|
Books > Humanities > Philosophy > Western philosophy
Before now, there has been no comprehensive analysis of the
multiple relations between A. Comte's and J.S. Mill's positive
philosophy and Franz Brentano's work. The present volume aims to
fill this gap and to identify Brentano's position in the context of
the positive philosophy of the 19th century by analyzing the
following themes: the concept of positive knowledge; philosophy and
empirical, genetic and descriptive psychology as sciences in
Brentano, Comte and Mill; the strategies for the rebirth of
philosophy in these three authors; the theory of the ascending
stages of thought, of their decline, of the intentionality in Comte
and Brentano; the reception of Comte's positivism in Whewell and
Mill; induction and phenomenalism in Brentano, Mill and Bain; the
problem of the "I" in Hume and Brentano; mathematics as a
foundational science in Brentano, Kant and Mill; Brentano's
critique of Mach's positivism; the concept of positive science in
Brentano's metaphysics and in Husserl's early phenomenology; the
reception of Brentano's psychology in Twardowski; The Brentano
Institute at Oxford. The volume also contains the translation of
the most significant writings of Brentano regarding philosophy as
science. I. Tanasescu, Romanian Academy; A. Bejinariu, Romanian
Society of Phenomenology; S. Krantz Gabriel, Saint Anselm College;
C. Stoenescu, University of Bucharest.
Plato was the first philosopher in the western tradition to reflect
systematically (and often critically) on rhetoric. In this book,
Tushar Irani presents a comprehensive and innovative reading of the
Gorgias and the Phaedrus, the only two Platonic dialogues to focus
on what an 'art of argument' should look like, treating each of the
texts individually, yet ultimately demonstrating how each can best
be understood in light of the other. For Plato, the way in which we
approach argument typically reveals something about our deeper
desires and motivations, particularly with respect to other people,
and so the key to understanding his views on the proper practice of
argument lies in his understanding of human psychology. According
to this reading, rhetoric done well is simply the practice of
philosophy, the pursuit of which has far-reaching implications for
how we should relate to others and how we ought to live.
Teachers not only serve as caretakers for the students in their
classroom but also serve as stewards for society's next generation.
In this way, teachers are charged with responsibility for the
present and the future of their world. Shouldering this
responsibility is no less than an existential dilemma that requires
not only professional solutions but also personal responsibility
rooted in subjective authenticity. In the edited volume, authors
will explore how the philosophy of Existentialism can help
teachers, teacher educators, educational researchers, and
policymakers better understand the existential responsibility that
teachers shoulder. The core concepts of Existential philosophy
explored in this edited volume imply that a teacher's lived
experience cannot be defined solely by professional knowledge or
dictates. Teachers have the capacity to create subjective meaning
through their own agency, and there is no guarantee that those
subjective meanings will accord with professional dictates.
Furthermore, there is no guarantee that professional dictates are
more valid than the existential realities of individual teachers.
The philosophy of Existentialism encourages individuals to reflect
on the existential realities of isolation, freedom,
meaninglessness, and death in an effort to propel individuals
towards more authentic ways of engaging in the world. The chapters
of this edited volume advance the argument that being and becoming
a teacher must be understood - at least in part - from the
subjective perspective of the individual and that teachers are
responsible for authoring the meaning of their lives and of their
work.
Nihilism seems to be per definition linked to violence. Indeed, if
the nihilist is a person who acknowledges no moral or religious
authority, then what does stop him from committing any kind of
crime? Dostoevsky precisely called attention to this danger: if
there is no God and no immortality of the soul, then everything is
permitted, even anthropophagy. Nietzsche, too, emphasised, although
in different terms, the consequences deriving from the death of God
and the collapse of Judeo-Christian morality. This context shaped
the way in which philosophers, writers and artists thought about
violence, in its different manifestations, during the 20th century.
The goal of this interdisciplinary volume is to explore the various
modern and contemporary configurations of the link between violence
and nihilism as understood by philosophers and artists (in both
literature and film).
