|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Western philosophy, c 500 to c 1600
This volume brings together contributions from distinguished
scholars in the history of philosophy, focusing on points of
interaction between discrete historical contexts, religions, and
cultures found within the premodern period. The contributions
connect thinkers from antiquity through the Middle Ages and include
philosophers from the three major monotheistic faiths-Judaism,
Islam, and Christianity. By emphasizing premodern philosophy's
shared textual roots in antiquity, particularly the writings of
Plato and Aristotle, the volume highlights points of
cross-pollination between different schools, cultures, and moments
in premodern thought. Approaching the complex history of the
premodern world in an accessible way, the editors organize the
volume so as to underscore the difficulties the premodern period
poses for scholars, while accentuating the fascinating interplay
between the Greek, Hebrew, Arabic, and Latin philosophical
traditions. The contributors cover many topics ranging from the
aims of Aristotle's cosmos, the adoption of Aristotle's Organon by
al-Farabi, and the origins of the Plotiniana Arabica to the role of
Ibn Gabirol's Fons vitae in the Latin West, the ways in which
Islamic philosophy shaped thirteenth-century Latin conceptions of
light, Roger Bacon's adaptation of Avicenna for use in his moral
philosophy, and beyond. The volume's focus on "source-based
contextualism" demonstrates an appreciation for the rich diversity
of thought found in the premodern period, while revealing
methodological challenges raised by the historical study of
premodern philosophy. Contextualizing Premodern Philosophy:
Explorations of the Greek, Hebrew, Arabic, and Latin Traditions is
a stimulating resource for scholars and advanced students working
in the history of premodern philosophy.
The appeal of the sublime in the midns of British critics and poets
during the eighteenth century holds a unique position in the
history of aesthetics. At no other time has aesthetics displayed a
similar interest in the experience of the sublime. This book
explores the impulses behind the fascination for that experience.
The Greek treatise Peri Hupsous by Longinus constitutes the
earliest source for the experience of the sublime, and as such it
shaped much of British eighteenth-century criticism. But the
attraction of the sublime received stimulus from other sources as
well. In the effort to expand the context of the sublime, the
author considers the incentives provided not only by Longinus, but
also by the criticism of intellectual literature during the second
half of the seventeenth century; a body of criticism that was not
primarily concerned with the sublime, but which nevertheless served
as an important link to its subsequent appeal.
This book offers an original contribution to debates about the
problem of evil and the existence of God. It develops a Thomistic,
Christian theodicy, the aim of which is to help us better
understand not only why God allows evil, but also how God works to
redeem it. In the author's view, the existence of evil does not
generate any intellectual problem that theists must address or
solve to vindicate God or the rationality of theism. This is
because acknowledging the existence of evil rationally leads us to
acknowledge the existence of God. However, understanding how these
two facts are compatible still requires addressing weighty,
wide-ranging questions concerning God and evil. The author draws on
diverse elements of Aquinas's philosophy and theology to build an
argument that evil only exists within God's world because God has
created and continues to sustain so much good. Moreover, God can
and does bring good out of all evil, both cosmically and within the
context of our own, individual lives. In making this argument, the
author engages with contemporary work on the problem of evil from
analytic philosophy of religion and theology. Additionally, he
addresses a broad range of topics and doctrines within Thomistic
and Christian thought, including God, creation, providence,
original sin, redemption, heaven and hell, and the theological
virtues. God, Evil, and Redeeming Good is an essential resource for
scholars and students interested in philosophy of religion,
philosophical theology, and the thought of Thomas Aquinas.
