|
Books > Science & Mathematics > Mathematics > Philosophy of mathematics
During the period of national isolation, a mathematical tradition
called wasan flourished in Japan. Though virtually unknown to
Europeans before the Meiji Restoration, its practitioners, the
wasanka, produced some results comparable to (and sometimes in
advance of) those of mathematicians of the European Enlightment.
This volume, a companion to Unger's earlier translation of
solutions by Aida Yasuaki (1747-1817), focuses on problems that
Aida most likely used as a teacher. Unger explains the reasons for
believing this, and sheds further light on the intellectual milieu
in which Aida worked by discussing other books by Aida, including
one in which he describes Dutch techniques of navigation.
Towards Non-Being presents an account of the semantics of
intentional language-verbs such as 'believes', 'fears', 'seeks',
'imagines'. Graham Priest tackles problems concerning intentional
states which are often brushed under the carpet in discussions of
intentionality, such as their failure to be closed under
deducibility. Priest's account draws on the work of the late
Richard Routley (Sylvan), and proceeds in terms of objects that may
be either existent or non-existent, at worlds that may be either
possible or impossible. Since Russell, non-existent objects have
had a bad press in Western philosophy; Priest mounts a full-scale
defence. In the process, he offers an account of both fictional and
mathematical objects as non-existent. The book will be of central
interest to anyone who is concerned with intentionality in the
philosophy of mind or philosophy of language, the metaphysics of
existence and identity, the philosophy or fiction, the philosophy
of mathematics, or cognitive representation in AI. This updated
second edition adds ten new chapters to the original eight. These
further develop the ideas of the first edition, reply to critics,
and explore new areas of relevance. New topics covered include:
conceivability, realism/antirealism concerning non-existent
objects, self-deception, and the verb to be.
This is the first complete English translation of Bernard Bolzano's
four-volume Wissenschaftslehre or Theory of Science, a masterwork
of theoretical philosophy. Bolzano (1781-1848), one of the greatest
philosophers of the nineteenth century, was a man of many parts.
Best known in his own time as a teacher and public intellectual, he
was also a mathematician and logician of rare ability, the peer of
other pioneers of modern mathematical logic such as Boole, Frege,
and Peirce. As Professor of Religion at the Charles University in
Prague from 1805, he proved to be a courageous and determined
critic of abuses in church and state, a powerful advocate for
reform. Dismissed by the Emperor in 1819 for political reasons, he
left public life and spent the next decade working on his "theory
of science," which he also called logic. The resulting
Wissenschaftslehre, first published in 1837, is a monumental,
wholly original study in logic, epistemology, heuristics, and
scientific methodology. Unlike most logical studies of the period,
it is not concerned with the "psychological self-consciousness of
the thinking mind." Instead, it develops logic as the science of
"propositions in themselves" and their parts, especially the
relations between these entities. It offers, for the first time in
the history of logic, a viable definition of consequence (or
deducibility), and a novel view of probability. Giving constant
attention to Bolzano's predecessors and contemporaries, with
particular emphasis on Kant, this richly documented work is also a
valuable source for the history of logic and philosophy. Each
volume of the edition is accompanied by a detailed introduction,
which alerts the reader to the historical context of Bolzano's work
and illuminates its continued relevance.
This book analyses the straw man fallacy and its deployment in
philosophical reasoning. While commonly invoked in both academic
dialogue and public discourse, it has not until now received the
attention it deserves as a rhetorical device. Scott Aikin and John
Casey propose that straw manning essentially consists in expressing
distorted representations of one’s critical interlocutor. To this
end, the straw man comprises three dialectical forms, and not only
the one that is usually suggested: the straw man, the weak man and
the hollow man. Moreover, they demonstrate that straw manning is
unique among fallacies as it has no particular logical form in
itself, because it is an instance of inappropriate meta-argument,
or argument about arguments. They discuss the importance of the
onlooking audience to the successful deployment of the straw man,
reasoning that the existence of an audience complicates the
dialectical boundaries of argument. Providing a lively, provocative
and thorough analysis of the straw man fallacy, this book will
appeal to postgraduates and researchers alike, working in a range
of fields including fallacies, rhetoric, argumentation theory and
informal logic.
