|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Modern Western philosophy, c 1600 to the present > Western philosophy, from c 1900 -
Reflections on the Religious, the Ethical, and the Political
presents fourteen essays devoted to the interconnected topics of
religion, ethics, and politics, along with an introductory
interview with the author regarding his philosophical development
over the years. This volume serves two interconnected purposes: as
an introduction or reintroduction to Calvin O.Schrag s intellectual
contributions to a critical consideration of these three topics,
and as a critical companion and supplement to Schrag s published
work on these topics. The topics of religion, ethics, and politics
have served as pivot points throughout Schrag s career in the
academy, which spans half a century."
This is a unique collection presenting work by Alain Badiou and
commentaries on his philosophical theories. It includes three
lectures by Badiou, on contemporary politics, the infinite, cinema
and theatre and two extensive interviews with Badiou - one
concerning the state of the contemporary situation and one wide
ranging interview on all facets of his work and engagements. It
also includes six interventions on aspects of Badiou's work by
established scholars in the field, addressing his concept of
history, Lacan, Cinema, poetry, and feminism; and four original
essays by young and established scholars in Australia and New
Zealand addressing the key concerns of Badiou's 2015 visit to the
Antipodal region and the work he presented there. With new material
by Badiou previously unpublished in English this volume is a
valuable overview of his recent thinking. Critical responses by
distinguished and gifted Badiou scholars writing outside of the
European context make this text essential reading for anyone
interested in the development and contemporary reception of
Badiou's thought.
This is a book about the body and its amazing contribution to the
moral mind. The author focuses on the important roles the body
plays in moral cognition. What happens to us when we observe moral
violations, make moral judgments and engage in moral actions? How
does the body affect our moral decisions and shape our moral
dispositions? Can embodied moral psychology be consistently pursued
as a viable alternative to disembodied traditions of moral
philosophy? Is there any school of philosophy where the body is
discussed as the underlying foundation of moral judgment and
action? To answer these questions, the author analyzes Confucian
philosophy as an intriguing and insightful example of embodied
moral psychology.
Imagination and Postmodernity addresses the role of the imagination
in philosophy today. By focusing on philosophy at the boundary of
reason with constant reference to Kant s view of the
boundary-limit, it is possible to advance a viable alternative to
deconstructing the imagination. Patrick L. Bourgeois puts forth the
claim that by refocusing the imagination in the postmodern
conversation, a far-reaching contemporary position can be reached
that reestablishes the position of the humanities as central
against the anti-humanism of deconstruction. This work addresses
some of the challenges and problems that emerge in conflicting
positions within contemporary philosophy, including a concentration
on the role of the imagination in the work of Paul Ricoeur in
contrast and in opposition to its role in such postmodern thinkers
as Derrida and Lyotard. This treatment requires going back to the
role of the imagination in the period of Kant and his immediate
followers in order to clarify the various ways of seeing the
imagination then and now, for the role today is anticipated in the
nineteenth century. Finally, this work, as a creative appropriation
of the position of Paul Ricoeur, presents a role for the
imagination today that is more encompassing than most thinkers
allow for.
Michel Foucault continues to be regarded as one of the most
essential thinkers of the twentieth century. A brilliantly
evocative writer and conceptual creator, his influence is clearly
discernible today across nearly every discipline-philosophy and
history, certainly, as well as literary and critical theory,
religious and social studies, and the arts. This volume exploits
Foucault's insistent blurring of the self-imposed limits formed by
the disciplines, with each author in this volume discovering in
Foucault's work a model useful for challenging not only these
divisions but developing a more fundamental interrogation of
modernism. Foucault himself saw the calling into question of
modernism to be the permanent task of his life's work, thereby
opening a path for rethinking the social. Understanding Foucault,
Understanding Modernism shows, on the one hand, that literature and
the arts play a fundamental structural role in Foucault's works,
while, on the other hand, it shifts to the foreground what it
presumes to be motivating Foucault: the interrogation of the
problem of modernism. To that end, even his most explicitly
historical or strictly epistemological and methodological enquiries
directly engage the problem of modernism through the works of
writers and artists from de Sade, Mallarme, Baudelaire to Artaud,
Manet, Borges, Roussel, and Bataille. This volume, therefore,
adopts a transdisciplinary approach, as a way to establish
connections between Foucault's thought and the aesthetic problems
that emerge out of those specific literary and artistic works,
methods, and styles designated "modern." The aim of this volume is
to provide a resource for students and scholars not only in the
fields of literature and philosophy, but as well those interested
in the intersections of art and intellectual history, religious
studies, and critical theory.
