|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy
Exploring the political ideology of Republicanism under the Roman
emperors of the first century AD, Sam Wilkinson puts forward the
hypothesis that there was indeed opposition to the political
structure and ideology of the rulers on the grounds of
Republicanism. While some Romans wanted a return to the Republic,
others wanted the emperor to ensure his reign was as close to
Republican moral and political ideology as possible. Analysing the
discourse of the period, the book charts how the view of law,
morality and behaviour changed under the various Imperial regimes
of the first century AD. Uniquely, this book explores how emperors
could choose to set their regime in a more Republican or more
Imperial manner, thus demonstrating it was possible for both the
opposition and an emperor to be Republican. The book concludes by
providing evidence of Republicanism in the first century AD which
not only created opposition to the emperors, but also became part
of the political debate in this period.
Modern Conspiracy attempts to sketch a new conception of conspiracy
theory. Where many commentators have sought to characterize
conspiracy theory in terms of the collapse of objectivity and
Enlightenment reason, Fleming and Jane trace the important role of
conspiracy in the formation of the modern world: the scientific
revolution, social contract theory, political sovereignty,
religious paranoia and mass communication media. Rather than see in
conspiratorial thinking the imminent death of Enlightenment reason,
and a regression to a new Dark Age, Modern Conspiracy contends that
many characteristic features of conspiracies tap very deeply into
the history of the Enlightenment itself: among other things, its
vociferous critique of established authorities, and a conception of
political sovereignty fuelled by fear of counter-plots. Drawing out
the roots of modern conspiratorial thinking leads us to truths less
salacious and scandalous than the claims of conspiracy theorists
themselves yet ultimately far more salutary: about mass
communication; about individual and crowd psychology; and about our
conception of and relation to knowledge.Perhaps, ultimately, what
conspiracy theory affords us is a renewed opportunity to reflect on
our very relationship to the truth itself.
It is widely believed in philosophy of science that nobody can
claim that any verdict of science is forced upon us by the effects
of a physical world upon our sense organs and instruments. The
Quine-Duhem problem supposedly allows us to resist any conclusion.
Views on language aside, Quine is supposed to have shown this
decisively. But it is just false. In many scientific examples,
there is simply no room to doubt that a particular hypothesis is
responsible for a refutation or established by the observations.
Fault Tracing shows how to play independently established
hypotheses against each other to determine whether an arbitrary
hypothesis needs to be altered in the light of (apparently)
refuting evidence. It analyses real examples from natural science,
as well as simpler cases. It argues that, when scientific theories
have a structure that prevents them from using this method, the
theory looks wrong, and is subject to serious criticism. This is a
new, and potentially far-reaching, theory of empirical
justification.
Heidegger and the Emergence of the Question of Being offers a new,
updated and comprehensive introduction to Heidegger's development
and his early confrontation with philosophical tradition, theology,
neo-Kantianism, vitalism, hermeneutics, and phenomenology, up to
the publication of Being and Time in 1927. The main thread is the
genealogy of the question of the meaning of being. Alongside the
most recent scholarly research, this book takes into account the
documentary richness of Heidegger's first Freiburg (1919-1923) and
Marburg (1923-1928) lectures, conferences, treatises and letters
and addresses the thematic and methodological richness of this
period of Heidegger's intellectual life, and offers a coherent and
unified interpretation of his earlier work. This book conveys
Heidegger's thought in a well-organized, impartial manner, without
deviating too far from Heideggerian vocabulary. It will be
invaluable for upper level undergraduates, graduate students of
philosophy, studying phenomenology, continental and German
philosophy.
This volume offers a much needed shift of focus in the study of
emotion in the history of philosophy. Discussion has tended to
focus on the moral relevance of emotions, and (except in ancient
philosophy) the role of emotions in cognitive life has received
little attention. Thirteen new essays investigate the continuities
between medieval and early modern thinking about the emotions, and
open up a contemporary debate on the relationship between emotions,
cognition, and reason, and the way emotions figure in our own
cognitive lives. A team of leading philosophers of the medieval,
renaissance, and early modern periods explore these ideas from the
point of view of four key themes: the situation of emotions within
the human mind; the intentionality of emotions and their role in
cognition; emotions and action; the role of emotion in
self-understanding and the social situation of individuals.
