|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Ancient Western philosophy to c 500 > General
We're all searching for answers to the biggest questions. How to be
good? How to find calm? How to properly grieve? How to beat FOMO?
How to work out what truly matters? Well, good news is that the
wisest minds in history asked the exact same questions - and they
found answers. Their ancient philosophy of Stoicism can show us
that we today are in fact already in possession of the very tools
we need to excavate this much-needed wisdom for ourselves. So into
the past we go with Brigid Delaney, to a time not unlike our own:
one full of pandemonium, war, plagues, pestilence, treachery,
corruption, anxiety, overindulgence and, even then, the fear of a
climate apocalypse. By learning and living the teachings of three
ancient guides, Epictetus, Seneca and Marcus Aurelius, Brigid shows
us how we can apply these lessons to our modern lives in a way that
allows us to regain a sense of agency and tranquillity. Stoicism
can be tough medicine to swallow, but not here-this book is awash
with insight, humour and compassion. Timely and so very useful, and
filled to the brim with ways you can wrest back control, here are
all the reasons not to worry.
Whereas the history of demography as a social science has been
amply explored, that of the construction of the concept of
population has been neglected. Specialists systematically ignore a
noteworthy paradox: strictly speaking, the great intellectual
figures of the past dealt with in this book have not produced
demographic theories or doctrines as such, but they have certainly
given some thought to population at both levels. First, the central
epistemological and methodological orientation of the book is
presented. Ideas on population, far from being part of the
harmonious advancement of knowledge are the product of their
context, that is evidently demographic, but also economic,
political and above all intellectual. Then the ideas on population
of Plato, Bodin, the French mercantilists, Quesnay and the
physiocrats are examined under this light. The last chapter
addresses the implicit philosophical, economic and political issues
of population thought.
Platonism and Christian Thought in Late Antiquity examines the
various ways in which Christian intellectuals engaged with
Platonism both as a pagan competitor and as a source of
philosophical material useful to the Christian faith. The chapters
are united in their goal to explore transformations that took place
in the reception and interaction process between Platonism and
Christianity in this period. The contributions in this volume
explore the reception of Platonic material in Christian thought,
showing that the transmission of cultural content is always
mediated, and ought to be studied as a transformative process by
way of selection and interpretation. Some chapters also deal with
various aspects of the wider discussion on how Platonic, and
Hellenic, philosophy and early Christian thought related to each
other, examining the differences and common ground between these
traditions. Platonism and Christian Thought in Late Antiquity
offers an insightful and broad ranging study on the subject, which
will be of interest to students of both philosophy and theology in
the Late Antique period, as well as anyone working on the reception
and history of Platonic thought, and the development of Christian
thought.
This book offers a novel defence of a highly contested
philosophical position: biological natural kind essentialism. This
theory is routinely and explicitly rejected for its purported
inability to be explicated in the context of contemporary
biological science, and its supposed incompatibility with the
process and progress of evolution by natural selection. Christopher
J. Austin challenges these objections, and in conjunction with
contemporary scientific advancements within the field of
evolutionary-developmental biology, the book utilises a
contemporary neo-Aristotelian metaphysics of "dispositional
properties", or causal powers, to provide a theory of essentialism
centred on the developmental architecture of organisms and its role
in the evolutionary process. By defending a novel theory of
Aristotelian biological natural kind essentialism, Essence in the
Age of Evolution represents the fresh and exciting union of
cutting-edge philosophical insight and scientific knowledge.
This book explores the origins of western biopolitics in ancient
Greek political thought. Ojakangas's argues that the conception of
politics as the regulation of the quantity and quality of
population in the name of the security and happiness of the state
and its inhabitants is as old as the western political thought
itself: the politico-philosophical categories of classical thought,
particularly those of Plato and Aristotle, were already
biopolitical categories. In their books on politics, Plato and
Aristotle do not only deal with all the central topics of
biopolitics from the political point of view, but for them these
topics are the very keystone of politics and the art of government.
Yet although the Western understanding of politics was already
biopolitical in classical Greece, the book does not argue that the
history of biopolitics would constitute a continuum from antiquity
to the twentieth century. Instead Ojakangas argues that the birth
of Christianity entailed a crisis of the classical biopolitical
rationality, as the majority of classical biopolitical themes
concerning the government of men and populations faded away or were
outright rejected. It was not until the renaissance of the
classical culture and literature - including the translation of
Plato's and Aristotles political works into Latin - that
biopolitics became topical again in the West. The book will be of
great interest to scholars and students in the field of social and
political studies, social and political theory, moral and political
philosophy, IR theory, intellectual history, classical studies.