Metaphysics and Hermeneutics in the Medieval Platonic Tradition
consists of twelve essays originally published between 2006 and
2015, dealing with main trends and specific figures within the
medieval Platonic tradition. Three essays provide general surveys
of the transmission of late ancient thought to the Middle Ages with
emphasis on the ancient authors, the themes, and their medieval
readers, respectively. The remaining essays deal especially with
certain major figures in the Platonic tradition, including
pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, Iohannes Scottus Eriugena, and
Nicholas of Cusa. The principal conceptual aim of the collection is
to establish the primacy of hermeneutics within the philosophical
program developed by these authors: in other words, to argue that
their philosophical activity, substantially albeit not exclusively,
consists of the reading and evaluation of authoritative texts. The
essays also argue that the role of hermeneutics varies in the
course of the tradition between being a means towards the
development of metaphysical theory and being an integral component
of metaphysics itself. In addition, such changes in the status and
application of hermeneutics to metaphysics are shown to be
accompanied by a shift from emphasizing the connection between
logic and philosophy to emphasizing that between rhetoric and
philosophy. The collection of essays fills in a lacuna in the
history of philosophy in general between the fifth and the
fifteenth centuries. It also initiates a dialogue between the
metaphysical hermeneutics of medieval Platonism and certain modern
theories of hermeneutics, structuralism, and deconstruction. The
book will be of special interest to students of the classical
tradition in western thought, and more generally to students of
medieval philosophy, theology, history, and literature. (CS1094).
Historical Imagination defends a phenomenological and hermeneutical
account of historical knowledge. The book's central questions are
what is historical imagination, what is the relation between the
imaginative and the empirical, in what sense is historical
knowledge always already imaginative, how does such knowledge serve
us, and what is the relation of historical understanding and
self-understanding? Paul Fairfield revisits some familiar
hermeneutical themes and endeavors to develop these further while
examining two important periods in which historical reassessments
or re-imaginings of the past occurred on a large scale. The
conception of historical imagination that emerges seeks to advance
beyond the debate between empiricists and postmodern
constructivists while focusing on narrative as well as a more
encompassing interpretation of who an historical people were, how
things stood with them, and how this comes to be known. Fairfield
supplements the philosophical argument with an historical
examination of how and why during late antiquity, early Christian
thinkers began to reimagine their Greek and Roman past, followed by
how and why renaissance and later enlightenment figures reimagined
their ancient and medieval past.
When does Renaissance philosophy end, and Early Modern philosophy
begin? Do Renaissance philosophers have something in common, which
distinguishes them from Early Modern philosophers? And ultimately,
what defines the modernity of the Early Modern period, and what
role did the Renaissance play in shaping it? The answers to these
questions are not just chronological. This book challenges
traditional constructions of these periods, which partly reflect
the prejudice that the Renaissance was a literary and artistic
phenomenon, rather than a philosophical phase. The essays in this
book investigate how the legacy of Renaissance philosophers
persisted in the following centuries through the direct encounters
of subsequent generations with Renaissance philosophical texts.
This volume treats Early Modern philosophers as joining their
predecessors as 'conversation partners': the 'conversations' in
this book feature, among others, Girolamo Cardano and Henry More,
Thomas Hobbes and Lorenzo Valla, Bernardino Telesio and Francis
Bacon, Rene Descartes and Tommaso Campanella, Giulio Cesare Vanini
and the anonymous Theophrastus redivivus.
This volume offers a new reading of Maimonides' Guide of the
Perplexed. In particular, it explores how Maimonides' commitment to
integrity led him to a critique of the Kal?m, to a complex concept
of immortality, and to insight into the human yearning for
metaphysical knowledge. Maimonides' search for objective truth is
also analysed in its connection with the scientific writings of his
time, which neither the Kal?m nor the Jewish philosophical
tradition that preceded him had endorsed. Through a careful
analysis of these issues, this book seeks to contribute to the
understanding of the modes of thought adopted in The Guide of the
Perplexed, including the 'philosophical theologian' model of
Maimonides' own design, and to the knowledge of its sources.
In Adulthood, Morality, and the Fully Human, John J. Shea describes
an adult, moral, and fully human self in terms of integrity and
mutuality. Those who are fully human are caring and just. Violence
is the absence of care and justice. Peace-the pinnacle of human
development-is their embodiment. Integrity and mutuality together
beget care and justice and care and justice together beget peace.
Shea shows the practical importance of the fully human self for
education, psychotherapy, and spirituality. This book is especially
recommended for scholars and those in helping professions.
Today, managers, politicians, educators, and healthcare providers
are highly skilled technicians who navigate modern systems.
