|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy > Western philosophy, c 500 to c 1600 > General
This collection of essays is unparalleled in the depth of its coverage of all facets of Galileo's work. A particular feature of the volume is the treatment of Galileo's relationship with the Church. It will be of particular interest to philosophers, historians of science, cultural historians and those in religious studies. New readers and nonspecialists will find this the most convenient, accessible guide to Galileo available. Advanced students and specialists will find a conspectus of recent developments in the interpretation of Galileo.
With the publication of Arthur Farndell's "Gardens of Philosophy"
(Shepheard-Walwyn 2006), there remained only four of Ficino's
commentaries on Plato's dialogues which had not yet been translated
into English. Farndell's translation of the commentaries on "The
Republic and the Laws" will comprise the third volume under the
title "When Philosophers Rule" and the fourth, "All Things
Natural", will contain the "Timaeus". As Carol Kaske of Cornell
University wrote when reviewing "Gardens of Philosophy" in
"Renaissance Quarterly", these translations fill 'A need. Even
those Anglophone scholars who know Latin still need a translation
in order to read quickly through a large body of material'. The
central message of 'Parmenides', that everything depends on the
One, resonates with the growing awareness around the world of the
inter-relatedness of all things, be it in the biosphere, the
intellectual or spiritual realms. Philosophers in ancient Greece
appreciated this unity and employed reason and dialectic to draw
the mind away from its preoccupation with the material world and
attract it towards contemplation of the soul, and ultimately of
that Oneness which embraces, but is distinct from, the multifarious
forms of creation. Thus Parmenides carefully instructed the young
Socrates, and Plato recorded their dialogue in this work which he
named after the elderly philosopher. Nearly 2000 years later,
Marsilio Ficino made 'Parmenides' available to the West by
translating it into Latin, the language of scholars in his time.
Ficino added a lengthy commentary to this translation, a commentary
which "Evermore Shall Be So" puts into English for the first time,
more than 500 years after its original composition. Ficino's
crucial influence upon the unfolding of the Renaissance and his
presentation of Plato's understanding of the One and the so-called
Platonic Ideas or Forms make "Evermore Shall Be So" an important
work in the history of thought. Though it will be an essential buy
for renaissance scholars and historians, its freshness of thought
and wisdom are as relevant today as they ever were to inspire a new
generation seeking spiritual and philosophical direction in their
lives.
Kants kritischer Philosophie wird bis heute von prominenter Seite
der Vorwurf gemacht, sie unterstelle ein im Kern
subjektivistisch-monologisches Individuum. Tatsachlich aber liegt
ihr nichts ferner als ein solcher Subjektivismus. Kants Vernunft
ist eine durch und durch oeffentliche Vernunft, sie ist, wie er
selbst sagt, existenziell angewiesen auf oeffentliches Rasonnement.
Kant verwendet den Begriff "OEffentlichkeit", anders als das
Adjektiv "oeffentlich", in seinem schriftlichen Werk zwar kein
einziges Mal, die Funktion der OEffentlichkeit aber sieht er als
fur sein Denken elementar an. Entscheidend dabei: OEffentlichkeit
ist nicht nur eine Bedingung allen kritischen Vernunftgebrauchs,
sondern gerade auch dessen Folge. Trager der Vernunft sind freie,
empirische Individuen. Machen diese Individuen Gebrauch von ihrer
oeffentlichen Vernunft, konstituieren sie bestimmte
OEffentlichkeiten des Vernunftgebrauchs - namlich neben der
politischen, die theoretische, die praktische und die asthetische
OEffentlichkeit. Die vorliegende Arbeit geht dieser OEffentlichkeit
der Vernunft unter anderem in den drei Kritiken nach - und zeigt
dabei, wie eng insbesondere Kants theoretische Philosophie mit
seinen politischen Schriften verbunden ist.
The third volume of The Hackett Aquinas, a series of central
philosophical treatises of Aquinas in new, state-of-the-art
translations accompanied by a thorough commentary on the text.
Global Justice and the Mind of Our Epoch explores the mind of our
epoch, defined as the period since the Nuremberg Trial and the
establishment of the United Nations in 1945. Xunwu Chen examines
four defining ideas of this epoch—global justice,
cosmopolitanism, crimes against humanity, and cultural
toleration—as well as the relationships among these ideas. Chen
argues that the mind of our epoch is the mind of humanity. Its
world view, horizon, standpoint, norms, standards, and vocabularies
are all embodied in human institutions and practices throughout the
globe. Furthermore, our epochal mind has a dialectical relationship
with particular cultures and peoples, bearing normative force. As a
metaphysical subjectivity and substance, humanity is the source of
all human values and defines what can and should be human values
and virtues. Humankind, therefore, is a people with socio-political
and legal sovereignty, sharing a common fate. This novel study
brings a cross-cultural approach and will be of great interest to
students and scholars of philosophy, political science, sociology,
and the humanities more broadly.
