|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy
It was not only in his histories that Voltaire thought, worried and
wrote about history. In fact, many of Voltaire's most provocative
and tantalising remarks on history lie outside the province of the
so-called OEuvres historiques, in the vast expanses of his complete
works, and historical events and historical figures elicit some of
his most imaginative writing. Voltaire's propensity to write about
history in works that are not histories sheds new light on his
historiographical thought and temper. The historian that emerges
from these pages is, by turns, a feverish, bed-ridden man haunted
by the St Bartholomew massacre (an overwhelming preoccupation of
Voltaire's, although it receives only cursory attention in the
prose histories) an inspired poet mythologising Henri IV's epic
adventures, a bawdy satirist amused by Joan of Arc, a raconteur
nourished by historical anecdotes, even a doting uncle winking at
his niece as he elaborates a philosophy of history. In all these
forms and at all these times, an interest in history is integral
and abiding. Far from being marginal or oblique, these works yield
important insights into a pervasive Voltairean sense of history
which finds in these different forms both the freedoms and the
traditions - and indeed often the readers - denied to the OEuvres
historiques. Moreover, innovative works like the Henriade and
Candide, which fall into this category, prove as influential to
historians as Voltaire's recognised histories. Voltaire's
prodigious energy and versatility in fields other than history have
probably harmed his reputation as a historian when, already in the
eighteenth century, historians were increasingly expected to be
specialists. This study shows that Voltaire's historiographical
thought ranges across areas and texts artificially sundered by
subsequent editorial compartmentalisations, and it reveals a
restlessly complex, inventive writer confronting history in
numerous different guises.
It is widely believed in philosophy of science that nobody can
claim that any verdict of science is forced upon us by the effects
of a physical world upon our sense organs and instruments. The
Quine-Duhem problem supposedly allows us to resist any conclusion.
Views on language aside, Quine is supposed to have shown this
decisively. But it is just false. In many scientific examples,
there is simply no room to doubt that a particular hypothesis is
responsible for a refutation or established by the observations.
Fault Tracing shows how to play independently established
hypotheses against each other to determine whether an arbitrary
hypothesis needs to be altered in the light of (apparently)
refuting evidence. It analyses real examples from natural science,
as well as simpler cases. It argues that, when scientific theories
have a structure that prevents them from using this method, the
theory looks wrong, and is subject to serious criticism. This is a
new, and potentially far-reaching, theory of empirical
justification.
Heidegger and the Emergence of the Question of Being offers a new,
updated and comprehensive introduction to Heidegger's development
and his early confrontation with philosophical tradition, theology,
neo-Kantianism, vitalism, hermeneutics, and phenomenology, up to
the publication of Being and Time in 1927. The main thread is the
genealogy of the question of the meaning of being. Alongside the
most recent scholarly research, this book takes into account the
documentary richness of Heidegger's first Freiburg (1919-1923) and
Marburg (1923-1928) lectures, conferences, treatises and letters
and addresses the thematic and methodological richness of this
period of Heidegger's intellectual life, and offers a coherent and
unified interpretation of his earlier work. This book conveys
Heidegger's thought in a well-organized, impartial manner, without
deviating too far from Heideggerian vocabulary. It will be
invaluable for upper level undergraduates, graduate students of
philosophy, studying phenomenology, continental and German
philosophy.
Exploring the political ideology of Republicanism under the Roman
emperors of the first century AD, Sam Wilkinson puts forward the
hypothesis that there was indeed opposition to the political
structure and ideology of the rulers on the grounds of
Republicanism. While some Romans wanted a return to the Republic,
others wanted the emperor to ensure his reign was as close to
Republican moral and political ideology as possible. Analysing the
discourse of the period, the book charts how the view of law,
morality and behaviour changed under the various Imperial regimes
of the first century AD. Uniquely, this book explores how emperors
could choose to set their regime in a more Republican or more
Imperial manner, thus demonstrating it was possible for both the
opposition and an emperor to be Republican. The book concludes by
providing evidence of Republicanism in the first century AD which
not only created opposition to the emperors, but also became part
of the political debate in this period.