This book offers a new account of Aristotle's practical philosophy.
Pavlos Kontos argues that Aristotle does not restrict practical
reason to its action-guiding and motivational role; rather,
practical reason remains practical in the full sense of the term
even when its exercise does not immediately concern the guidance of
our present actions. To elucidate why this wider scope of practical
reason is important, Kontos brings into the foreground five
protagonists that have long been overlooked: (a) spectators or
judges who make non-motivational judgments about practical matters
that do not interact with their present deliberations and actions;
(b) legislators who exercise practical reason to establish
constitutions and laws; (c) hopes as an active engagement with
moral luck and its impact on our individual lives; (d) prayers as
legislators' way to deal with the moral luck hovering around the
birth of constitutions and the prospect of a utopia; and (e) people
who are outsiders or marginal cases of the responsibility community
because they are totally deprived of practical reason. Building on
a wide range of interpretations of Aristotle's practical philosophy
(from the ancient commentators to contemporary analytic and
continental philosophers), Kontos offers new insights about
Aristotle's philosophical contribution to the current debates about
radical evil, moral luck, hope, utopia, internalism and
externalism, and the philosophy of law. Aristotle on the Scope of
Practical Reason will appeal to researchers and advanced students
interested in Aristotle's ethics, ancient philosophy, and the
history of practical philosophy.
This new edition introduces the reader to the philosophy of early
Christianity in the second to fourth centuries AD, and
contextualizes the philosophical contributions of early Christians
in the framework of the ancient philosophical debates. It examines
the first attempts of Christian thinkers to engage with issues such
as questions of cosmogony and first principles, freedom of choice,
concept formation, and the body-soul relation, as well as later
questions like the status of the divine persons of the Trinity. It
also aims to show that the philosophy of early Christianity is part
of ancient philosophy as a distinct school of thought, being in
constant dialogue with the ancient philosophical schools, such as
Platonism, Aristotelianism, Stoicism, and even Epicureanism and
Scepticism. This book examines in detail the philosophical views of
Christian thinkers such as Justin Martyr, Clement of Alexandria,
Irenaeus, Tertullian, Origen, Basil, and Gregory of Nyssa, and
sheds light in the distinct ways they conceptualized traditional
philosophical issues and made some intriguing contributions. The
book's core chapters survey the central philosophical concerns of
the early Christian thinkers and examines their contributions.
These range across natural philosophy, metaphysics, logic and
epistemology, psychology, and ethics, and include such questions as
how the world came into being, how God relates to the world, the
status of matter, how we can gain knowledge, in what sense humans
have freedom of choice, what the nature of soul is and how it
relates to the body, and how we can attain happiness and salvation.
This revised edition takes into account the recent developments in
the area of later ancient philosophy, especially in the philosophy
of Early Christianity, and integrates them in the relevant
chapters, some of which are now heavily expanded. The Philosophy of
Early Christianity remains a crucial introduction to the subject
for undergraduate and postgraduate students of ancient philosophy
and early Christianity, across the disciplines of classics,
history, and theology.
The present work has three principal objectives: (1) to fix the
chronology of the development of the pre-Euclidean theory of
incommensurable magnitudes beginning from the first discoveries by
fifth-century Pythago reans, advancing through the achievements of
Theodorus of Cyrene, Theaetetus, Archytas and Eudoxus, and
culminating in the formal theory of Elements X; (2) to correlate
the stages of this developing theory with the evolution of the
Elements as a whole; and (3) to establish that the high standards
of rigor characteristic of this evolution were intrinsic to the
mathematicians' work. In this third point, we wish to
counterbalance a prevalent thesis that the impulse toward
mathematical rigor was purely a response to the dialecticians'
critique of foundations; on the contrary, we shall see that not
until Eudoxus does there appear work which may be described as
purely foundational in its intent. Through the examination of these
problems, the present work will either alter or set in a new light
virtually every standard thesis about the fourth-century Greek
geometry. I. THE PRE-EUCLIDEAN THEORY OF INCOMMENSURABLE MAGNITUDES
The Euclidean theory of incommensurable magnitudes, as preserved in
Book X of the Elements, is a synthetic masterwork. Yet there are
detect able seams in its structure, seams revealed both through
terminology and through the historical clues provided by the
neo-Platonist commentator Proclus."