It is generally accepted that the European Renaissance began in
Italy. However, a historical transformation of similar magnitude
also took place in northern Europe at the same time. This 'Other
Renaissance' was initially centred on the city of Bruges in
Flanders (modern Belgium), but its influence was soon being felt in
France, the German states, England, and even in Italy itself.
Following a sequence of major figures, including Copernicus,
Gutenberg, Luther, Catherine de Medici, Rabelais, van Eyck and
Shakespeare, Paul Strathern tells the fascinating story of how this
'Other Renaissance' played as significant a role as the Italian
renaissance in bringing our modern world into being.
Already a classic, this landmark study of early Western thought now
appears in a new edition with expanded coverage of the Middle Ages.
This landmark study of Western thought takes a fresh look at the
writings of the great thinkers of classic philosophy and questions
many pieces of conventional wisdom. The book invites comparison
with Bertrand Russell's monumental History of Western Philosophy,
"but Gottlieb's book is less idiosyncratic and based on more recent
scholarship" (Colin McGinn, Los Angeles Times). A New York Times
Notable Book, a Los Angeles Times Best Book, and a Times Literary
Supplement Best Book of 2001.
Im Zentrum des Bandes steht die Frage nach dem Zusammenhang von
Erkenntnis- und Wissenschaftstheorie im Kontext der
mittelalterlichen Rezeption der Texte des Aristoteles an Hof und
Universitaten, insbesondere der fur die Epistemologie einschlagigen
Passagen in "De anima" und in den "Zweiten Analytiken" sowie ihre
spatantike und arabische Vermittlung. In diesem komplexen
Rezeptions- und vor allem Transformationsprozess werden zugleich
die wissenschaftlichen und gesellschaftlich-institutionellen
Grundlagen fur den okzidentalen Prozess der Rationalisierung und
Aufklarung gelegt, deren "Dialektik" nicht nur die Geschichte
Europas bis zum heutigen Tag bestimmt."
Despite our admiration for Renaissance achievement in the arts and
sciences, in literature and classical learning, the rich and
diversified philosophical thought of the period remains largely
unknown. This volume illuminates three major currents of thought
dominant in the earlier Italian Renaissance: classical humanism
(Petrarch and Valla), Platonism (Ficino and Pico), and
Aristotelianism (Pomponazzi). A short and elegant work of the
Spaniard Vives is included to exhibit the diffusion of the ideas of
humanism and Platonism outside Italy. Now made easily accessible,
these texts recover for the English reader a significant facet of
Renaissance learning.
Too often the study of philosophical texts is carried out in ways
that do not pay significant attention to how the ideas contained
within them are presented, articulated, and developed. This was not
always the case. The contributors to this collected work consider
Jewish philosophy in the medieval period, when new genres and forms
of written expression were flourishing in the wake of renewed
interest in ancient philosophy. Many medieval Jewish philosophers
were highly accomplished poets, for example, and made conscious
efforts to write in a poetic style. This volume turns attention to
the connections that medieval Jewish thinkers made between the
literary, the exegetical, the philosophical, and the mystical to
shed light on the creativity and diversity of medieval thought. As
they broaden the scope of what counts as medieval Jewish
philosophy, the essays collected here consider questions about how
an argument is formed, how text is put into the service of
philosophy, and the social and intellectual environment in which
philosophical texts were produced.
A historical and systematic introduction to what the medieval
philospher and theologian Thomas Aquinas (1225-74) said about faith
in the Trinity. Gilles Emery OP provides an explanation of the main
questions in Thomas's treatise on the Trinity in his major work,
the Summa Theologiae. His presentation clarifies the key ideas
through which Thomas accounts for the nature of Trinitarian
monotheism. Emery focuses on the personal relations of the Father,
Son, and Holy Spirit, both in their eternal communion and in their
creative and saving action. By highlighting the thought of one of
the greatest defenders of the doctrine of the Trinity, he enables
people to grasp the classical Christian understanding of God.
