|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy
Heidegger and the Emergence of the Question of Being offers a new,
updated and comprehensive introduction to Heidegger's development
and his early confrontation with philosophical tradition, theology,
neo-Kantianism, vitalism, hermeneutics, and phenomenology, up to
the publication of Being and Time in 1927. The main thread is the
genealogy of the question of the meaning of being. Alongside the
most recent scholarly research, this book takes into account the
documentary richness of Heidegger's first Freiburg (1919-1923) and
Marburg (1923-1928) lectures, conferences, treatises and letters
and addresses the thematic and methodological richness of this
period of Heidegger's intellectual life, and offers a coherent and
unified interpretation of his earlier work. This book conveys
Heidegger's thought in a well-organized, impartial manner, without
deviating too far from Heideggerian vocabulary. It will be
invaluable for upper level undergraduates, graduate students of
philosophy, studying phenomenology, continental and German
philosophy.
This volume offers a much needed shift of focus in the study of
emotion in the history of philosophy. Discussion has tended to
focus on the moral relevance of emotions, and (except in ancient
philosophy) the role of emotions in cognitive life has received
little attention. Thirteen new essays investigate the continuities
between medieval and early modern thinking about the emotions, and
open up a contemporary debate on the relationship between emotions,
cognition, and reason, and the way emotions figure in our own
cognitive lives. A team of leading philosophers of the medieval,
renaissance, and early modern periods explore these ideas from the
point of view of four key themes: the situation of emotions within
the human mind; the intentionality of emotions and their role in
cognition; emotions and action; the role of emotion in
self-understanding and the social situation of individuals.
This text presents and addresses the philosophical movement of
antiphilosophy working thru the texts of Christian thinkers such as
Pascal and Kierkegaard. The author as influenced by Alain Badiou,
portrays these Christian thinkers as of a subjective dimension
negating the possibility of an objective quest for truth. The claim
here is that antiphilosophy is abundant in the eyes of these two
thinkers who frame the thought event as represented by
Christianity, ultimately resigning itself to more or less the
opposite of philosophy itself. Readers will discover why
philosophical reason should never be convinced by that which denies
its very authority. Subjecting faith to the perils of philosophical
analysis, confronting the philosophical tradition with the truth of
the Christian faith, and occupying the space between the two: such
are the challenges facing an antiphilosophy of Christianity. This
text will appeal to researchers and students working in continental
philosophy, philosophy of religion and those in religious studies
who want to investigate the links between Christianity and
antiphilosophy.
A discussion of the rapidly growing field, from a thinker at the
forefront of research at the interface of technology and the
humanities, this is a must-read for anyone interested in
contemporary developments in Continental philosophy and philosophy
of technology. Philosophy of technology regularly draws on key
thinkers in the Continental tradition, including Husserl,
Heidegger, and Foucault. Yet because of the problematic legacy of
the 'empirical turn', it often criticizes 'bad' continental
tendencies - lyricism, pessimism, and an outdated view of
technology as an autonomous, transcendental force. This
misconception is based on a faulty image of Continental thought,
and in addressing it Smith productively redefines our concept of
technology. By closely engaging key texts, and by examining
'exceptional technologies' such as imagined, failed, and impossible
technologies that fall outside philosophy of technology's current
focus, this book offers a practical guide to thinking about and
using continental philosophy and philosophy of technology. It
outlines and enacts three key characteristics of philosophy as
practiced in the continental tradition: close reading of the
history of philosophy; focus on critique; and openness to other
disciplinary fields. Smith deploys the concept of exceptional
technologies to provide a novel way of widening discussion in
philosophy of technology, navigating the relationship between
philosophy of technology and Continental philosophy; the history of
both these fields; the role of imagination in relation to
technologies; and the social function of technologies themselves.