On the basis of the Thomist and Pietist tradition, Christian August
Crusius (1715-1775) elaborated a philosophically challenging and
influential alternative to the philosophy of Christian Wolff. For
the first time, this edited collection offers a rigorous overview
of the work of the Leipzig-based philosopher and theologian.
HarperCollins is proud to present its incredible range of
best-loved, essential classics. Plato's The Republic has influenced
Western philosophers for centuries, with its main focus on what
makes a well-balanced society and individual.
This book is mainly concerned with elaborating an account of the
unique theoretical essence and activities of philosophy. What
manner of civilization should modern humans forge? On what
developmental path should a nation embark? What lifestyle should
each individual choose? These are the most fundamental issues of
our time. Profoundly implicit in the choices outlined above is a
deeper question: What are the criteria of choice? An examination of
these criteria is a reflection on the premises constituting
thought, or a critique of the premises underlying thought. Using a
"critique of the premises underlying thought" as the basic idea and
hermeneutic principle in philosophy will open a wider theoretical
space for contemporary philosophy so as to avoid the predicament of
being "pseudo-scientific" or "pseudo-artistic." It will also
present contemporary philosophy with a realistic path of
development for the task of reflecting on the criteria of choice.
This book seeks to formulate concrete philosophical arguments for a
critique of the basic beliefs, logic, modes, concepts, and
philosophical ideas which constitute thought, with the aim of
demonstrating the vigorous self-critique and inexhaustible
theoretical space found in philosophical development. This book
provides a new principle of interpretation for understanding
philosophy and, in turn, uses this principle to develop a critique
of the premises underlying thought, thereby furthering the
contemporary development of philosophy. This book encompasses a
critique of the premises underlying thought, which mainly includes
the basic beliefs, logic, modes, concepts, and philosophical ideas
constituting thought. Such a critique should comprise five aspects:
First, the basic beliefs constituting thought propose a critique of
the identity of thought and being; second, the basic logic
constituting thought refers to a critique of the formal,
intensional, and practical logic of thought; third, the basic modes
constituting thought denote a critique of the basic modes by which
humans comprehend the world, including commonsense, religion, art,
and science; fourth, the basic concepts constituting thought entail
a critique centering on being, the world, history, truth, value,
and other basic concepts; and finally, the philosophical ideas
constituting thought indicate a critique of philosophy itself. A
critique aligned on these five aspects will provide a general
philosophical overview of the premise critique of thought.
The Greek word eoikos can be translated in various ways. It can be
used to describe similarity, plausibility or even suitability. This
book explores the philosophical exploitation of its multiple
meanings by three philosophers, Xenophanes, Parmenides and Plato.
It offers new interpretations of the way that each employs the term
to describe the status of his philosophy, tracing the development
of this philosophical use of eoikos from the fallibilism of
Xenophanes through the deceptive cosmology of Parmenides to Plato's
Timaeus. The central premise of the book is that, in reflecting on
the eoikos status of their accounts, Xenophanes, Parmenides and
Plato are manipulating the contexts and connotations of the term as
it has been used by their predecessors. By focusing on this
continuity in the development of the philosophical use of eoikos,
the book serves to enhance our understanding of the epistemology
and methodology of Xenophanes, Parmenides and Plato's Timaeus.
What makes individuals what they are? How should they judge their
social and political interaction with the world? What makes them
authentic or inauthentic? This original and provocative study
explores the concept of "authenticity" and its relevance for
radical politics. Weaving together close readings of three 20th
century thinkers: Martin Heidegger, Karl Jaspers and Jean-Paul
Sartre with the concept of authenticity, Stephen Eric Bronner
illuminates the phenomenological foundations for self-awareness
that underpin our sense of identity and solidarity. He claims that
different expressions of the existential tradition compete with one
another in determining how authenticity might be experienced, but
all of them ultimately rest on self-referential judgments. The
author's own new framework for a political ethic at once serves as
a corrective and an alternative. Wonderfully rich, insightful, and
nuanced, Stephen Eric Bronner has produced another bookshelf staple
that speaks to crucial issues in politics, philosophy, psychology,
and sociology. Existentialism, Authenticity, Solidarity will appeal
to scholars, students and readers from the general public alike.