However, followers seek more than know-how; they desire moral
leadership. Even leaders equipped with skills must make difficult
ethical choices. This book connects philosophy to leadership by
examining three representative texts from the history of
philosophy: Plato's Republic, Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, and
Niccolo Machiavelli's The Prince. The leadership ideas contained in
each one of these philosopher's works were not only pioneering for
their age but continue to be relevant today because they provide
insight into the enduring questions of leadership. The book
demonstrates the timeliness of the classical works by applying
these philosophical approaches to historical and contemporary
cases. This book is ideal for readers who are acquainted with
philosophy and those who are uninitiated. The connections made
between philosophy, leadership literature, and real-life leaders
enable readers to appreciate how deeper reflection into the themes
of leadership might merit scholarly attention and bear witness to
the close union between the philosophy of leadership and the real
world.
How can the Body and Blood of Christ, without ever leaving heaven,
come to be really present on eucharistic altars where the bread and
wine still seem to be? Thirteenth and fourteenth century Christian
Aristotelians thought the answer had to be "transubstantiation."
Acclaimed philosopher, Marilyn McCord Adams, investigates these
later medieval theories of the Eucharist, concentrating on the
writings of Thomas Aquinas, Giles of Rome, Duns Scotus, and William
Ockham, with some reference to Peter Lombard, Hugh of St. Victor,
and Bonaventure. She examines how their efforts to formulate and
integrate this theological datum provoked them to make significant
revisions in Aristotelian philosophical theories regarding the
metaphysical structure and location of bodies, differences between
substance and accidents, causality and causal powers, and
fundamental types of change. Setting these developments in the
theological context that gave rise to the question draws attention
to their understandings of the sacraments and their purpose, as
well as to their understandings of the nature and destiny of human
beings.
Adams concludes that their philosophical modifications were mostly
not ad hoc, but systematic revisions that made room for
transubstantiation while allowing Aristotle still to describe what
normally and naturally happens. By contrast, their picture of the
world as it will be (after the last judgment) seems less well
integrated with their sacramental theology and their understandings
of human nature.
A thoroughgoing examination of Maximus Confessor’s singular
theological vision through the prism of Christ’s cosmic and
historical Incarnation. Jordan Daniel Wood changes the trajectory
of patristic scholarship with this comprehensive historical and
systematic study of one of the most creative and profound thinkers
of the patristic era: Maximus Confessor (560–662 CE). Wood's
panoramic vantage on Maximus’s thought emulates the theological
depth of Hans Urs von Balthasar’s Cosmic Liturgy while also
serving as a corrective to that classic text. Maximus's theological
vision may be summed up in his enigmatic assertion that “the Word
of God, very God, wills always and in all things to actualize the
mystery of his Incarnation.” The Whole Mystery of Christ sets out
to explicate this claim. Attentive to the various contexts in which
Maximus thought and wrote—including the wisdom of earlier church
fathers, conciliar developments in Christological and Trinitarian
doctrine, monastic and ascetic ways of life, and prominent
contemporary philosophical traditions—the book explores the
relations between God’s act of creation and the Word’s
historical Incarnation, between the analogy of being and
Christology, and between history and the Fall, in addition to
treating such topics as grace, deification, theological
predication, and the ontology of nature versus personhood. Perhaps
uniquely among Christian thinkers, Wood argues, Maximus envisions
creatio ex nihilo as creatio ex Deo in the event of the Word’s
kenosis: the mystery of Christ is the revealed identity of the
Word’s historical and cosmic Incarnation. This book will be of
interest to scholars and students of patristics, historical
theology, systematic theology, and Byzantine studies.
According to Avicenna, whatever exists, while it exists, exists of
necessity. Not all beings, however, exist with the same kind of
necessity. Instead, they exist either necessarily per se or
necessarily per aliud. Avicenna on the Necessity of the Actual: His
Interpretation of Four Aristotelian Arguments explains how Avicenna
uses these modal claims to show that God is the efficient as well
as the final cause of an eternally existing cosmos. In particular,
Celia Kathryn Hatherly shows how Avicenna uses four Aristotelian
arguments to prove this very un-Aristotelian conclusion. These
arguments include Aristotle's argument for the finitude of
efficient causes in Metaphysics 2; his proof for the prime mover in
the Physics and Metaphysics 12; his argument against the Megarians
in Metaphysics 9; and his argument for the mutual entailment
between the necessary and the eternal in De Caelo 1.12. Moreover,
Hatherly contends, when Avicenna's versions of these arguments are
correctly interpreted using his distinctive understanding of
necessity and possibility, the objections raised against them by
his contemporaries and modern scholars fail.