This book is concerned with the evaluation of natural argumentative
discourse, and, in particular, with the language in which arguments
are expressed. It introduces a systematic procedure for the
analysis and assessment of arguments, which is designed to be a
practical tool, and may be considered a pseudo-algorithm for
argument evaluation. The first half of the book lays the
theoretical groundwork, with a thorough examination of both the
nature of language and the nature of argument. This leads to a
definition of argumentation as reasoning expressed within a
procedure, which itself yields the three frames of analysis used in
the evaluation procedure: Process, Reasoning, and Expression. The
second half begins with a detailed discussion of the concept of
fallacy, with particular attention on fallacies of language, their
origin and their effects. A new way of looking at fallacies emerges
from these chapters, and it is that conception, together with the
understanding of the nature of argumentation described in earlier
sections, which ultimately provides the support for the
Comprehensive Assessment Procedure for Natural Argumentation. The
first two levels of this innovative procedure are outlined, while
the third, that dealing with language, and involving the
development of an Informal Argument Semantics, is fully described.
The use of the system, and its power of analysis, are illustrated
through the evaluation of a variety of examples of argumentative
texts.
The Greek word eoikos can be translated in various ways. It can be
used to describe similarity, plausibility or even suitability. This
book explores the philosophical exploitation of its multiple
meanings by three philosophers, Xenophanes, Parmenides and Plato.
It offers new interpretations of the way that each employs the term
to describe the status of his philosophy, tracing the development
of this philosophical use of eoikos from the fallibilism of
Xenophanes through the deceptive cosmology of Parmenides to Plato's
Timaeus. The central premise of the book is that, in reflecting on
the eoikos status of their accounts, Xenophanes, Parmenides and
Plato are manipulating the contexts and connotations of the term as
it has been used by their predecessors. By focusing on this
continuity in the development of the philosophical use of eoikos,
the book serves to enhance our understanding of the epistemology
and methodology of Xenophanes, Parmenides and Plato's Timaeus.
 |
Walking
(Hardcover)
Henry David Thoreau
|
R668
Discovery Miles 6 680
|
Ships in 12 - 17 working days
|
|
What is the meaning of life? Does anything really matter? In the
past few decades these questions, perennially associated with
philosophy in the popular consciousness, have rightly retaken their
place as central topics in the academy. In this major contribution,
Nicholas Waghorn provides a sustained and rigorous elucidation of
what it would take for lives to have significance. Bracketing
issues about ways our lives could have more or less meaning, the
focus is rather on the idea of ultimate meaning, the issue of
whether a life can attain meaning that cannot be called into
question. Waghorn sheds light on this most fundamental of
existential problems through a detailed yet comprehensive
examination of the notion of nothing, embracing classic and
cutting-edge literature from both the analytic and Continental
traditions. Central figures such as Heidegger, Carnap,
Wittgenstein, Nozick and Nagel are drawn upon to anchor the
discussion in some of the most influential discussion of recent
philosophical history. In the process of relating our ideas
concerning nothing to the problem of life's meaning, Waghorn's book
touches upon a number of fundamental themes, including reflexivity
and its relation to our conceptual limits, whether religion has any
role to play in the question of life's meaning, and the nature and
constraints of philosophical methodology. A number of major
philosophical traditions are addressed, including phenomenology,
poststructuralism, and classical and paraconsistent logics. In
addition to providing the most thorough current discussion of
ultimate meaning, it will serve to introduce readers to
philosophical debates concerning the notion of nothing, and the
appendix engaging religion will be of value to both philosophers
and theologians.
This book examines the cogency and value of Nietzsche's idea of
eternal recurrence, as an antidote to the nihilism resulting from
the catastrophic event of 'the death of God'. Its significance to
Nietzsche's philosophy as a whole (when presented either as an
imaginative thought experiment, a cosmological hypothesis, or a
poetic metaphor) is analysed, alongside the manifold criticisms the
idea has attracted. In this original reading of eternal recurrence,
McNeil explores the strength of metaphorical meaning contained
within Heraclitean and Stoic cosmologies, revealing their influence
on Nietzsche's own cosmology, along with their holistic approach to
life which Nietzsche endorsed. Furthermore, an extensive critique
of Heidegger's interpretation of eternal recurrence is given.