The concept of resistance has always been central to the reception
of Hegel's philosophy. The prevalent image of Hegel's system, which
continues to influence the scholarship to this day, is that of an
absolutist, monist metaphysics which overcomes all resistance,
sublating or assimilating all differences into a single organic
'Whole'. For that reason, the reception of Hegel has always been
marked by the question of how to resist Hegel: how to think that
which remains outside of or other to the totalizing system of
dialectics. In recent years the work of scholars such as Catherine
Malabou, Slavoj Zizek, Rebecca Comay and Frank Ruda has brought
considerable nuance to this debate. A new reading of Hegel has
emerged which challenges the idea that there is no place for
difference, otherness or resistance in Hegel, both by refusing to
reduce Hegel's complex philosophy to a straightforward systematic
narrative and by highlighting particular moments within Hegel's
philosophy which seem to counteract the traditional understanding
of dialectics. This book brings together established and new voices
in this field in order to show that the notion of resistance is
central to this revaluation of Hegel.
What is the meaning of life? Does anything really matter? In the
past few decades these questions, perennially associated with
philosophy in the popular consciousness, have rightly retaken their
place as central topics in the academy. In this major contribution,
Nicholas Waghorn provides a sustained and rigorous elucidation of
what it would take for lives to have significance. Bracketing
issues about ways our lives could have more or less meaning, the
focus is rather on the idea of ultimate meaning, the issue of
whether a life can attain meaning that cannot be called into
question. Waghorn sheds light on this most fundamental of
existential problems through a detailed yet comprehensive
examination of the notion of nothing, embracing classic and
cutting-edge literature from both the analytic and Continental
traditions. Central figures such as Heidegger, Carnap,
Wittgenstein, Nozick and Nagel are drawn upon to anchor the
discussion in some of the most influential discussion of recent
philosophical history. In the process of relating our ideas
concerning nothing to the problem of life's meaning, Waghorn's book
touches upon a number of fundamental themes, including reflexivity
and its relation to our conceptual limits, whether religion has any
role to play in the question of life's meaning, and the nature and
constraints of philosophical methodology. A number of major
philosophical traditions are addressed, including phenomenology,
poststructuralism, and classical and paraconsistent logics. In
addition to providing the most thorough current discussion of
ultimate meaning, it will serve to introduce readers to
philosophical debates concerning the notion of nothing, and the
appendix engaging religion will be of value to both philosophers
and theologians.
Hegel's critique of Early German Romanticism and its theory of
irony resonates to the core of his own philosophy in the same way
that Plato's polemics with the Sophists have repercussions that go
to the centre of his thought. The Anti-Romantic examines Hegel's
critique of Fr. Schlegel, Novalis and Schleiermacher. Hegel rarely
mentions these thinkers by name and the texts dealing with them
often exist on the periphery of his oeuvre. Nonetheless,
individually, they represent embodiments of specific forms of
irony: Schlegel, a form of critical individuality; Novalis, a form
of sentimental nihilism; Schleiermacher, a monstrous hybrid of the
other two. The strength of Hegel's polemical approach to these
authors shows how irony itself represents for him a persistent
threat to his own idea of systematic Science. This is so, we
discover, because Romantic irony is more than a rival ideology; it
is an actual form of discourse, one whose performative objectivity
interferes with the objectivity of Hegel's own logos. Thus, Hegel's
critique of irony allows us to reciprocally uncover a Hegelian
theory of scientific discourse. Far from seeing irony as a form of
consciousness overcome by Spirit, Hegel sees it as having become a
pressing feature of his own contemporary world, as witnessed in the
popularity of his Berlin rival, Schleiermacher. Finally, to the
extent that ironic discourse seems, for Hegel, to imply a certain
world beyond his own notion of modernity, we are left with the
hypothesis that Hegel's critique of irony may be viewed as a
critique of post-modernity.
French philosopher and Talmudic commentator Emmanuel Levinas
(1906-1995) has received considerable attention for his influence
on philosophical and religious thought. In this book, Victoria
Tahmasebi-Birgani provides the first examination of the
applicability of Emmanuel Levinas' work to social and political
movements. Investigating his ethics of responsibility and his
critique of the Western liberal imagination, Tahmasebi-Birgani
advances the moral, political, and philosophical debates on the
radical implications of Levinas' work.
Emmanuel Levinas and the Politics of Non-Violence is the first
book to closely consider the affinity between Levinas' ethical
vision and Mohandas Gandhi's radical yet non-violent political
struggle. Situating Levinas' insights within a transnational,
transcontinental, and global framework, Tahmasebi-Birgani
highlights Levinas' continued relevance in an age in which violence
is so often resorted to in the name of "justice" and "freedom."
