|
Books > Science & Mathematics > Science: general issues > Philosophy of science
The authors describe systematic methods for uncovering scientific
laws a priori, on the basis of intuition, or "Gedanken
Experiments". Mathematical expressions of scientific laws are, by
convention, constrained by the rule that their form must be
invariant with changes of the units of their variables. This
constraint makes it possible to narrow down the possible forms of
the laws. It is closely related to, but different from, dimensional
analysis. It is a mathematical book, largely based on solving
functional equations. In fact, one chapter is an introduction to
the theory of functional equations.
The book examines the emerging approach of using qualitative
methods, such as interviews and field observations, in the
philosophy of science. Qualitative methods are gaining popularity
among philosophers of science as more and more scholars are
resorting to empirical work in their study of scientific practices.
At the same time, the results produced through empirical work are
quite different from those gained through the kind of introspective
conceptual analysis more typical of philosophy. This volume
explores the benefits and challenges of an empirical philosophy of
science and addresses questions such as: What do philosophers gain
from empirical work? How can empirical research help to develop
philosophical concepts? How do we integrate philosophical
frameworks and empirical research? What constraints do we accept
when choosing an empirical approach? What constraints does a
pronounced theoretical focus impose on empirical work? Nine experts
discuss their thoughts and empirical results in the chapters of
this book with the aim of providing readers with an answer to these
questions.
The essays and commentaries presented here are intended to strike a
balance between the disciplines to which the Bar-Hillel Colloquium
(formerly the Israel Colloquium) is dedicated. The historical and
sociological vantage point is addressed in Krammick's and Mali's
treatment of Priestley, in Vicker's and Feldhay's studies of the
Renaissance occult and in Warnke's and Barasch's work on the
imagination. From a philosophical angle several concepts, all
material to the methodology of science, are taken up: rule
following, by Smart and Margalit; analysis, by Ackerman,
explanation, by Taylor; and the role of mathematics in physics, by
Levy-Leblond and Pitowsky. In addition, the volume contains the
proceedings of two symposia dedicated to two towering scientific
figures: one celebrates Bohr's centennial, and the other examines
the "other" Newton. The book should appeal to people whose interest
or research is in the fields of philosophy, sociology and history
of science, technology and medicine, as well as those interested in
science education.
The fifth volume of the collected works of Professor M.A.K.
Halliday, The Language of Science, explores the semantic character
of scientific discourse. The chapters are organized into two
sections, one being on grammatical metaphor; the other dealing with
scientific English. In language, there exists the potential for
constructing new discourses, among them scientific discourse. The
volume opens with a new work from Professor Halliday addressing the
question, How big is a language? It is a question that goes to the
heart of the paradigmatic complexity, or meaning potential, that
characterizes language.
"The Emerging Religion of Science" is a broad and erudite
examination of the individual's place in the modern world. What can
we believe today that will not betray us tomorrow? the author asks.
Religion is losing influence. But the scientist, who explores the
laws of nature, may be the modern guide to meaning. The
mathematical equations of science have become unifying elements of
the world as we know it. The author explores ways to face today's
problems within the context of good and evil, freedom and
restraint, probability and certainty, the real and the illusory,
and the concept of self. He offers the view that, thought the paths
we take may be different, we are all searching for the same thing:
a thread on which the beads of experience and education can be
strung.
This is a translation of work which first appeared in 1816 in
Germany. Although Schopenhauer himself acknowledged that the
treatise did not present any new and significant doctrines to his
philosophy, he nonetheless considered it important enough to
publish it again in revised form toward the end of his life, in
1854. As Professor Cartwright argues in his introduction, the
book's philosophical value is to be found in the means it provides
for increasing our understanding of Schopenhauer's philosophy, both
in terms of its method and meaning. Not only does this book aim to
offer insight into the younger Schopenhauer, it is also a
significant document in the history of optics and colour theory.