This book intends to broaden the study of idealism beyond its
simplistic characterizations in contemporary philosophy. After
idealist stances have practically disappeared from the mental
landscape in the last hundred years, and the term "idealism" has
itself become a sort of philosophical anathema, continental
philosophy was, first, plunged into one of its deepest crises of
truth, culminating in postmodernism, and then, the 21st century
ushered in a new era of realism. Against this background, the
volume gathers a number of renowned philosophers, among them Slavoj
Zizek, Robert B. Pippin, Mladen Dolar, Sebastian Roedl, Paul
Redding, Isabelle Thomas-Fogiel, James I. Porter, and others, in
order to address the issue as to what exactly has been lost with
the retreat of idealism, and what kind of idealism could still be
rehabilitated in the present day. The contributions will both
provide historical studies on idealism, pointing out the little
known, overlooked, and surprising instances of idealist impulses,
and set out to develop new perspectives and possibilities for a
contemporary idealism. The appeal of the book lies in the fact that
it defends a philosophical concept that has been increasingly under
attack and thus contributes to an ongoing debate in ontology.
This volume examines the historical end of the Platonic tradition
in relation to creation theories of the natural world through
Neoplatonist philosopher Proclus (412-485) elaboration of an
investigation of Plato's theory of metaphysical archetypal Forms.
Nietzsche's famous attack upon established Christianity and
religion is brought to the reader in this superb hardcover edition
of The Antichrist, introduced and translated by H.L. Mencken. The
incendiary tone throughout The Antichrist separates it from most
other well-regarded philosophical texts; even in comparison to
Nietzsche's earlier works, the tone of indignation and conviction
behind each argument made is evident. There is little lofty
ponderousness; the book presents its arguments and points at a
blistering pace, placing itself among the most accessible and
comprehensive works of philosophy. The Antichrist comprises a total
of sixty-two short chapters, each with distinct philosophical
arguments or angle upon the targets of Christianity, organised
religion, and those who masquerade as faithful but are in actuality
anything but. Pointedly opposed to notions of Christian morality
and virtue, Nietzsche vehemently sets out a case for the faith's
redundancy and lack of necessity in human life.
The Greek commentary tradition devoted to explicating Aristotle's
Nicomachean Ethics (NE) was extensive. It began in antiquity with
Aspasius and reached a point of immense sophistication in the
twelfth century with the commentaries of Eustratius of Nicaea and
Michael of Ephesus, which primarily served educational purposes.
The use of Aristotle's ethics in the classroom continued into the
late Byzantine period, but until recently scholastic use of the NE
was known mostly through George Pachymeres' epitome of the NE (Book
11 of his Philosophia). This volume radically changes the landscape
by providing the editio princeps of the last surviving exegetical
commentary on the NE stricto sensu, also penned by Pachymeres. This
represents a new witness to the importance of Aristotelian studies
in the cultural revival of late Byzantium. The editio princeps is
accompanied by an English translation and a thorough introduction,
which offers an informed reading of the commentary's genre and
layout, relationship to its sources, exegetical strategies, and
philosophical originality. This book also includes the edition of
diagrams and scholia accompanying Pachymeres' exegesis, whose
paratextual function is key to a full understanding of the work.
Paul and the Greco-Roman Philosophical Tradition provides a fresh
examination of the relationship of Greco-Roman philosophy to
Pauline Christianity. It offers an in-depth look at different
approaches employed by scholars who draw upon philosophical
settings in the ancient world to inform their understanding of
Paul. The volume houses an international team of scholars from a
range of diverse traditions and backgrounds, which opens up a
platform for multiple voices from various corridors. Consequently,
some of the chapters seek to establish new potential resonances
with Paul and the Greco-Roman philosophical tradition, but others
question such connections. While a number of them propose radically
new relationships between Paul and GrecoRoman philosophy, a few
seek to tweak or modulate current discussions. There are arguments
in the volume which are more technical and exegetical, and others
that remain more synthetic and theological. This diversity,
however, is accentuated by a goal shared by each author - to
further our understanding of Paul's relationship to and
appropriation of Greco-Roman philosophical traditions in his
literary and missionary efforts.
|
|