It is widely agreed that there is such a thing as sensory
phenomenology and imagistic phenomenology. The central concern of
the cognitive phenomenology debate is whether there is a
distinctive "cognitive phenomenology"--that is, a kind of
phenomenology that has cognitive or conceptual character in some
sense that needs to be precisely determined. This volume presents
new work by leading philosophers in the field, and addresses the
question of whether conscious thought has cognitive phenomenology.
It also includes a number of essays which consider whether
cognitive phenomenology is part of conscious perception and
conscious emotion.
Three broad themes run through the volume. First, some authors
focus on the question of how the notion of cognitive phenomenology
ought to be understood. How should the notion of cognitive
phenomenology be defined? Are there different kinds of cognitive
phenomenology? A second theme concerns the existence of cognitive
phenomenology. Some contributors defend the existence of a
distinctive cognitive phenomenology, whereas others deny it. The
arguments for and against the existence of cognitive phenomenology
raise questions concerning the nature of first-person knowledge of
thought, the relationship between consciousness and intentionality,
and the scope of the explanatory gap. A third theme concerns the
implications of the cognitive phenomenology debate. What are the
implications of the debate for accounts of our introspective access
to conscious thought and for accounts of the very nature of
conscious thought? Cognitive Phenomenology brings the debate to the
forefront of philosophy, and provides a state-of-the-art account of
the issues at stake.
A discussion of the rapidly growing field, from a thinker at the
forefront of research at the interface of technology and the
humanities, this is a must-read for anyone interested in
contemporary developments in Continental philosophy and philosophy
of technology. Philosophy of technology regularly draws on key
thinkers in the Continental tradition, including Husserl,
Heidegger, and Foucault. Yet because of the problematic legacy of
the 'empirical turn', it often criticizes 'bad' continental
tendencies - lyricism, pessimism, and an outdated view of
technology as an autonomous, transcendental force. This
misconception is based on a faulty image of Continental thought,
and in addressing it Smith productively redefines our concept of
technology. By closely engaging key texts, and by examining
'exceptional technologies' such as imagined, failed, and impossible
technologies that fall outside philosophy of technology's current
focus, this book offers a practical guide to thinking about and
using continental philosophy and philosophy of technology. It
outlines and enacts three key characteristics of philosophy as
practiced in the continental tradition: close reading of the
history of philosophy; focus on critique; and openness to other
disciplinary fields. Smith deploys the concept of exceptional
technologies to provide a novel way of widening discussion in
philosophy of technology, navigating the relationship between
philosophy of technology and Continental philosophy; the history of
both these fields; the role of imagination in relation to
technologies; and the social function of technologies themselves.
This book is exclusively written on the foundation of sacred books
called Bible and on the experience of many good and great people,
for man who was created for hard work, accordingly to its given
gift calls talent. (1Co. 12:4) Which is precisely given accordingly
to everybody's abilities. (1Co. 12:7). To do good work and to
become son of living God (Jn. 15:15) and eventually on the end to
become god, (Ps. 82:6) when come time to give its record and hear;
well done my faithful son, enter into my rest. In this book it is
not my intention to teach anyone but only to incite everyone to
think about, to speak about and to recommend in order improving
life for entire humanity independent, of race, color, ethnicity,
languages or religion for everyone to become in agreement according
to its given gift, which is powerful Spirit of love, what we call
talent. It is not my idea that proves that, but myriad of humans as
modern prophets that by their work witnessed for real life directed
by the powerful Spirit of love call talent is only one way only one
direction toward goodness for entire humanity, which pleases only
One whom we call Great Creator. We may call it as universal secular
religion or secular ideology as you wish which is universal and
founded on free gift, given talent and responsibility while divine
religion is religion of individuals gathered in the congregation
founded on faith and obedience, while both are blessed with the
power of love. It is true and is easy to understand that life that
is directed by the given talent as a life purpose for the love
toward One who sent you to do it and for devoted love for entire
humanity as a fulfi llment of fi rst law to love your Great Creator
and not only your neighbor but entire humanity to be like sun that
shine from above for all and rain that comes for above for all as a
HEAVENLY WISDOM An end I would like to hear from you about your
opinion and suggestion in order to further improve that given
program suggested from many and for goodness for entire humanity.
Dr. Dragan P. Bogunovic MD FAAFP. Bogdani
|
|