Like any other group of philosophers, scholastic thinkers from the
Middle Ages disagreed about even the most fundamental of concepts.
With their characteristic style of rigorous semantic and logical
analysis, they produced a wide variety of diverse theories about a
huge number of topics. The Routledge Companion to Medieval
Philosophy offers readers an outstanding survey of many of these
diverse theories, on a wide array of subjects. Its 35 chapters, all
written exclusively for this Companion by leading international
scholars, are organized into seven parts: I Language and Logic II
Metaphysics III Cosmology and Physics IV Psychology V Cognition VI
Ethics and Moral Philosophy VII Political Philosophy In addition to
shedding new light on the most well-known philosophical debates and
problems of the medieval era, the Companion brings to the fore
topics that may not traditionally be associated with scholastic
philosophy, but were in fact a veritable part of the tradition.
These include chapters covering scholastic theories about
propositions, atomism, consciousness, and democracy and
representation. The Routledge Companion to Medieval Philosophy is a
helpful, comprehensive introduction to the field for undergraduate
students and other newcomers as well as a unique and valuable
resource for researchers in all areas of philosophy.
This book argues that the moral quality of an act comes from the
agent's inner states. By arguing for the indispensable relevance of
intention in the moral evaluation of acts, the book moves against a
mainstream, 'objective' approach in normative ethics.
This book is not merely a study of Shakespeare's debt to Montaigne.
It traces the evolution of self-consciousness in literary,
philosophical and religious writings from antiquity to the
Renaissance and demonstrates that its early modern forms first
appeared in the Essays and in Shakespearean drama. It shows,
however, that, contrary to some postmodern assumptions, the early
calling in question of the self did not lead to a negation of
identity. Montaigne acknowledged the fairly stable nature of his
personality and Shakespeare, as Dryden noted, maintained 'the
constant conformity of each character to itself from its very first
setting out in the Play quite to the End'. A similar evolution is
traced in the progress from an objective to a subjective
apprehension of time from Greek philosophy to early modern authors.
A final chapter shows that the influence of scepticism on Montaigne
and Shakespeare was counterbalanced by their reliance on permanent
humanistic values. -- .
In this final edition of his classic study of St. Thomas Aquinas,
Etienne Gilson presents the sweeping range and organic unity of
Thomistic philosophical thought. The philosophical thinking of
Aquinas is the result of reason being challenged to relate to many
theological conceptions of the Christian tradition. Gilson
carefully reviews how Aquinas grapples with the relation itself of
faith and reason and continuing through the existence and nature of
God and His creation, the world and its creatures, especially human
beings with their power of intellect, will, and moral life. He
concludes this study by discussing the life of people in society,
along with their purpose and final destiny. Gilson demonstrates
that Aquinas drew from a wide spectrum of sources in the
development of his thought-from the speculations of the ancient
Greeks such as Aristotle, to the Arabic and Jewish philosophers of
his time, as well as from Christian writers and scripture. The
Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas offers students of
philosophy and medieval studies an insightful introduction to the
thought of Aquinas and the Scholastic philosophy of the Middles
Ages, insights that are still revelant for today.
This book is the result of a collective attempt to give a general
survey of the development of atomism and its critics in the late
Middle Ages. All the contributors focussed on the thirteenth and
fourteenth centuries atomists and anti-atomists, with a thorough
examination of some important figures, as Nicholas of Autrecourt or
John Wyclif, and lesser known as Gerard of Odo or William Crathorn
for example. From those essays on particular authors a new way of
understanding the discussions of atomism in late medieval
philosophy and theology emerges. This volume demonstrates the
existence of strong and complicated connections between natural
philosophy, mathematics and theology in the medieval discussions of
the atomistic hypothesis. All chapters present a new research that
will be of interest to historians of medieval philosophy, science
and theology. Contributors include: Joel Biard, Sander W. de Boer,
Jean Celeyrette, Christophe Grellard, Elzbieta Jung, Emily Michael,
John E. Murdoch, Robert Podkonski, Aurelien Robert, and Rega Wood.