Too often the study of philosophical texts is carried out in ways
that do not pay significant attention to how the ideas contained
within them are presented, articulated, and developed. This was not
always the case. The contributors to this collected work consider
Jewish philosophy in the medieval period, when new genres and forms
of written expression were flourishing in the wake of renewed
interest in ancient philosophy. Many medieval Jewish philosophers
were highly accomplished poets, for example, and made conscious
efforts to write in a poetic style. This volume turns attention to
the connections that medieval Jewish thinkers made between the
literary, the exegetical, the philosophical, and the mystical to
shed light on the creativity and diversity of medieval thought. As
they broaden the scope of what counts as medieval Jewish
philosophy, the essays collected here consider questions about how
an argument is formed, how text is put into the service of
philosophy, and the social and intellectual environment in which
philosophical texts were produced.
First published in Paris in 1511, The Praise of Folly hasenjoyed
enormous and highly controversial success from the author’s
lifetime down to our own day.It hasno rival, except perhaps Thomas
More’s Utopia, as the most intense and lively presentation of the
literary, social, and theological aims and methods of Northern
Humanism. Clarence H. Miller’s highly praised translation of The
Praise of Folly, based on the definitive Latin text, echoes
Erasmus’ own lively style while retaining the nuances of the
original text. In his introduction, Miller places the work in the
context of Erasmus as humanist and theologian. In a new afterword,
William H. Gass playfully considers the meaning, or meanings, of
folly and offers fresh insights into one of the great books of
Western literature. Praise for the earlier edition: “An eminently
reliable and fully annotated edition based on the Latin
text.”—Library Journal “Exciting and brilliant, this is
likely to be the definitive translation of The Praise of Folly
intoEnglish.”—Richard J. Schoeck
The book is a systematic study of the issue of self-individuation
in the scholastic debate on principles of individuation (principia
individuationis). The point of departure is a general formulation
of the problem of individuation acceptable for all the participants
of the scholastic debate: a principle of individuation of x is what
makes x individual (in various possible senses of 'making something
individual'). The book argues against a prima facie plausible view
that everything that is individual is individual by itself and not
by anything distinct from it (Strong Self-Individuation Thesis).
The keynote topic of the book is a detailed analysis of the two
competing ways of rejecting the Strong Self-Individuation Thesis:
the Scotistic and the Thomistic one. The book defends the latter
one, discussing a number of issues concerning substantial and
accidental forms, essences, properties, instantiation, the
Thomistic notion of materia signata, Frege's Begriff-Gegenstand
distinction, and Geach's form-function analogy developed in his
writings on Aquinas. In the context of both the scholastic and
contemporary metaphysics, the book offers a framework for dealing
with issues of individuality and defends a Thomistic theory of
individuation.
The Singular Voice of Being reconsiders John Duns Scotus's
well-studied theory of the univocity of being in light of his less
explored discussions of ultimate difference. Ultimate difference is
a notion introduced by Aristotle and known by the Aristotelian
tradition, but one that, this book argues, Scotus radically
retrofits to buttress his doctrine of univocity. Scotus broadens
ultimate difference to include not only specific differences, but
also intrinsic modes of being (e.g., finite/infinite) and
principles of individuation (i.e., haecceitates). Furthermore, he
deepens it by divorcing it from anything with categorical
classification, such as substantial form. Scotus uses his revamped
notion of ultimate difference as a means of dividing being, despite
the longstanding Parmenidean arguments against such division. The
book highlights the unique role of difference in Scotus's thought,
which conceives of difference not as a fall from the perfect unity
of being but rather as a perfective determination of an otherwise
indifferent concept. The division of being culminates in
individuation as the final degree of perfection, which constitutes
indivisible (i.e., singular) degrees of being. This systematic
study of ultimate difference opens new dimensions for understanding
Scotus's dense thought with respect to not only univocity, but also
to individuation, cognition, and acts of the will.
The "Platonic Theology" is a visionary work and the
philosophical masterpiece of Marsilio Ficino (1433-1499), the
Florentine scholar-philosopher-magus who was largely responsible
for the Renaissance revival of Plato.
A student of the Neoplatonic schools of Plotinus and Proclus,
he was committed to reconciling Platonism with Christianity, in the
hope that such a reconciliation would initiate a spiritual revival
and return of the golden age. His Platonic evangelizing was
eminently successful and widely influential, and his "Platonic
Theology, " translated into English for the first time in this
edition, is one of the keys to understanding the art, thought,
culture, and spirituality of the Renaissance.
Includes an introduction by Marilyn McCord Adams along with Notes
and Appendices.
