmful
effects of consumption, population growth, commodification,
technology, and globalization. It is sure to mobilize today's
philosophers, environmentalists, policy makers, and the general
public into seeking-with whole hearts rather than with superficial
motives-more effective and timelier solutions. Naess's style is
reflective and anecdotal as he shares stories and details from his
rich and long life. With characteristic goodwill, wit, and wisdom,
he denounces our unsustainable actions while simultaneously
demonstrating the unsurpassed wonder, beauty, and possibility our
world offers, and ultimately shows us that there is always reason
for hope, that everyone is a potential ally in our fight for the
future.
The philosophical and philological study of Aristotle fragments and
lost works has fallen somewhat into the background since the
1960's. This is regrettable considering the different and
innovative directions the study of Aristotle has taken in the last
decades. This collection of new peer-reviewed essays applies the
latest developments and trends of analysis, criticism, and
methodology to the study of Aristotle's fragments. The individual
essays use the fragments as tools of interpretation, shed new light
on different areas of Aristotle philosophy, and lay bridges between
Aristotle's lost and extant works. The first part shows how
Aristotle frames parts of his own understanding of Philosophy in
his published, 'popular' work. The second part deals with issues of
philosophical interpretation in Aristotle's extant works which can
be illuminated by fragments of his lost works. The philosophical
issues treated in this section range from Theology to Natural
Science, Psychology, Politics, and Poetics. As a whole, the book
articulates a new approach to Aristotle's lost works, by providing
a reassessment and new methodological explorations of the
fragments.
This book examines South Africa's post-apartheid culture through
the lens of affect theory in order to argue that the
socio-political project of the "new" South Africa, best exemplified
in their Truth and Reconciliation Commission Hearings, was
fundamentally an affective, emotional project. Through the TRC
hearings, which publicly broadcast the testimonies of both victims
and perpetrators of gross human rights violations, the African
National Congress government of South Africa, represented by Nelson
Mandela and Archbishop Desmond Tutu, endeavoured to generate
powerful emotions of contrition and sympathy in order to build an
empathetic bond between white and black citizens, a bond referred
to frequently by Tutu in terms of the African philosophy of
interconnection: ubuntu. This book explores the representations of
affect, and the challenges of generating ubuntu, through close
readings of a variety of cultural products: novels, poetry, memoir,
drama, documentary film and audio anthology.
Our era is profoundly marked by the phenomenon of exile and it is
has become increasingly urgent to rethink the concept of exile and
our stance towards it. This renewed reflection on the problem of
exile brings to the fore a number of questions regarding the
traditionally negative connotation of exile. Is there not another
way to understand the condition of exile? Permeated with references
to the 'stranger', the 'other' and 'exteriority', the philosophy of
Emmanuel Levinas signifies a positive understanding of exile. This
original and compelling book distills from Levinas's philosophy a
wisdom of exile, for the first time shedding a positive light on
the condition of exile itself. Abi Doukhan argues that Levinas's
philosophy can be understood as a comprehensive philosophy of
exile, from his ethics to his thoughts on society, love, knowledge,
spirituality and art, thereby presenting a comprehensive view of
the philosophy of Levinas himself as well as a renewed
understanding of the wealth and contribution of exile to a given
society.
Alain Badiou is undoubtedly the most exciting and influential voice
in contemporary French philosophy and one of the most important
theorists at work today. His impact on continental philosophy and
the wider philosophy community, politics and the arts in the last
twenty years has been immense. Alain Badiou: Live Theory offers a
concise and accessible introduction to his work and thought, laying
out the central themes of his major works, including his magnum
opus, Being and Event, and its long-awaited sequel, Logics of
Worlds. Oliver Feltham explores the fundamental questions through
which Badiou's philosophy constantly evolves, identifies the key
turning points in his ideas, and makes a clear case for the
coherence and powerful singularity of his thought when employed in
the analysis of political and artistic situations. Feltham examines
the thinkers and theorists with whom Badiou has engaged and who
have engaged with him, arguing that Badiou's work is compelling
precisely because it opens up new genealogies and new polemics in
the intellectual landscape. The book includes a brand new interview
with Badiou, in which he discusses his current concerns and future
plans. This is the ideal companion to study for students and
readers encountering this fascinating thinker for the first time.