On the basis of the Thomist and Pietist tradition, Christian August
Crusius (1715-1775) elaborated a philosophically challenging and
influential alternative to the philosophy of Christian Wolff. For
the first time, this edited collection offers a rigorous overview
of the work of the Leipzig-based philosopher and theologian.
Modern Conspiracy attempts to sketch a new conception of conspiracy
theory. Where many commentators have sought to characterize
conspiracy theory in terms of the collapse of objectivity and
Enlightenment reason, Fleming and Jane trace the important role of
conspiracy in the formation of the modern world: the scientific
revolution, social contract theory, political sovereignty,
religious paranoia and mass communication media. Rather than see in
conspiratorial thinking the imminent death of Enlightenment reason,
and a regression to a new Dark Age, Modern Conspiracy contends that
many characteristic features of conspiracies tap very deeply into
the history of the Enlightenment itself: among other things, its
vociferous critique of established authorities, and a conception of
political sovereignty fuelled by fear of counter-plots. Drawing out
the roots of modern conspiratorial thinking leads us to truths less
salacious and scandalous than the claims of conspiracy theorists
themselves yet ultimately far more salutary: about mass
communication; about individual and crowd psychology; and about our
conception of and relation to knowledge.Perhaps, ultimately, what
conspiracy theory affords us is a renewed opportunity to reflect on
our very relationship to the truth itself.
Aristotle described the scientific explanation of universal or
general facts as deducing them through scientific demonstrations,
that is, through syllogisms that met requirements of logical
validity and explanatoriness which he first formulated. In Chapters
19-23, he adds arguments for the further logical restrictions that
scientific demonstrations can neither be indefinitely long nor
infinitely extendible through the interposition of new middle
terms. Chapters 24-26 argue for the superiority of universal over
particular demonstration, of affirmative over negative
demonstration, and of direct negative demonstration over
demonstration to the impossible. Chapters 27-34 discuss different
aspects of sciences and scientific understanding, allowing us to
distinguish between sciences, and between scientific understanding
and other kinds of cognition, especially opinion. Philoponus'
comments on these chapters are interesting especially because of
his metaphysical analysis of universal predication and his
understanding of the notion of subordinate sciences. We learn from
his commentary that Philoponus believed in Platonic Forms as
inherent in, and posterior to, the Divine Intellect, but ascribed
to Aristotle an interpretation of Plato's Forms as independent
substances, prior to the Demiurgic Intellect. A very important
notion from Aristotle's Posterior Analytics is that of the
'subordination' of sciences, i.e. the idea that some sciences
depend on 'higher' ones for some of their principles. Philoponus
goes beyond Aristotle in suggesting a taxonomy of sciences, in
which the subordinate science concerns the same scientific genus as
the superordinate, but a different species.
The Greek word eoikos can be translated in various ways. It can be
used to describe similarity, plausibility or even suitability. This
book explores the philosophical exploitation of its multiple
meanings by three philosophers, Xenophanes, Parmenides and Plato.
It offers new interpretations of the way that each employs the term
to describe the status of his philosophy, tracing the development
of this philosophical use of eoikos from the fallibilism of
Xenophanes through the deceptive cosmology of Parmenides to Plato's
Timaeus. The central premise of the book is that, in reflecting on
the eoikos status of their accounts, Xenophanes, Parmenides and
Plato are manipulating the contexts and connotations of the term as
it has been used by their predecessors. By focusing on this
continuity in the development of the philosophical use of eoikos,
the book serves to enhance our understanding of the epistemology
and methodology of Xenophanes, Parmenides and Plato's Timaeus.