This book presents a collection of authoritative contributions on
the concept of time in early twentieth-century philosophy. It is
structured in the form of a thematic atlas: each section is
accompanied by relevant elementary logic maps that reproduce in a
"spatial" form the directionalities (arguments and/or discourses)
reported on in the text. The book is divided into three main
sections, the first of which covers phenomenology and the
perception of time by analyzing the works of Bergson, Husserl,
Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze, Guattari and Derrida. The second
section focuses on the language and conceptualization of time,
examining the works of Cassirer, Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Lacan,
Ricoeur and Foucault, while the last section addresses the science
and logic of time as they appear in the works of Guillaume,
Einstein, Reichenbach, Prigogine and Barbour. The purpose of the
book is threefold: to provide readers with a comprehensive overview
of the concept of time in early twentieth-century philosophy; to
show how conceptual reasoning can be supported by accompanying
linguistic and spatial representations; and to stimulate novel
research in the humanistic field concerning the complex role of
graphic representations in the comprehension of concepts.
This book systematically creates a general descriptive theory of
scientific change that explains the mechanics of changes in both
scientific theories and the methods of their assessment. It was
once believed that, while scientific theories change through time,
their change itself is governed by a fixed method of science.
Nowadays we know that there is no such thing as an unchangeable
method of science; the criteria employed by scientists in theory
evaluation also change through time. But if that is so, how and why
do theories and methods change? Are there any general laws that
govern this process, or is the choice of theories and methods
completely arbitrary and random? Contrary to the widespread
opinion, the book argues that scientific change is indeed a
law-governed process and that there can be a general descriptive
theory of scientific change. It does so by first presenting
meta-theoretical issues, divided into chapters on the scope,
possibility and assessment of theory of scientific change. It then
builds a theory about the general laws that govern the process of
scientific change, and goes into detail about the axioms and
theorems of the theory.
Sudduth provides a critical exploration of classical empirical
arguments for survival arguments that purport to show that data
collected from ostensibly paranormal phenomena constitute good
evidence for the survival of the self after death. Utilizing the
conceptual tools of formal epistemology, he argues that classical
arguments are unsuccessful.
This original work contains the first detailed account of the
natural philosophy of Robert Hooke (1635-1703), leading figure of
the early Royal Society. From celestial mechanics to microscopy,
from optics to geology and biology, Hooke's contributions to the
Scientific Revolution proved decisive. Focusing separately on
partial aspects of Hooke's works, scholars have hitherto failed to
see the unifying idea of the natural philosophy underlying them.
Some of his unpublished papers have passed almost unnoticed. Hooke
pursued the foundation of a real, mechanical and experimental
philosophy, and this book is an attempt to reconstruct it. The book
includes a selection of Hooke's unpublished papers. Readers will
discover a study of the new science through the works of one of the
most known protagonists. Challenging the current views on the
scientific life of restoration England, this book sheds new light
on the circulation of Baconian ideals and the mechanical philosophy
in the early Royal Society. This book is a must-read to anybody
interested in Hooke, early modern science or Restoration history.
Paul Abela presents a powerful, experience-sensitive form of realism about the relation between mind and world, based on an innovative interpretation of Kant. Abela breaks with tradition in taking seriously Kant's claim that his Transcendental Idealism yields a form of empirical realism, and giving a realist analysis of major themes of the Critique of Pure Reason. Abela's blending of Kantian scholarship with contemporary epistemology offers a new way of resolving philosophical debates about realism.
Disease is everywhere. Everyone experiences disease, everyone knows
somebody who is, or has been diseased, and disease-related stories
hit the headlines on a regular basis. Many important issues in the
philosophy of disease, however, have received remarkably little
attention from philosophical thinkers. This book examines a number
of important debates in the philosophy of medicine, including 'what
is disease?', and the roles and viability of concepts of causation,
in clinical medicine and epidemiology. Where much of the existing
literature targets conceptual analyses of health and disease, this
book provides the reader with an insight into these debates, and
develops plausible alternative accounts. The author explores a
range of related subjects, discussing a host of interesting
philosophical questions within clinical medicine, pathology and
epidemiology. In the second part of the book, the author examines
the concepts of causation employed by clinicians and pathologists,
how one should classify diseases, and whether the epidemiologist's
models for inferring the causes of disease are all they're cracked
up to be.
Chapters "Turing and Free Will: A New Take on an Old Debate" and
"Turing and the History of Computer Music" are available open
access under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International
License via link.springer.com.
Scientific realism is at the core of the contemporary philosophical
debate on science. This book analyzes new versions of scientific
realism. It makes explicit the advantages of scientific realism
over alternatives and antagonists, contributes to deciding which of
the new approaches better meets the descriptive and the
prescriptive criteria, and expands the philosophico-methodological
field to take in new topics and disciplines.