McNeil argues that Heidegger ignores not only the life-affirming
Dionysian aspects of the concept, but also the Heraclitean sense of
play evident in the cosmology, and the importance of this for
developing a positive, celebratory attitude towards our lives and
creative projects.
It is widely believed in philosophy of science that nobody can
claim that any verdict of science is forced upon us by the effects
of a physical world upon our sense organs and instruments. The
Quine-Duhem problem supposedly allows us to resist any conclusion.
Views on language aside, Quine is supposed to have shown this
decisively. But it is just false. In many scientific examples,
there is simply no room to doubt that a particular hypothesis is
responsible for a refutation or established by the observations.
Fault Tracing shows how to play independently established
hypotheses against each other to determine whether an arbitrary
hypothesis needs to be altered in the light of (apparently)
refuting evidence. It analyses real examples from natural science,
as well as simpler cases. It argues that, when scientific theories
have a structure that prevents them from using this method, the
theory looks wrong, and is subject to serious criticism. This is a
new, and potentially far-reaching, theory of empirical
justification.
Hegel's critique of Early German Romanticism and its theory of
irony resonates to the core of his own philosophy in the same way
that Plato's polemics with the Sophists have repercussions that go
to the centre of his thought. The Anti-Romantic examines Hegel's
critique of Fr. Schlegel, Novalis and Schleiermacher. Hegel rarely
mentions these thinkers by name and the texts dealing with them
often exist on the periphery of his oeuvre. Nonetheless,
individually, they represent embodiments of specific forms of
irony: Schlegel, a form of critical individuality; Novalis, a form
of sentimental nihilism; Schleiermacher, a monstrous hybrid of the
other two. The strength of Hegel's polemical approach to these
authors shows how irony itself represents for him a persistent
threat to his own idea of systematic Science. This is so, we
discover, because Romantic irony is more than a rival ideology; it
is an actual form of discourse, one whose performative objectivity
interferes with the objectivity of Hegel's own logos. Thus, Hegel's
critique of irony allows us to reciprocally uncover a Hegelian
theory of scientific discourse. Far from seeing irony as a form of
consciousness overcome by Spirit, Hegel sees it as having become a
pressing feature of his own contemporary world, as witnessed in the
popularity of his Berlin rival, Schleiermacher. Finally, to the
extent that ironic discourse seems, for Hegel, to imply a certain
world beyond his own notion of modernity, we are left with the
hypothesis that Hegel's critique of irony may be viewed as a
critique of post-modernity.
French philosopher and Talmudic commentator Emmanuel Levinas
(1906-1995) has received considerable attention for his influence
on philosophical and religious thought. In this book, Victoria
Tahmasebi-Birgani provides the first examination of the
applicability of Emmanuel Levinas' work to social and political
movements. Investigating his ethics of responsibility and his
critique of the Western liberal imagination, Tahmasebi-Birgani
advances the moral, political, and philosophical debates on the
radical implications of Levinas' work.
Emmanuel Levinas and the Politics of Non-Violence is the first
book to closely consider the affinity between Levinas' ethical
vision and Mohandas Gandhi's radical yet non-violent political
struggle. Situating Levinas' insights within a transnational,
transcontinental, and global framework, Tahmasebi-Birgani
highlights Levinas' continued relevance in an age in which violence
is so often resorted to in the name of "justice" and "freedom."
On the basis of the Thomist and Pietist tradition, Christian August
Crusius (1715-1775) elaborated a philosophically challenging and
influential alternative to the philosophy of Christian Wolff. For
the first time, this edited collection offers a rigorous overview
of the work of the Leipzig-based philosopher and theologian.
It is widely agreed that there is such a thing as sensory
phenomenology and imagistic phenomenology. The central concern of
the cognitive phenomenology debate is whether there is a
distinctive "cognitive phenomenology"--that is, a kind of
phenomenology that has cognitive or conceptual character in some
sense that needs to be precisely determined. This volume presents
new work by leading philosophers in the field, and addresses the
question of whether conscious thought has cognitive phenomenology.
It also includes a number of essays which consider whether
cognitive phenomenology is part of conscious perception and
conscious emotion.