In studies of early Christian thought, 'philosophy' is often a
synonym for 'Platonism', or at most for 'Platonism and Stoicism'.
Nevertheless, it was Aristotle who, from the sixth century AD to
the Italian Renaissance, was the dominant Greek voice in Christian,
Muslim and Jewish philosophy. Aristotle and Early Christian Thought
is the first book in English to give a synoptic account of the slow
appropriation of Aristotelian thought in the Christian world from
the second to the sixth century. Concentrating on the great
theological topics - creation, the soul, the Trinity, and
Christology - it makes full use of modern scholarship on the
Peripatetic tradition after Aristotle, explaining the significance
of Neoplatonism as a mediator of Aristotelian logic. While
stressing the fidelity of Christian thinkers to biblical
presuppositions which were not shared by the Greek schools, it also
describes their attempts to overcome the pagan objections to
biblical teachings by a consistent use of Aristotelian principles,
and it follows their application of these principles to matters
which lay outside the purview of Aristotle himself. This volume
offers a valuable study not only for students of Christian theology
in its formative years, but also for anyone seeking an introduction
to the thought of Aristotle and its developments in Late Antiquity.
This collection of essays engages with several topics in
Aristotle's philosophy of mind, some well-known and hotly debated,
some new and yet to be explored. The contributors analyze
Aristotle's arguments and present their cases in ways that invite
contemporary philosophers of mind to consider the potentials-and
pitfalls-of an Aristotelian philosophy of mind. The volume brings
together an international group of renowned Aristotelian scholars
as well as rising stars to cover five main themes: method in the
philosophy of mind, sense perception, mental representation,
intellect, and the metaphysics of mind. The papers collected in
this volume, with their choice of topics and quality of exposition,
show why Aristotle is a philosopher of mind to be studied and
reckoned with in contemporary discussions. Encounters with
Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind will be of interest to scholars and
advanced students of ancient philosophy and philosophy of mind.
The Symposium is Plato's dramatic masterpiece, his most perfect
work and arguably his most seminal dialogue. Its influence on the
minds of Europe, from Plotinus to Proust, is everywhere in
evidence. Yet today when we talk of Platonic love we are not near
Plato's conception. This translation aims to recover the sense of
Plato's original idea.
Xenophon's Socratic Works demonstrates that Xenophon, a student of
Socrates, military man, and man of letters, is an indispensable
source for our understanding of the life and philosophy of
Socrates. David M. Johnson restores Xenophon's most ambitious
Socratic work, the Memorabilia (Socratic Recollections), to its
original literary context, enabling readers to experience it as
Xenophon's original audience would have, rather than as a pale
imitation of Platonic dialogue. He shows that the Memorabilia,
together with Xenophon's Apology, provides us with our best
evidence for the trial of Socrates, and a comprehensive and
convincing refutation of the historical charges against Socrates.
Johnson's account of Socrates' moral psychology shows how
Xenophon's emphasis on control of the passions can be reconciled
with the intellectualism normally attributed to Socrates. Chapters
on Xenophon's Symposium and Oeconomicus (Estate Manager) reveal how
Xenophon used all the literary tools of Socratic dialogue to defend
Socratic sexual morality (Symposium) and debate the merits and
limits of conventional elite values (Oeconomicus). Throughout the
book, Johnson argues that Xenophon's portrait of Socrates is rich
and coherent, and largely compatible with the better-known portrait
of Socrates in Plato. Xenophon aimed not to provide a rival
portrait of Socrates, Johnson shows, but to supplement and clarify
what others had said about Socrates. Xenophon's Socratic Works,
thus, provides readers with a far firmer basis for reconstruction
of the trial of Socrates, a key moment in the history of Athenian
democracy, and for our understanding of Socrates' seminal impact on
Greek philosophy. This volume introduces Xenophon's Socratic works
to a wide range of readers, from undergraduate students
encountering Socrates or ancient philosophy for the first time to
scholars with interests in Socrates or ancient philosophy more
broadly. It is also an important resource for readers interested in
Socratic dialogue as a literary form, the trial of Socrates, Greek
sexual morality (the central topic of Xenophon's Symposium), or
Greek social history (for which the Oeconomicus is a key text).
Did the ancient Greeks and Romans use psychoactive cannabis?