This book provides a concise and coherent overview of Jeremy
Bentham, the widely read and studied political philosopher - ideal
for undergraduates who require more than just a simple introduction
to his work and thought. Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832), utilitarian
philosopher and reformer, is a key figure in our intellectual
heritage, and a far more subtle, sophisticated, and profound
thinker than his popular reputation suggests. "Bentham: A Guide for
the Perplexed" presents a clear account of his life and thought,
and highlights his relevance to contemporary debates in philosophy,
politics, and law. Key concepts and themes, including Bentham's
theory of logic and language, his utilitarianism, his legal theory,
his panopticon prison, and his democratic politics, together with
his views on religion, sex, and torture, are lucidly explored. The
book also contains an illuminating discussion of the nature of the
text from the perspective of an experienced textual editor.The book
will not only prove exceptionally valuable to students who need to
reach a sound understanding of Bentham's ideas, serving as a clear
and concise introduction to his philosophy, but also form an
original contribution to Bentham studies more generally. It is the
ideal companion for the study of this most influential and
challenging of thinkers. "Continuum's Guides for the Perplexed" are
clear, concise and accessible introductions to thinkers, writers
and subjects that students and readers can find especially
challenging - or indeed downright bewildering. Concentrating
specifically on what it is that makes the subject difficult to
grasp, these books explain and explore key themes and ideas,
guiding the reader towards a thorough understanding of demanding
material.
George Berkeley was an idealist and an extraordinarily eloquent man
of letters. Yet his views are traditionally regarded as wild and
extravagant. He is well known for his departure from common sense,
yet perversely represents himself as siding with 'the common folk',
presenting a complex challenge for students. Berkeley A Guide for
the Perplexed is a clear and thorough account of Berkeley's
philosophy. The book covers the whole range of Berkeley's
philosophical work, offering an accessible review of his views on
philosophy and common sense and the nature of philosophical
perplexity, together with an examination of his two major
philosophical works, The Principles of Human Knowledge and Three
Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. Geared towards the specific
requirements of students who need to reach a sound understanding of
Berkeley's thought, the book provides a cogent and reliable survey
of the various concepts and paradoxes of his thought. This is the
ideal companion to the study of this most influential and
challenging of philosophers.
Continuum's "Guides for the Perplexed" are clear, concise and
accessible introductions to thinkers, writers and subjects that
students and readers can find especially challenging. Concentrating
specifically on what it is that makes the subject difficult to
fathom, these books explain and explore key themes and ideas,
guiding the reader towards a thorough understanding of demanding
material. Benedict de Spinoza is a major philosopher of enduring
influence and importance, whose work is encountered by all serious
students of Western philosophy; his "Ethics" is one of the seminal
works of moral, religious and political thought. Nevertheless,
Spinoza is a considerable challenge for the modern student; his
language, rooted in the vocabulary of late medieval scholasticism
is frequently opaque, while the esoteric themes explored in his
work often require elucidation. "Spinoza: A Guide for the
Perplexed" provides that elucidation, offering a thorough account
and analysis of Spinoza's key works and overall philosophical
project. The text equips the reader with the necessary means to
draw full and clear understanding from Spinoza's often inaccessible
language and complex philosophical system and method. His "Ethics"
and political treatises are covered in detail; Spinoza's
'geometrical' approach to his subject is opened up, and his obscure
terminology fully explained. The book concludes with a valuable
assessment of Spinoza's enduring influence and his relevance for
contemporary philosophical debates and concerns. It is an excellent
support resource for anyone trying to get to grips with this
challenging and important philosopher.
This is volume 16 in the "Major Conservative and Libertarian
Thinkers" series. The Scottish philosopher Adam Smith (1723-1790)
was as a pioneer of political economy. In fact, his economic
thought became the foundation of classical economics and his key
work, "An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of
Nations", is considered to be the first modern work in economics.
For Smith, a free competition environment was the best way to
foster economic development that would work in accordance with
natural laws. The framework he set up to explain the free market
remains true to this day. "Major Conservative and Libertarian
Thinkers" provides comprehensive accounts of the works of seminal
conservative thinkers from a variety of periods, disciplines, and
traditions - the first series of its kind. Even the selection of
thinkers adds another aspect to conservative thinking, including
not only theorists but also writers and practitioners. The series
comprises twenty volumes, each including an intellectual biography,
historical context, critical exposition of the thinker's work,
reception and influence, contemporary relevance, bibliography
including references to electronic resources, and an index.
The book is the first detailed and full exegesis of the role of
death in Heidegger's philosophy and provides a decisive answer to
the question of being. It is well-known that Heidegger asked the
"question of being". It is equally commonplace to assume that
Heidegger failed to provide a proper answer to the question. In
this provocative new study Niederhauser argues that Heidegger gives
a distinct response to the question of being and that the
phenomenon of death is key to finding and understanding it. The
book offers challenging interpretations of crucial moments of
Heidegger's philosophy such as aletheia, the history of being,
time, technology, the fourfold, mortality, the meaning of
existence, the event, and language. Niederhauser makes the case
that any reading of Heidegger that ignores death cannot fully
understand those concepts. The book argues that death is central to
Heidegger's "thinking path" from the early 1920s until his late
post-war philosophy. The book thus attempts to show that there is a
unity of the early and late Heidegger often ignored by other
commentators. Niederhauser argues that death is the fulcrum of
Heidegger's ontology and the turning point of the history of being.