Three broad themes run through the volume. First, some authors
focus on the question of how the notion of cognitive phenomenology
ought to be understood. How should the notion of cognitive
phenomenology be defined? Are there different kinds of cognitive
phenomenology? A second theme concerns the existence of cognitive
phenomenology. Some contributors defend the existence of a
distinctive cognitive phenomenology, whereas others deny it. The
arguments for and against the existence of cognitive phenomenology
raise questions concerning the nature of first-person knowledge of
thought, the relationship between consciousness and intentionality,
and the scope of the explanatory gap. A third theme concerns the
implications of the cognitive phenomenology debate. What are the
implications of the debate for accounts of our introspective access
to conscious thought and for accounts of the very nature of
conscious thought? Cognitive Phenomenology brings the debate to the
forefront of philosophy, and provides a state-of-the-art account of
the issues at stake.
The Syriac treatise published in the present volume is in many
respects a unique text. Though it has been preserved anonymously,
there remains little doubt that it belongs to Porphyry of Tyre.
Accordingly, it enlarges our knowledge of the views of the most
famous disciple of Plotinus. The text is an important witness to
Platonist discussions on First Principles and on Plato's concept of
Prime Matter in the Timaeus. It contains extensive quotations from
Atticus, Severus, and Boethus. This text thus provides us with new
textual witnesses to these philosophers, whose legacy remains very
poorly attested and little known. Additionally, the treatise is a
rare example of a Platonist work preserved in the Syriac language.
The Syriac reception of Plato and Platonic teachings has left
rather sparse textual traces, and the question of what precisely
Syriac Christians knew about Plato and his philosophy remains a
debated issue. The treatise provides evidence for the close
acquaintance of Syriac scholars with Platonic cosmology and with
philosophical commentaries on Plato's Timaeus.
Although the Greeks were responsible for the first systematic
philosophy of which we have any record, they were not alone in the
Mediterranean world and were happy to draw inspiration from other
traditions; traditions that are now largely neglected by
philosophers and scholars. This book tells the story of 'Greek
Philosophy', paying due attention to its historical context and the
contributions made by Egyptians, Hebrews, Persians and even
barbarians from northern Europe. Stephen Clark provides a narrative
history of the philosophical traditions that took shape over
several centuries in the Mediterranean world and offers a
comprehensive survey of this crucial period in the history of
philosophy. The book includes a thorough historical and
philosophical overview of all the key thinkers, events and ideas
that characterized the period and explores in detail central themes
such as the contest of gods and giants, the contrast between the
reality and appearance, and the idea of the philosopher. Ideal for
undergraduate students, this concise and accessible book provides a
comprehensive guide to a fascinating period in the history of
philosophy.>
SUNDAY TIMES NUMBER ONE BESTSELLER 'The most important book of the
year' Daily Mail The brilliant and provocative new book from one of
the world's foremost political writers 'The anti-Western
revisionists have been out in force in recent years. It is high
time that we revise them in turn...' In The War on the West,
international bestselling author Douglas Murray asks: if the
history of humankind is one of slavery, conquest, prejudice,
genocide and exploitation, why are only Western nations taking the
blame for it? It's become perfectly acceptable to celebrate the
contributions of non-Western cultures, but discussing their flaws
and crimes is called hate speech. What's more it has become
acceptable to discuss the flaws and crimes of Western culture, but
celebrating their contributions is also called hate speech. Some of
this is a much-needed reckoning; however, some is part of a larger
international attack on reason, democracy, science, progress and
the citizens of the West by dishonest scholars, hatemongers,
hostile nations and human-rights abusers hoping to distract from
their ongoing villainy. In The War on the West, Douglas Murray
shows the ways in which many well-meaning people have been lured
into polarisation by lies, and shows how far the world's most
crucial political debates have been hijacked across Europe and
America. Propelled by an incisive deconstruction of inconsistent
arguments and hypocritical activism, The War on the West is an
essential and urgent polemic that cements Murray's status as one of
the world's foremost political writers.
|
You may like...
Republic
Plato
Paperback
R95
R78
Discovery Miles 780
|