Alone among Thomas Aquinas' works, the Summa Theologiae contains
well-developed and integrated discussions of metaphysics, ethics,
law, human action, and the divine nature. The essays in this
volume, by scholars representing varied approaches to the study of
Aquinas, offer thorough, cutting-edge expositions and analyses of
these topics and show how they relate to Aquinas' larger system of
thought. The volume also examines the reception of the Summa
Theologiae from the thirteenth century to the present day, showing
how scholars have understood and misunderstood this key text - and
how, even after seven centuries of interpretation, we still have
much to learn from it. Detailed and accessible, this book will be
highly important for scholars and students of medieval philosophy
and theology.
The ancient topic of universals was central to scholastic
philosophy, which raised the question of whether universals exist
as Platonic forms, as instantiated Aristotelian forms, as concepts
abstracted from singular things, or as words that have universal
signification. It might be thought that this question lost its
importance after the decline of scholasticism in the modern period.
However, the fourteen contributions contained in The Problem of
Univerals in Early Modern Philosophy indicate that the issue of
universals retained its vitality in modern philosophy. Modern
philosophers in fact were interested in 3 sets of issues concerning
universals: (i) issues concerning the ontological status of
universals, (ii) issues concerning the psychology of the formation
of universal concepts or terms, and (iii) issues concerning the
value and use of universal concepts or terms in the acquisition of
knowledge. Chapters in this volume consider the various forms of
"Platonism," "conceptualism" and "nominalism" (and distinctive
combinations thereof) that emerged from the consideration of such
issues in the work of modern philosophers. Furthermore, this volume
covers not only the canonical modern figures, namely, Descartes,
Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, Hume and Kant, but also more
neglected figures such as Pierre Gassendi, Pierre-Sylvain Regis,
Nicolas Malebranche, Henry More, Ralph Cudworth and John Norris.
In diesem Band deckt Diego D'Angelo semiotische Strukturen in der
Husserl'schen Phanomenologie der Wahrnehmung auf. Ist es der
Phanomenologie darum zu tun, die Erfahrung von Dingen in unserer
Umwelt zu beschreiben, so ist dabei der Begriff des Horizontes von
zentraler Bedeutung: Was wir unmittelbar wahrnehmen, verweist immer
schon auf anderes, was nur "mitgegeben" ist. Wenn wir Dinge
wahrnehmen, haben wir nur eine bestimmte Perspektive, d.h. wir
sehen lediglich einen Aspekt. Aber wir nehmen immer ganze
Gegenstande wahr (wir sehen Tische und Stuhle und andere Menschen).
Jeder dieser Gegenstande erscheint in einem Feld weiterer
Gegenstande, und es ist der Horizontbegriff, der es erlaubt, das
Verhaltnis zwischen Selbstgegebenheit und Mitgegebenheit zu
explizieren. Dieses Buch stellt den ersten detaillierten Versuch
dar, die Ursprunge solcher horizontaler Felder in semiotischen
Strukturen zu suchen. Aus der Verbindung zwischen Husserls eigener
Semiotik und seiner Phanomenologie der Wahrnehmung ergibt sich,
dass das wahrgenommene Phanomen als Zeichen verstanden werden muss.
Das Zeichen wiederum bezeichnet etwas, was in leiblicher Bewegung
eingeholt werden kann. Mit der Verbindung von Leiblichkeit,
Semiotik und Wahrnehmung thematisiert diese Monographie das
Verhaltnis zwischen folgenden phanomenologischen
Forschungsgebieten: * Husserls Semiotik der Wahrnehmung in den
Logischen Untersuchungen * Phanomenologische Raumanalyse -
kinasthetische Indikation * Horizont und Noema * Passive Anzeige *
Zeichen und Leiblichkeit als Grundlagen der Fremderfahrung *
Genetische Phanomenologie und Semiotik der Erfahrung * Protentionen
und teleologische Semiose * Induktion und Ursprung des menschlichen
Ichs Das Buch eroeffnet die Moeglichkeit, Husserls Phanomenologie
jenseits einer Metaphysik der Prasenz zu verstehen. Zudem leisten
D'Angelos Einzeluntersuchungen einen Beitrag zu aktuellen
Diskussionen in der Philosophie der leiblichen Kognition. - Eine
hilfreiche Leseempfehlung fur * Interessierte Themenneulinge *
Bachelor- und Masterstudenten der Geisteswissenschaften *
Hochschulabsolventen sowie Forschungswissenschaftler
|
You may like...
Meditations
Marcus Aurelius
Hardcover
R618
Discovery Miles 6 180
|