This publication includes an unabridged and annotated translation
of two works by Johann Heinrich Lambert (1728-1777) written in the
1760s: Vorlaufige Kenntnisse fur die, so die Quadratur und
Rectification des Circuls suchen and Memoire sur quelques
proprietes remarquables des quantites transcendentes circulaires et
logarithmiques. The translations are accompanied by a
contextualised study of each of these works and provide an overview
of Lambert's contributions, showing both the background and the
influence of his work. In addition, by adopting a biographical
approach, it allows readers to better get to know the scientist
himself. Lambert was a highly relevant scientist and polymath in
his time, admired by the likes of Kant, who despite having made a
wide variety of contributions to different branches of knowledge,
later faded into an undeserved secondary place with respect to
other scientists of the eighteenth century. In mathematics, in
particular, he is famous for his research on non-Euclidean
geometries, although he is likely best known for having been the
first who proved the irrationality of pi. In his Memoire, he
conducted one of the first studies on hyperbolic functions, offered
a surprisingly rigorous proof of the irrationality of pi,
established for the first time the modern distinction between
algebraic and transcendental numbers, and based on such
distinction, he conjectured the transcendence of pi and therefore
the impossibility of squaring the circle.
This book introduces the reader to Serres' unique manner of 'doing
philosophy' that can be traced throughout his entire oeuvre: namely
as a novel manner of bearing witness. It explores how Serres takes
note of a range of epistemologically unsettling situations, which
he understands as arising from the short-circuit of a proprietary
notion of capital with a praxis of science that commits itself to a
form of reasoning which privileges the most direct path (simple
method) in order to expend minimal efforts while pursuing maximal
efficiency. In Serres' universal economy, value is considered as a
function of rarity, not as a stock of resources. This book
demonstrates how Michel Serres has developed an architectonics that
is coefficient with nature. Mathematic and Information in the
Philosophy of Michel Serres acquaints the reader with Serres'
monist manner of addressing the universality and the power of
knowledge - that is at once also the anonymous and empty faculty of
incandescent, inventive thought. The chapters of the book
demarcate, problematize and contextualize some of the
epistemologically unsettling situations Serres addresses, whilst
also examining the particular manner in which he responds to and
converses with these situations.
I first had a quick look, then I started reading it. I couldn't
stop. -Gerard 't Hooft (Nobel Prize, in Physics 1999) This is a
book about the mathematical nature of our Universe. Armed with no
more than basic high school mathematics, Dr. Joel L. Schiff takes
you on a foray through some of the most intriguing aspects of the
world around us. Along the way, you will visit the bizarre world of
subatomic particles, honey bees and ants, galaxies, black holes,
infinity, and more. Included are such goodies as measuring the
speed of light with your microwave oven, determining the size of
the Earth with a stick in the ground and the age of the Solar
System from meteorites, understanding how the Theory of Relativity
makes your everyday GPS system possible, and so much more. These
topics are easily accessible to anyone who has ever brushed up
against the Pythagorean Theorem and the symbol , with the lightest
dusting of algebra. Through this book, science-curious readers will
come to appreciate the patterns, seeming contradictions, and
extraordinary mathematical beauty of our Universe.
Is anything truly random? Does infinity actually exist? Could we ever see into other dimensions?
In this delightful journey of discovery, David Darling and extraordinary child prodigy Agnijo Banerjee draw connections between the cutting edge of modern maths and life as we understand it, delving into the strange would we like alien music? and venturing out on quests to consider the existence of free will and the fantastical future of quantum computers. Packed with puzzles and paradoxes, mind-bending concepts and surprising solutions, this is for anyone who wants life s questions answered even those you never thought to ask.