The Risk of Freedom presents an in-depth analysis of the philosophy
of Jan Patocka, one of the most influential Central European
thinkers of the twentieth century, examining both the
phenomenological and ethical-political aspects of his work. In
particular, Francesco Tava takes an original approach to the
problem of freedom, which represents a recurring theme in Patocka's
work, both in his early and later writings. Freedom is conceived of
as a difficult and dangerous experience. In his deep analysis of
this particular problem, Tava identifies the authentic ethical
content of Patocka's work and clarifies its connections with
phenomenology, history of philosophy, politics and dissidence. The
Risk of Freedom retraces Patocka's philosophical journey and
elucidates its more problematic and less evident traits, such as
his original ethical conception, his political ideals and his
direct commitment as a dissident.
It is widely believed in philosophy of science that nobody can
claim that any verdict of science is forced upon us by the effects
of a physical world upon our sense organs and instruments. The
Quine-Duhem problem supposedly allows us to resist any conclusion.
Views on language aside, Quine is supposed to have shown this
decisively. But it is just false. In many scientific examples,
there is simply no room to doubt that a particular hypothesis is
responsible for a refutation or established by the observations.
Fault Tracing shows how to play independently established
hypotheses against each other to determine whether an arbitrary
hypothesis needs to be altered in the light of (apparently)
refuting evidence. It analyses real examples from natural science,
as well as simpler cases. It argues that, when scientific theories
have a structure that prevents them from using this method, the
theory looks wrong, and is subject to serious criticism. This is a
new, and potentially far-reaching, theory of empirical
justification.
Heidegger and the Emergence of the Question of Being offers a new,
updated and comprehensive introduction to Heidegger's development
and his early confrontation with philosophical tradition, theology,
neo-Kantianism, vitalism, hermeneutics, and phenomenology, up to
the publication of Being and Time in 1927. The main thread is the
genealogy of the question of the meaning of being. Alongside the
most recent scholarly research, this book takes into account the
documentary richness of Heidegger's first Freiburg (1919-1923) and
Marburg (1923-1928) lectures, conferences, treatises and letters
and addresses the thematic and methodological richness of this
period of Heidegger's intellectual life, and offers a coherent and
unified interpretation of his earlier work. This book conveys
Heidegger's thought in a well-organized, impartial manner, without
deviating too far from Heideggerian vocabulary. It will be
invaluable for upper level undergraduates, graduate students of
philosophy, studying phenomenology, continental and German
philosophy.
What is the meaning of life? Does anything really matter? In the
past few decades these questions, perennially associated with
philosophy in the popular consciousness, have rightly retaken their
place as central topics in the academy. In this major contribution,
Nicholas Waghorn provides a sustained and rigorous elucidation of
what it would take for lives to have significance. Bracketing
issues about ways our lives could have more or less meaning, the
focus is rather on the idea of ultimate meaning, the issue of
whether a life can attain meaning that cannot be called into
question. Waghorn sheds light on this most fundamental of
existential problems through a detailed yet comprehensive
examination of the notion of nothing, embracing classic and
cutting-edge literature from both the analytic and Continental
traditions. Central figures such as Heidegger, Carnap,
Wittgenstein, Nozick and Nagel are drawn upon to anchor the
discussion in some of the most influential discussion of recent
philosophical history. In the process of relating our ideas
concerning nothing to the problem of life's meaning, Waghorn's book
touches upon a number of fundamental themes, including reflexivity
and its relation to our conceptual limits, whether religion has any
role to play in the question of life's meaning, and the nature and
constraints of philosophical methodology. A number of major
philosophical traditions are addressed, including phenomenology,
poststructuralism, and classical and paraconsistent logics. In
addition to providing the most thorough current discussion of
ultimate meaning, it will serve to introduce readers to
philosophical debates concerning the notion of nothing, and the
appendix engaging religion will be of value to both philosophers
and theologians.