Metaphysics has often held that laws of nature, if legitimate, must
be time-independent. Yet mounting evidence from the foundations of
science suggests that this constraint may be obsolete. This book
provides arguments against this atemporality conjecture, which it
locates both in metaphysics and in the philosophy of science,
drawing on developments in a range of fields, from the foundations
of physics to the philosophy of finance. It then seeks to excavate
an alternative philosophical lineage which reconciles
time-dependent laws with determinism, converging in the thought of
Immanuel Kant.
This book offers a close and rigorous examination of the arguments
for and against scientific realism and introduces key positions in
the scientific realism/antirealism debate, which is one of the
central debates in contemporary philosophy of science. On the one
hand, scientific realists argue that we have good reasons to
believe that our best scientific theories are approximately true
because, if they were not even approximately true, they would not
be able to explain and predict natural phenomena with such
impressive accuracy. On the other hand, antirealists argue that the
success of science does not warrant belief in the approximate truth
of our best scientific theories. This is because the history of
science is a graveyard of theories that were once successful but
were later discarded. The author eventually settles on a
middle-ground position between scientific realism and antirealism
called "relative realism".
Interdisciplinarity has seemingly become a paradigm for modern and
meaningful research. Clearly, the interdisciplinary modus of
deliberation enables to unfold relevant but quite different
disciplinary perspectives to the reflection of broader scientific
questions or societal problems. However, whether the comprehensive
results of interdisciplinary reflection prove to be valid or to be
acceptable in trans-disciplinary terms depends upon certain
preconditions, which have to be fulfilled for securing scientific
quality and social trust in advisory contexts. The present book is
written by experts and practitioners of interdisciplinary research
and policy advice. It analyses topical and methodological
approaches towards interdisciplinarity, starting with the current
role of scientific research in society. The volume continues with
contributions to the issues of knowledge and acting and to
trans-disciplinary deliberation. The final conclusions address the
scientific system as substantial actor itself as well as the
relevant research and education politics.
This book explores the prospects of rivaling ontological and
epistemic interpretations of quantum mechanics (QM). It concludes
with a suggestion for how to interpret QM from an epistemological
point of view and with a Kantian touch. It thus refines, extends,
and combines existing approaches in a similar direction. The author
first looks at current, hotly debated ontological interpretations.
These include hidden variables-approaches, Bohmian mechanics,
collapse interpretations, and the many worlds interpretation. He
demonstrates why none of these ontological interpretations can
claim to be the clear winner amongst its rivals. Next, coverage
explores the possibility of interpreting QM in terms of knowledge
but without the assumption of hidden variables. It examines QBism
as well as Healey's pragmatist view. The author finds both
interpretations or programs appealing, but still wanting in certain
respects. As a result, he then goes on to advance a genuine
proposal as to how to interpret QM from the perspective of an
internal realism in the sense of Putnam and Kant. The book also
includes two philosophical interludes. One details the notions of
probability and realism. The other highlights the connections
between the notions of locality, causality, and reality in the
context of violations of Bell-type inequalities.
What would it mean to apply quantum theory, without restriction and
without involving any notion of measurement and state reduction, to
the whole universe? What would realism about the quantum state then
imply? This book brings together an illustrious team of
philosophers and physicists to debate these questions. The
contributors broadly agree on the need, or aspiration, for a
realist theory that unites micro- and macro-worlds. But they
disagree on what this implies. Some argue that if unitary quantum
evolution has unrestricted application, and if the quantum state is
taken to be something physically real, then this universe emerges
from the quantum state as one of countless others, constantly
branching in time, all of which are real. The result, they argue,
is many worlds quantum theory, also known as the Everett
interpretation of quantum mechanics. No other realist
interpretation of unitary quantum theory has ever been found.