From an infant's first grasp of quantity to Einstein's theory of
relativity, the human experience of number has intrigued
researchers for centuries. Numeracy and mathematics have played
fundamental roles in the development of societies and
civilisations, and yet there is an essential mystery to these
concepts, evidenced by the fear many people still feel when
confronted by apparently simple sums. Including perspectives from
anthropology, education and psychology, The Nature and Development
of Mathematics addresses three core questions: Is maths natural?
What is the impact of our culture and environment on mathematical
thinking? And how can we improve our mathematical ability?
Examining the cognitive processes that we use, the origins of these
skills and their cultural context, and how learning and teaching
can be supported in the classroom, the book contextualises each
issue within the wider field, arguing that only by taking a
cross-disciplinary perspective can we fully understand what it
means to be numerate, as well as how we become numerate in our
modern world. This is a unique collection including contributions
from a range of renowned international researchers. It will be of
interest to students and researchers across cognitive psychology,
cultural anthropology and educational research.
Mathematical platonism is the view that mathematical statements are
true of real mathematical objects like numbers, shapes, and sets.
One central problem with platonism is that numbers, shapes, sets,
and the like are not perceivable by our senses. In contemporary
philosophy, the most common defense of platonism uses what is known
as the indispensability argument. According to the
indispensabilist, we can know about mathematics because mathematics
is essential to science. Platonism is among the most persistent
philosophical views. Our mathematical beliefs are among our most
entrenched. They have survived the demise of millennia of failed
scientific theories. Once established, mathematical theories are
rarely rejected, and never for reasons of their inapplicability to
empirical science. Autonomy Platonism and the Indispensability
Argument is a defense of an alternative to indispensability
platonism. The autonomy platonist believes that mathematics is
independent of empirical science: there is purely mathematical
evidence for purely mathematical theories which are even more
compelling to believe than empirical science. Russell Marcus begins
by contrasting autonomy platonism and indispensability platonism.
He then argues against a variety of indispensability arguments in
the first half of the book. In the latter half, he defends a new
approach to a traditional platonistic view, one which includes
appeals to a priori but fallible methods of belief acquisition,
including mathematical intuition, and a natural adoption of
ordinary mathematical methods. In the end, Marcus defends his
intuition-based autonomy platonism against charges that the
autonomy of mathematics is viciously circular. This book will be
useful to researchers, graduate students, and advanced
undergraduates with interests in the philosophy of mathematics or
in the connection between science and mathematics.
This is a reproduction of a book published before 1923. This book
may have occasional imperfections such as missing or blurred pages,
poor pictures, errant marks, etc. that were either part of the
original artifact, or were introduced by the scanning process. We
believe this work is culturally important, and despite the
imperfections, have elected to bring it back into print as part of
our continuing commitment to the preservation of printed works
worldwide. We appreciate your understanding of the imperfections in
the preservation process, and hope you enjoy this valuable book.
++++ The below data was compiled from various identification fields
in the bibliographic record of this title. This data is provided as
an additional tool in helping to ensure edition identification:
++++ Cours D'analyse De L'ecole Polytechnique, Volume 1; Cours
D'analyse De L'ecole Polytechnique; Camille Jordan 2 Camille Jordan
s.n., 1893 Calculus; Calculus of variations; Curves, Plane;
Differential equations; Functions; Mathematical analysis; Series,
Infinite
This book is an attempt to change our thinking about thinking. Anna
Sfard undertakes this task convinced that many long-standing,
seemingly irresolvable quandaries regarding human development
originate in ambiguities of the existing discourses on thinking.
Standing on the shoulders of Vygotsky and Wittgenstein, the author
defines thinking as a form of communication. The disappearance of
the time-honoured thinking-communicating dichotomy is epitomised by
Sfard's term, commognition, which combines communication with
cognition. The commognitive tenet implies that verbal communication
with its distinctive property of recursive self-reference may be
the primary source of humans' unique ability to accumulate the
complexity of their action from one generation to another. The
explanatory power of the commognitive framework and the manner in
which it contributes to our understanding of human development is
illustrated through commognitive analysis of mathematical discourse
accompanied by vignettes from mathematics classrooms.
|
|