Hegel's critique of Early German Romanticism and its theory of
irony resonates to the core of his own philosophy in the same way
that Plato's polemics with the Sophists have repercussions that go
to the centre of his thought. The Anti-Romantic examines Hegel's
critique of Fr. Schlegel, Novalis and Schleiermacher. Hegel rarely
mentions these thinkers by name and the texts dealing with them
often exist on the periphery of his oeuvre. Nonetheless,
individually, they represent embodiments of specific forms of
irony: Schlegel, a form of critical individuality; Novalis, a form
of sentimental nihilism; Schleiermacher, a monstrous hybrid of the
other two. The strength of Hegel's polemical approach to these
authors shows how irony itself represents for him a persistent
threat to his own idea of systematic Science. This is so, we
discover, because Romantic irony is more than a rival ideology; it
is an actual form of discourse, one whose performative objectivity
interferes with the objectivity of Hegel's own logos. Thus, Hegel's
critique of irony allows us to reciprocally uncover a Hegelian
theory of scientific discourse. Far from seeing irony as a form of
consciousness overcome by Spirit, Hegel sees it as having become a
pressing feature of his own contemporary world, as witnessed in the
popularity of his Berlin rival, Schleiermacher. Finally, to the
extent that ironic discourse seems, for Hegel, to imply a certain
world beyond his own notion of modernity, we are left with the
hypothesis that Hegel's critique of irony may be viewed as a
critique of post-modernity.
French philosopher and Talmudic commentator Emmanuel Levinas
(1906-1995) has received considerable attention for his influence
on philosophical and religious thought. In this book, Victoria
Tahmasebi-Birgani provides the first examination of the
applicability of Emmanuel Levinas' work to social and political
movements. Investigating his ethics of responsibility and his
critique of the Western liberal imagination, Tahmasebi-Birgani
advances the moral, political, and philosophical debates on the
radical implications of Levinas' work.
Emmanuel Levinas and the Politics of Non-Violence is the first
book to closely consider the affinity between Levinas' ethical
vision and Mohandas Gandhi's radical yet non-violent political
struggle. Situating Levinas' insights within a transnational,
transcontinental, and global framework, Tahmasebi-Birgani
highlights Levinas' continued relevance in an age in which violence
is so often resorted to in the name of "justice" and "freedom."
A discussion of the rapidly growing field, from a thinker at the
forefront of research at the interface of technology and the
humanities, this is a must-read for anyone interested in
contemporary developments in Continental philosophy and philosophy
of technology. Philosophy of technology regularly draws on key
thinkers in the Continental tradition, including Husserl,
Heidegger, and Foucault. Yet because of the problematic legacy of
the 'empirical turn', it often criticizes 'bad' continental
tendencies - lyricism, pessimism, and an outdated view of
technology as an autonomous, transcendental force. This
misconception is based on a faulty image of Continental thought,
and in addressing it Smith productively redefines our concept of
technology. By closely engaging key texts, and by examining
'exceptional technologies' such as imagined, failed, and impossible
technologies that fall outside philosophy of technology's current
focus, this book offers a practical guide to thinking about and
using continental philosophy and philosophy of technology. It
outlines and enacts three key characteristics of philosophy as
practiced in the continental tradition: close reading of the
history of philosophy; focus on critique; and openness to other
disciplinary fields. Smith deploys the concept of exceptional
technologies to provide a novel way of widening discussion in
philosophy of technology, navigating the relationship between
philosophy of technology and Continental philosophy; the history of
both these fields; the role of imagination in relation to
technologies; and the social function of technologies themselves.
As neuroscience continues to reveal the biological basis of human
thought and behavior, what impact will this have on legal theory
and practice? The emerging field of neurolaw seeks to address this
question, but doing so adequately requires confronting difficult
philosophical issues surrounding the nature of mind, free will,
rationality, and responsibility. In The Philosophical Foundations
of Neurolaw, Martin Roth claims that the central philosophical
issue facing neurolaw is whether we can reconcile the conception of
ourselves as free, rational, and responsible agents with the
conception of ourselves as complex bio-chemical machines. Roth
argues that we can reconcile these conceptions. To show this, Roth
develops and defends an account of free will that identifies free
will with the capacity to respond to rational demands, and he
argues that this capacity is at the foundation of our thinking
about responsibility. Roth also shows how the mind sciences can
explain this capacity, thus revealing that a purely physical system
can have the kind of free will that is relevant to responsible
agency. Along the way, Roth critiques a number of arguments that
purport to show that the kind of reconciliation provided is not
possible. Roth concludes that though we should rethink our legal
system in important ways, both in light of his account of free will
and what neuroscience is poised to reveal, neuroscience does not
threaten the law's core commitment to responsible agency.
This book is mainly concerned with elaborating an account of the
unique theoretical essence and activities of philosophy. What
manner of civilization should modern humans forge? On what
developmental path should a nation embark? What lifestyle should
each individual choose? These are the most fundamental issues of
our time. Profoundly implicit in the choices outlined above is a
deeper question: What are the criteria of choice? An examination of
these criteria is a reflection on the premises constituting
thought, or a critique of the premises underlying thought. Using a
"critique of the premises underlying thought" as the basic idea and
hermeneutic principle in philosophy will open a wider theoretical
space for contemporary philosophy so as to avoid the predicament of
being "pseudo-scientific" or "pseudo-artistic." It will also
present contemporary philosophy with a realistic path of
development for the task of reflecting on the criteria of choice.