Scholars say that hemp was commonplace in the ancient world, but
there is no consensus on cannabis usage. According to botany, hemp
and cannabis are the same plant and thus the ancient Greeks and
Romans must have used it in their daily lives. Cultures parallel to
the ancient Greeks and Romans, like the Egyptians, Scythians, and
Hittites, were known to use cannabis in their medicine, religion
and recreational practices. Cannabis in the Ancient Greek and Roman
World surveys the primary references to cannabis in ancient Greek
and Roman texts and covers emerging scholarship about the plant in
the ancient world. Ancient Greek and Latin medical texts from the
Roman Empire contain the most mentions of the plant, where it
served as an effective ingredient in ancient pharmacy. Cannabis in
the Ancient Greek and Roman World focuses on the ancient rationale
behind cannabis and how they understood the plant's properties and
effects, as well as its different applications. For the first time
ever, this book provides a sourcebook with the original ancient
Greek and Latin, along with translations, of all references to
psychoactive cannabis in the Greek and Roman world. It covers the
archaeology of cannabis in the ancient world, including amazing
discoveries from Scythian burial sites, ancient proto-Zoroastrian
fire temples, Bronze Age Chinese burial sites, as well as evidence
in Greece and Rome. Beyond cannabis, Cannabis in the Ancient Greek
and Roman World also explores ancient views on medicine, pharmacy,
and intoxication.
Liberation and Authority: Plato's Gorgias, the First Book of the
Republic, and Thucydides provides a comparative treatment of
Plato's Gorgias, the first book of the Republic, and Thucydides'
History, arguing that they share similarities not only in the
oft-noted "natural justice" of Callicles, Thrasymachus, and the
Melian Dialogue, but also in a development that runs through the
whole of each work. Nicholas Thorne argues that all three works
give an account of the collapse of the authority of an older
ethical order, out of which a subjective spirit arises that strives
to liberate itself from all limits on its own activity. The
readings of Plato give a new account of each work that shows how
the logic of the arguments is inextricably bound together with the
literary detail, including each work's structure. The account of
Thucydides argues for certain new interpretive concepts, such as
the idea that the whole is greater than the sum of its parts, while
also providing a new look at a number of familiar theses, such as
the three-step structure running through the whole. Taken together,
these works provide complementary reflections on a development
profoundly relevant to our own time.
First published in 1991, The Greatest Happiness Principle traces
the history of the theory of utility, starting with the Bible, and
running through Plato, Aristotle, and Epicurus. It goes on to
discuss the utilitarian theories of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart
Mill in detail, commenting on the latter's view of the Christianity
of his day and his optimal socialist society. The book argues that
the key theory of utility is fundamentally concerned with
happiness, stating that discussions of happiness have been largely
left out of discussions of utility, it also argues utility as a
moral theory, posing the question ultimately, what is happiness?
Pyrrhonian Buddhism reconstructs the path to enlightenment shared
both by early Buddhists and the ancient Greek sceptics inspired by
Pyrrho of Elis, who may have had extended contacts with Buddhists
when he accompanied Alexander the Great to India in the third
century BCE. This volume explores striking parallels between early
Buddhism and Pyrrhonian scepticism, suggesting their virtual
identity. Both movements saw beliefs-fictions mistaken for
truths-as the principal source of human suffering. Both practiced
suspension of judgment about beliefs to obtain release from
suffering, and to achieve enlightenment, which the Buddhists called
bodhi and the Pyrrhonists called ataraxia. And both came to
understand the structure of human experience without belief, which
the Buddhists called dependent origination and the Pyrrhonists
described as phenomenalistic atomism. This book is intended for the
general reader, as well as historians, classicists, Buddhist
scholars, philosophers, and practitioners of spiritual techniques.
'I'll stop doing it as soon as I understand what I'm doing.'
Somewhere between a historical account and work of philosophy,
Socrates' Defence details the final plea of Plato's beloved mentor.
Introducing Little Black Classics: 80 books for Penguin's 80th
birthday. Little Black Classics celebrate the huge range and
diversity of Penguin Classics, with books from around the world and
across many centuries. They take us from a balloon ride over
Victorian London to a garden of blossom in Japan, from Tierra del
Fuego to 16th-century California and the Russian steppe. Here are
stories lyrical and savage; poems epic and intimate; essays
satirical and inspirational; and ideas that have shaped the lives
of millions. Plato (474 BC-347 BC). Plato's works available in
Penguin Classics are Republic, The Last Days of Socrates, The Laws,
Phaedrus, Protagoras and Meno, Timaeus and Critias, Theaetetus,
Early Socratic Dialogues, The Symposium and Gorgias.