Others argue in reply that this picture of many worlds is in no
sense inherent to quantum theory, or fails to make physical sense,
or is scientifically inadequate. The stuff of these worlds, what
they are made of, is never adequately explained, nor are the worlds
precisely defined; ordinary ideas about time and identity over time
are compromised; no satisfactory role or substitute for probability
can be found in many worlds theories; they can't explain
experimental data; anyway, there are attractive realist
alternatives to many worlds. Twenty original essays, accompanied by
commentaries and discussions, examine these claims and
counterclaims in depth. They consider questions of ontology - the
existence of worlds; probability - whether and how probability can
be related to the branching structure of the quantum state;
alternatives to many worlds - whether there are one-world realist
interpretations of quantum theory that leave quantum dynamics
unchanged; and open questions even given many worlds, including the
multiverse concept as it has arisen elsewhere in modern cosmology.
A comprehensive introduction lays out the main arguments of the
book, which provides a state-of-the-art guide to many worlds
quantum theory and its problems.
The cover of Lifeconscious helps to explain its topic in a
nutshell. The background shows a cliff face that reveals the
catastrophic boundary between two historical epochs. In this case
the Valles Caldera super volcanic eruption 1.4 million years ago.
The thin boundary line separating the two epochs is plainly visible
and provides stark evidence that this is just one of many
catastrophes of biblical proportions that life has had to overcome
during our Earth's turbulent history. Lifeconscious will reveal how
nature can generate New Species through assimilation and not
through the tedious genetic mutations that evolution preaches. The
inset picture of the Venus of Willendorf harks back to a time when
Man was a hunter/gatherer and when Women were still regarded in
high esteem as the mysterious providers of human life.
Lifeconscious will demonstrate how life is an unending linear
transference of species-specific memories from females to their
unborn young. It will finally provide answers to the puzzling
questions of What is instinct?, How are new species generated? and
Why can't evolution explain the existence of living fossils?. novel
light.
This book discusses how scientific and other types of cognition
make use of models, abduction, and explanatory reasoning in order
to produce important or creative changes in theories and concepts.
It includes revised contributions presented during the
international conference on Model-Based Reasoning (MBR'015), held
on June 25-27 in Sestri Levante, Italy. The book is divided into
three main parts, the first of which focuses on models, reasoning
and representation. It highlights key theoretical concepts from an
applied perspective, addressing issues concerning information
visualization, experimental methods and design. The second part
goes a step further, examining abduction, problem solving and
reasoning. The respective contributions analyze different types of
reasoning, discussing various concepts of inference and creativity
and their relationship with experimental data. In turn, the third
part reports on a number of historical, epistemological and
technological issues. By analyzing possible contradictions in
modern research and describing representative case studies in
experimental research, this part aims at fostering new discussions
and stimulating new ideas. All in all, the book provides
researchers and graduate students in the field of applied
philosophy, epistemology, cognitive science and artificial
intelligence alike with an authoritative snapshot of current
theories and applications of model-based reasoning.
The philosophy of computer science is concerned with issues that
arise from reflection upon the nature and practice of the
discipline of computer science. This book presents an approach to
the subject that is centered upon the notion of computational
artefact. It provides an analysis of the things of computer science
as technical artefacts. Seeing them in this way enables the
application of the analytical tools and concepts from the
philosophy of technology to the technical artefacts of computer
science. With this conceptual framework the author examines some of
the central philosophical concerns of computer science including
the foundations of semantics, the logical role of specification,
the nature of correctness, computational ontology and abstraction,
formal methods, computational epistemology and explanation, the
methodology of computer science, and the nature of computation. The
book will be of value to philosophers and computer scientists.
This book addresses the mathematical rationality contained in the
making of string figures. It does so by using interdisciplinary
methods borrowed from anthropology, mathematics, history and
philosophy of mathematics. The practice of string figure-making has
long been carried out in many societies, and particularly in those
of oral tradition. It consists in applying a succession of
operations to a string (knotted into a loop), mostly using the
fingers and sometimes the feet, the wrists or the mouth. This
succession of operations is intended to generate a final figure.
The book explores different modes of conceptualization of the
practice of string figure-making and analyses various source
material through these conceptual tools: it looks at research by
mathematicians, as well as ethnographical publications, and
personal fieldwork findings in the Chaco, Paraguay, and in the
Trobriand Islands, Papua New Guinea, which all give evidence of the
rationality that underlies this activity. It concludes that the
creation of string figures may be seen as the result of
intellectual processes, involving the elaboration of algorithms,
and concepts such as operation, sub-procedure, iteration, and
transformation.
|
|