Medieval and Early Modern Science, 9
William of Moerbeke was a prolific medieval translator of Aristotle
and other ancient philosophical and scientific authors from Greek
into Latin, and he played a decisive role in the acceptance of
Aristotelian philosophy in the Latin world. He is often criticized
for an allegedly deficient translation method. However, this book
argues that his approach was a deliberate attempt to allow readers
to reach the correct understanding of the source texts in
accordance with the medieval view of the role of the translator.
William's project to make all genuine works of Aristotle - and also
of other important authors from Antiquity - available in Latin is
framed against the background of intellectual life in the 13th
century, the deliberate policy of his Dominican order to reconcile
Christian doctrine with worldly knowledge, and new trends in book
production that influenced the spread of the new translations.
William of Moerbeke's seemingly modest acts of translation started
an intellectual revolution, the impact of which extended from the
Middle Ages into the early modern era. The Friar and the
Philosopher will appeal to researchers and students alike
interested in Medieval perceptions of Aristotle, as well as other
works from Antiquity.
Byzantinists entered the study of emotion with Henry Maguire's
ground-breaking article on sorrow, published in 1977. Since then,
classicists and western medievalists have developed new ways of
understanding how emotional communities work and where the
ancients' concepts of emotion differ from our own, and Byzantinists
have begun to consider emotions other than sorrow. It is time to
look at what is distinctive about Byzantine emotion. This volume is
the first to look at the constellation of Byzantine emotions.
Originating at an international colloquium at Dumbarton Oaks, these
papers address issues such as power, gender, rhetoric, or
asceticism in Byzantine society through the lens of a single
emotion or cluster of emotions. Contributors focus not only on the
construction of emotions with respect to perception and cognition
but also explore how emotions were communicated and exchanged
across broad (multi)linguistic, political and social boundaries.
Priorities are twofold: to arrive at an understanding of what the
Byzantines thought of as emotions and to comprehend how theory
shaped their appraisal of reality. Managing Emotion in Byzantium
will appeal to researchers and students alike interested in
Byzantine perceptions of emotion, Byzantine Culture, and medieval
perceptions of emotion.
The authors of the standard approach to Bonaventure's aesthetics
established the broad themes that continue to inform the current
interpretation of his philosophy, theology, and mysticism of
beauty: his definition of beauty and its status as a transcendental
of being, his description of the aesthetic experience, and the role
of that experience in the soul's ascent into God. Nevertheless,
they also introduced a series of pointed questions that remain
without adequate resolution in the current literature. Thomas J.
McKenna's book, Bonaventure's Aesthetics: The Delight of the Soul
in Its Ascent into God, provides a comprehensive analysis of
Bonaventure's aesthetics, the first to appear since Balthasar's
Herrlichkeit, and, in doing so, argues for a resolution to these
questions in the context of his principal aesthetic text, the
Itinerarium mentis in Deum.
Even well after his lifetime, Ibn Sina was renowned, not just in
medicine or philosophy, but in other areas, especially in the
Islamic world. In brief, he was an authority in the Islamic East,
or an "auctoritas". However, in the west, his work was massively
influential in not only the medical education curricula, but also
in the important, innovative doctrines in philosophy. The most
fundamental sections of his major encyclopedia, al-Shifa being
translated into Latin as early as the 12th and 13th centuries and
spreading throughout universities dispersed this impact rapidly.
Known as "the prince of physicians", Ibn Sina is the writer of the
Canon of Medicine (al-Qa-nu- n fi 'al-Tibb), which became a medical
standard in the Christian west as well as the Islamic world.
This book offers a comprehensive history of the principle of double
effect and its applications in ethics. Written from a
non-theological perspective, it makes the case for the centrality
of the double effect reasoning in philosophical ethics. The book is
divided into two parts. The first part thoroughly examines the
history of double effect reasoning. The author's history spans from
Thomas Aquinas's opera omnia to the modern and influential
understanding of the principle known as proportionalism. The second
part of the book elucidates the principle and addresses various
objections that have been raised against it, including those that
arise from an in-depth discussion of the trolley problem. Finally,
the author examines the role of intentions in ethical thinking and
constructs a novel defense of the principle based on fine
distinctions between intentions. The Principle of Double Effect: A
History and Philosophical Defense will be of interest to scholars
and advanced students working in moral philosophy, the history of
ethics, bioethics, medical ethics, and the Catholic moral
tradition.
|
|