This is the first volume of essays devoted to Aristotelian formal
causation and its relevance for contemporary metaphysics and
philosophy of science. The essays trace the historical development
of formal causation and demonstrate its relevance for contemporary
issues, such as causation, explanation, laws of nature, functions,
essence, modality, and metaphysical grounding. The introduction to
the volume covers the history of theories of formal causation and
points out why we need a theory of formal causation in contemporary
philosophy. Part I is concerned with scholastic approaches to
formal causation, while Part II presents four contemporary
approaches to formal causation. The three chapters in Part III
explore various notions of dependence and their relevance to formal
causation. Part IV, finally, discusses formal causation in biology
and cognitive sciences. Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on Formal
Causation will be of interest to advanced graduate students and
researchers working on contemporary Aristotelian approaches to
metaphysics and philosophy of science. This volume includes
contributions by Jose Tomas Alvarado, Christopher J. Austin,
Giacomo Giannini, Jani Hakkarainen, Ludger Jansen, Markku Keinanen,
Gyula Klima, James G. Lennox, Stephen Mumford, David S. Oderberg,
Michele Paolini Paoletti, Sandeep Prasada, Petter Sandstad,
Wolfgang Sattler, Benjamin Schnieder, Matthew Tugby, and Jonas
Werner.
"Pleasure in Aristotle's Ethics" provides an innovative and
crucially important account of the role of pleasure and desire in
Aristotle's ethics. Michael Weinman seeks to overcome common
impasses in the mainstream interpretation of Aristotle's ethical
philosophy through the careful study of Aristotle's account of
pleasure in the human, but not merely human, good, thus presenting
a new way in which we can improve our understanding of Aristotle's
ethics. Weinman asserts that we should read Aristotle's ethical
arguments in the light of his views on the cosmos (the living whole
we call nature) and the never-changing principles informing that
living whole. Weinman shows that what, above all else, emerges from
this new re-reading of the ethical writings is a new understanding
of human desire as the natural stretching ourselves toward
pleasure, which is the good, and which is the good by nature. These
lessons will demonstrate why we must understand the virtues as
unified, why the good described in "Nicomachean Ethics" is both a
human and greater-than-human good, and why the reasoning and
desiring parts of the soul must be understood as companions. The
necessary but as yet unrealised account of pleasure this book
advances is integral to improving our understanding of Aristotle's
ethics. This fascinating book will be of interest to anyone with an
interest in Aristotle's ethical theory and in particular his
"Nicomachean Ethics".
Martin Heidegger held Plato responsible for inaugurating the slow
slide of the West into nihilism and the apocalyptic crisis of
modernity. In this book, Gregory Fried defends Plato against
Heidegger's critiques. While taking seriously Heidegger's analysis
of human finitude and historicity, Fried argues that Heidegger
neglects the transcending ideals that necessarily guide human life
as situated in time and place. That neglect results in Heidegger's
disastrous politics, unhinged from a practical reason grounded in
the philosophical search from a truth that transcends historical
contingency. Thinking both with and against Heidegger, Fried shows
how Plato's skeptical idealism provides an ethics that captures
both the situatedness of finite human existence and the need for
transcendent ideals. The result is a novel way of understanding
politics and ethical life that Fried calls a polemical ethics,
which mediates between finitude and transcendence by engaging in
constructive confrontation with both traditions and other persons.
The contradiction between the founding ideals of the United States
and its actual history of racism and slavery provides an occasion
to discuss polemical ethics in practice.
This book is the first comprehensive study of Plato's conception of
justice. The universality of human rights and human
dignity-recognized as the source of the former-are among the
crucial philosophical problems in modern-day legal orders and in
contemporary culture in general. If dignity is genuinely universal,
then human beings also possessed it in ancient times. Plato not
only perceived human dignity, but a recognition of dignity is also
visible in his conception of justice, which forms the core of his
philosophy. Plato's Republic is consistently interpreted in the
book as a treatise on justice, relating to the individual and not
the state. The famous myth of the cave is a story about education
taking place in the world here and now. The best activity is not
contemplation but acting for the benefit of others. Not ideas but
individuals are the proper objects of love. Plato's philosophy may
provide foundations for modern-day human rights protection rather
than for totalitarian orders.
|
|