Death resurfaces at the most crucial moments of the "thinking path"
- from beginning to end. The book is of interest to those invested
in current debates on the ethics of dying and the transhumanist
project of digital human immortality. The text also shows that for
Heidegger philosophy means first and foremost to learn how to die.
This volume speaks to continental and analytical philosophers and
students alike as it draws on a number of diverse Heidegger
interpretations and appreciates intercultural differences in
reading Heidegger.
Weakness of will, the phenomenon of acting contrary to one's own
better judgment, has remained a prominent discussion topic of
philosophy. The history of this discussion in ancient, medieval,
and modern times has been outlined in many studies. Weakness of
Will in Renaissance and ReformationThought is, however, the first
book to cover the fascinating source materials on weakness of will
between 1350 and 1650. In addition to considering the work of a
broad range of Renaissance authors (including Petrarch, Donato
Acciaiuoli, John Mair, and Francesco Piccolomini), Risto Saarinen
explores the theologically coloured debates of the Reformation
period, such as those provided by Martin Luther, Philip
Melanchthon, John Calvin, and Lambert Daneau. He goes on to discuss
the impact of these authors on prominent figures of early
modernity, including Shakespeare, Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz.
While most of the historical research on weakness of will has
focused on the reception history of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics,
Saarinen pays attention to the Platonic and Stoic discussions and
their revival during the Renaissance and the Reformation. He also
shows the ways in which Augustine's discussion of the divided will
is intertwined with the Christian reception of ancient Greek
ethics, and argues that the theological underpinnings of early
modern authors do not rule out weakness of will, but transform the
philosophical discussion and lead it towards new solutions.
Michael Forster here presents a ground-breaking study of German
philosophy of language in the nineteenth century (and beyond). His
previous book, After Herder, showed that the eighteenth-century
philosopher J.G. Herder played the fundamental role in founding
modern philosophy of language, including new theories of
interpretation ('hermeneutics') and translation, as well as in
establishing such whole new disciplines concerned with language as
anthropology and linguistics. This new volume reveals that Herder's
ideas continued to have a profound impact on such important
nineteenth-century thinkers as Friedrich Schlegel (the leading
German Romantic), Wilhelm von Humboldt (a founder of linguistics),
and G.W.F. Hegel (the leading German Idealist). Forster shows that
the most valuable ideas about language in this tradition were
continuous with Herder's, whereas deviations from the latter that
occurred tended to be inferior. This book not only sets the
historical record straight but also champions the Herderian
tradition for its philosophical depth and breadth.
The Long Life invites the reader to range widely from the writings
of Plato through to recent philosophical work by Derek Parfit,
Bernard Williams, and others, and from Shakespeare's King Lear
through works by Thomas Mann, Balzac, Dickens, Beckett, Stevie
Smith, Philip Larkin, to more recent writing by Saul Bellow, Philip
Roth, and J. M. Coetzee.
Helen Small argues that if we want to understand old age, we have
to think more fundamentally about what it means to be a person, to
have a life, to have (or lead) a good life, to be part of a just
society. What did Plato mean when he suggested that old age was the
best place from which to practice philosophy - or Thomas Mann when
he defined old age as the best time to be a writer - and were they
right? If we think, as Aristotle did, that a good life requires the
active pursuit of virtue, how will our view of later life be
affected? If we think that lives and persons are unified, much as
stories are said to be unified, how will our thinking about old age
differ from that of someone who thinks that lives and/or persons
can be strongly discontinuous? In a just society, what constitutes
a fair distribution of limited resources between the young and the
old? How, if at all, should recent developments in the theory of
evolutionary senescence alter our thinking about what it means to
grow old?
This is a groundbreaking book, deep as well as broad, and likely
to alter the way in which we talk about one of the great social
concerns of our time - the growing numbers of those living to be
old, and the growing proportion of the old to the young.
This work examines the unique way in which Benedict de Spinoza
(1632-77) combines two significant philosophical principles: that
real existence requires causal power and that geometrical objects
display exceptionally clearly how things have properties in virtue
of their essences. Valtteri Viljanen argues that underlying
Spinoza's psychology and ethics is a compelling metaphysical theory
according to which each and every genuine thing is an entity of
power endowed with an internal structure akin to that of
geometrical objects. This allows Spinoza to offer a theory of
existence and of action - human and non-human alike - as dynamic
striving that takes place with the same kind of necessity and
intelligibility that pertain to geometry. Viljanen's fresh and
original study will interest a wide range of readers in Spinoza
studies and early modern philosophy more generally.
|
|