What is the meaning of life? Does anything really matter? In the
past few decades these questions, perennially associated with
philosophy in the popular consciousness, have rightly retaken their
place as central topics in the academy. In this major contribution,
Nicholas Waghorn provides a sustained and rigorous elucidation of
what it would take for lives to have significance. Bracketing
issues about ways our lives could have more or less meaning, the
focus is rather on the idea of ultimate meaning, the issue of
whether a life can attain meaning that cannot be called into
question. Waghorn sheds light on this most fundamental of
existential problems through a detailed yet comprehensive
examination of the notion of nothing, embracing classic and
cutting-edge literature from both the analytic and Continental
traditions. Central figures such as Heidegger, Carnap,
Wittgenstein, Nozick and Nagel are drawn upon to anchor the
discussion in some of the most influential discussion of recent
philosophical history. In the process of relating our ideas
concerning nothing to the problem of life's meaning, Waghorn's book
touches upon a number of fundamental themes, including reflexivity
and its relation to our conceptual limits, whether religion has any
role to play in the question of life's meaning, and the nature and
constraints of philosophical methodology. A number of major
philosophical traditions are addressed, including phenomenology,
poststructuralism, and classical and paraconsistent logics. In
addition to providing the most thorough current discussion of
ultimate meaning, it will serve to introduce readers to
philosophical debates concerning the notion of nothing, and the
appendix engaging religion will be of value to both philosophers
and theologians.
Hegel's critique of Early German Romanticism and its theory of
irony resonates to the core of his own philosophy in the same way
that Plato's polemics with the Sophists have repercussions that go
to the centre of his thought. The Anti-Romantic examines Hegel's
critique of Fr. Schlegel, Novalis and Schleiermacher. Hegel rarely
mentions these thinkers by name and the texts dealing with them
often exist on the periphery of his oeuvre. Nonetheless,
individually, they represent embodiments of specific forms of
irony: Schlegel, a form of critical individuality; Novalis, a form
of sentimental nihilism; Schleiermacher, a monstrous hybrid of the
other two. The strength of Hegel's polemical approach to these
authors shows how irony itself represents for him a persistent
threat to his own idea of systematic Science. This is so, we
discover, because Romantic irony is more than a rival ideology; it
is an actual form of discourse, one whose performative objectivity
interferes with the objectivity of Hegel's own logos. Thus, Hegel's
critique of irony allows us to reciprocally uncover a Hegelian
theory of scientific discourse. Far from seeing irony as a form of
consciousness overcome by Spirit, Hegel sees it as having become a
pressing feature of his own contemporary world, as witnessed in the
popularity of his Berlin rival, Schleiermacher. Finally, to the
extent that ironic discourse seems, for Hegel, to imply a certain
world beyond his own notion of modernity, we are left with the
hypothesis that Hegel's critique of irony may be viewed as a
critique of post-modernity.
The concept of resistance has always been central to the reception
of Hegel's philosophy. The prevalent image of Hegel's system, which
continues to influence the scholarship to this day, is that of an
absolutist, monist metaphysics which overcomes all resistance,
sublating or assimilating all differences into a single organic
'Whole'. For that reason, the reception of Hegel has always been
marked by the question of how to resist Hegel: how to think that
which remains outside of or other to the totalizing system of
dialectics. In recent years the work of scholars such as Catherine
Malabou, Slavoj Zizek, Rebecca Comay and Frank Ruda has brought
considerable nuance to this debate. A new reading of Hegel has
emerged which challenges the idea that there is no place for
difference, otherness or resistance in Hegel, both by refusing to
reduce Hegel's complex philosophy to a straightforward systematic
narrative and by highlighting particular moments within Hegel's
philosophy which seem to counteract the traditional understanding
of dialectics. This book brings together established and new voices
in this field in order to show that the notion of resistance is
central to this revaluation of Hegel.
French philosopher and Talmudic commentator Emmanuel Levinas
(1906-1995) has received considerable attention for his influence
on philosophical and religious thought. In this book, Victoria
Tahmasebi-Birgani provides the first examination of the
applicability of Emmanuel Levinas' work to social and political
movements. Investigating his ethics of responsibility and his
critique of the Western liberal imagination, Tahmasebi-Birgani
advances the moral, political, and philosophical debates on the
radical implications of Levinas' work.
Emmanuel Levinas and the Politics of Non-Violence is the first
book to closely consider the affinity between Levinas' ethical
vision and Mohandas Gandhi's radical yet non-violent political
struggle. Situating Levinas' insights within a transnational,
transcontinental, and global framework, Tahmasebi-Birgani
highlights Levinas' continued relevance in an age in which violence
is so often resorted to in the name of "justice" and "freedom."