This book seeks to formulate concrete philosophical arguments for a
critique of the basic beliefs, logic, modes, concepts, and
philosophical ideas which constitute thought, with the aim of
demonstrating the vigorous self-critique and inexhaustible
theoretical space found in philosophical development. This book
provides a new principle of interpretation for understanding
philosophy and, in turn, uses this principle to develop a critique
of the premises underlying thought, thereby furthering the
contemporary development of philosophy. This book encompasses a
critique of the premises underlying thought, which mainly includes
the basic beliefs, logic, modes, concepts, and philosophical ideas
constituting thought. Such a critique should comprise five aspects:
First, the basic beliefs constituting thought propose a critique of
the identity of thought and being; second, the basic logic
constituting thought refers to a critique of the formal,
intensional, and practical logic of thought; third, the basic modes
constituting thought denote a critique of the basic modes by which
humans comprehend the world, including commonsense, religion, art,
and science; fourth, the basic concepts constituting thought entail
a critique centering on being, the world, history, truth, value,
and other basic concepts; and finally, the philosophical ideas
constituting thought indicate a critique of philosophy itself. A
critique aligned on these five aspects will provide a general
philosophical overview of the premise critique of thought.
The history of Continental philosophy is often conceived as being
represented by two major schools: German idealism and
phenomenology/existentialism. These two schools are frequently
juxtaposed so as to highlight their purported radical differences.
There is a commonly held view that an abrupt break occurred in the
nineteenth century, resulting in a disdainful rejection of idealism
in all its forms. This break is often located in the transition
from Hegel to Kierkegaard. The history of philosophy in the first
half of the nineteenth century has thus been read as a grand
confrontation between the overambitious rationalistic system of
Hegel and the devastating criticisms of it by Kierkegaard's
philosophy of existence. This work aims to undermine this popular
view of the radical break between idealism and existentialism by
means of a series of detailed studies in specific episodes of
European thought. As a whole, this book represents an important
attempt to demonstrate the long shadow cast by Kant and Hegel over
the subsequent history of European philosophy.
This book provides the first detailed study in English of the
religious philosophy of Vasilii Rozanov, one of the most
influential and controversial thinkers of Russia's Silver Age. It
examines his subversion of traditional Russian Orthodoxy, including
his reverence for the Creation, his focus on the family, and his
worship of sex.Rozanov is one of the towering figures of Russian
culture, a major influence on thinkers and writers such as Bakhtin,
Maiakovskii, and Mandelshtam, as well as many European writers. He
critiqued Orthodox theology, and wrote extensively on philosophy,
literature, and politics, and helped reform marriage and divorce
laws.His enormous contribution to Russian thought has been largely
neglected, and much of his work has been misunderstood. Ure
addresses this by examining the basis of Rozanov's religious
philosophy, the Creation of the Earth and the Book of Genesis.>
In this highly readable and well-arranged compilation-including his
much-celebrated "The Practice of Reading Good Books" and
award-winning "Playing with Bateson"-Corey Anton brings together
some of his most accessible and well-received essays. The
collection, in addition to advancing and integrating the fields of
media ecology and general semantics, will be of great interest to
people who are concerned over the changing role of reading and
literacy in contemporary life. A stimulating and provocative book
having wide relevance to scholars and students in the areas of
semiotics, rhetorical theory, orality/literacy studies, philosophy
of communication, pedagogical theory, and communication theory,
Communication Uncovered offers countless insights and broad-based
orientations regarding the nature of language, linguistic and
communicative habits, communication technologies, and symbolic
practices more generally. This is a "must have" resource for anyone
interested in multidisciplinary communication theory.
This book synthesizes Jacques Derrida's hauntology and spectrality
with affect theory, in order to create a rhetorical framework
analyzing the felt absences and hauntings of written and oral
texts. The book opens with a history of hauntology, spectrality,
and affect theory and how each of those ideas have been applied.
The book then moves into discussing the unique elements of the
rhetorical framework known as the rhetorrectional situation. Three
case studies taken from the Christian tradition, serve to
demonstrate how spectral rhetoric works. The first is fictional,
C.S. Lewis 'The Great Divorce. The second is non-fiction, Tim
Jennings 'The God Shaped Brain. The final one is taken from
homiletics, Bishop Michael Curry's royal wedding 2018 sermon. After
the case studies conclusion offers the reader a summary and ideas
future applications for spectral rhetoric.
|
|