A discussion of the rapidly growing field, from a thinker at the
forefront of research at the interface of technology and the
humanities, this is a must-read for anyone interested in
contemporary developments in Continental philosophy and philosophy
of technology. Philosophy of technology regularly draws on key
thinkers in the Continental tradition, including Husserl,
Heidegger, and Foucault. Yet because of the problematic legacy of
the 'empirical turn', it often criticizes 'bad' continental
tendencies - lyricism, pessimism, and an outdated view of
technology as an autonomous, transcendental force. This
misconception is based on a faulty image of Continental thought,
and in addressing it Smith productively redefines our concept of
technology. By closely engaging key texts, and by examining
'exceptional technologies' such as imagined, failed, and impossible
technologies that fall outside philosophy of technology's current
focus, this book offers a practical guide to thinking about and
using continental philosophy and philosophy of technology. It
outlines and enacts three key characteristics of philosophy as
practiced in the continental tradition: close reading of the
history of philosophy; focus on critique; and openness to other
disciplinary fields. Smith deploys the concept of exceptional
technologies to provide a novel way of widening discussion in
philosophy of technology, navigating the relationship between
philosophy of technology and Continental philosophy; the history of
both these fields; the role of imagination in relation to
technologies; and the social function of technologies themselves.
This book is mainly concerned with elaborating an account of the
unique theoretical essence and activities of philosophy. What
manner of civilization should modern humans forge? On what
developmental path should a nation embark? What lifestyle should
each individual choose? These are the most fundamental issues of
our time. Profoundly implicit in the choices outlined above is a
deeper question: What are the criteria of choice? An examination of
these criteria is a reflection on the premises constituting
thought, or a critique of the premises underlying thought. Using a
"critique of the premises underlying thought" as the basic idea and
hermeneutic principle in philosophy will open a wider theoretical
space for contemporary philosophy so as to avoid the predicament of
being "pseudo-scientific" or "pseudo-artistic." It will also
present contemporary philosophy with a realistic path of
development for the task of reflecting on the criteria of choice.
This book seeks to formulate concrete philosophical arguments for a
critique of the basic beliefs, logic, modes, concepts, and
philosophical ideas which constitute thought, with the aim of
demonstrating the vigorous self-critique and inexhaustible
theoretical space found in philosophical development. This book
provides a new principle of interpretation for understanding
philosophy and, in turn, uses this principle to develop a critique
of the premises underlying thought, thereby furthering the
contemporary development of philosophy. This book encompasses a
critique of the premises underlying thought, which mainly includes
the basic beliefs, logic, modes, concepts, and philosophical ideas
constituting thought. Such a critique should comprise five aspects:
First, the basic beliefs constituting thought propose a critique of
the identity of thought and being; second, the basic logic
constituting thought refers to a critique of the formal,
intensional, and practical logic of thought; third, the basic modes
constituting thought denote a critique of the basic modes by which
humans comprehend the world, including commonsense, religion, art,
and science; fourth, the basic concepts constituting thought entail
a critique centering on being, the world, history, truth, value,
and other basic concepts; and finally, the philosophical ideas
constituting thought indicate a critique of philosophy itself. A
critique aligned on these five aspects will provide a general
philosophical overview of the premise critique of thought.
The history of Continental philosophy is often conceived as being
represented by two major schools: German idealism and
phenomenology/existentialism. These two schools are frequently
juxtaposed so as to highlight their purported radical differences.
There is a commonly held view that an abrupt break occurred in the
nineteenth century, resulting in a disdainful rejection of idealism
in all its forms. This break is often located in the transition
from Hegel to Kierkegaard. The history of philosophy in the first
half of the nineteenth century has thus been read as a grand
confrontation between the overambitious rationalistic system of
Hegel and the devastating criticisms of it by Kierkegaard's
philosophy of existence. This work aims to undermine this popular
view of the radical break between idealism and existentialism by
means of a series of detailed studies in specific episodes of
European thought. As a whole, this book represents an important
attempt to demonstrate the long shadow cast by Kant and Hegel over
the subsequent history of European philosophy.
|
You may like...
Hot Water
Nadine Dirks
Paperback
R280
R259
Discovery Miles 2 590
|