|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy
In Philosophies of Gratitude, Ashraf H. A. Rushdy explores
gratitude as a philosophical concept. The first half of the book
traces its significance in fundamental Western moral philosophy and
notions of ethics, specifically examining key historical moments
and figures in classical antiquity, the early modern era, and the
Enlightenment. In the second half of the book, Rushdy focuses on
contemporary meanings of gratitude as a sentiment, action, and
disposition: how we feel grateful, act grateful, and cultivate
grateful being. He identifies these three forms of gratitude to
discern various roles our emotions play in our ethical responses to
the world around us. Rushdy then discusses how ingratitude, instead
of indicating a moral failure, can also act as an important
principle and ethical stand against injustice. Rushdy asserts that
if we practice gratitude as a moral recognition of the other, then
that gratitude varies alongside the different kinds of benefactors
who receive it, ranging from the person who provides an expected
service or gift, to the divine or natural sources whom we may
credit with our very existence. By arguing for the necessity of
analyzing gratitude as a philosophical concept, Rushdy reminds us
of our capacity and appreciation for gratitude simply as an
acknowledgment and acceptance of our humble dependency on and
connectedness with our families, friends, communities,
environments, and universe.
A bold new conception of Heidegger’s project of Destruktion as a
method of interpreting history For Martin Heidegger, our inherited
traditions provide the concepts through which we make our world
intelligible. Concepts we can also oppose, disrupt, and even
exceed. First, however, if Western philosophy is our inheritance,
we must submit it to Destruktion—starting with Aristotle.
Heidegger and the Destruction of Aristotle: On How to Read the
Tradition presents a new conception of Heidegger’s
“destruction” as a way of reading. Situated between Nietzschean
genealogy and Derridean deconstruction, this method uncovers in
Aristotle the most vital originating articulations of the Western
tradition and gives us the means to confront it. Sean D. Kirkland
argues this is not a rejection of the past but a sophisticated and
indeed timely hermeneutic tool—a complex, illuminating, and
powerful method for interpreting historical texts at our present
moment. Acknowledging the historical Heidegger as a politically
compromised and still divisive figure, Kirkland demonstrates that
Heideggerian destruction is a method of interpreting history that
enables us to reorient and indeed transform its own most troubling
legacies.
This volume of newly written chapters on the history and
interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus represents a significant
step beyond the polemical debate between broad interpretive
approaches that has recently characterized the field. Some of the
contributors might count their approach as 'new' or 'resolute',
while others are more 'traditional', but all are here concerned
primarily with understanding in detail the structure of argument
that Wittgenstein presents within the Tractatus, rather than with
its final self-renunciation, or with the character of the
understanding that renunciation might leave behind. The volume
makes a strong case that close investigation, both biographical and
textual, into the composition of the Tractatus, and into the
various influences on it, still has much to yield in revealing the
complexity and fertility of Wittgenstein's early thought. Amongst
these influences Kant and Kierkegaard are considered alongside
Wittgenstein's immediate predecessors in the analytic tradition.
The themes explored range across the breadth of Wittgenstein's
book, and include his accounts of ethics and aesthetics, as well as
issues in metaphysics and the philosophy of mind, and aspects of
the logical framework of his account of representation. The
contrast of saying and showing, and Wittgenstein's attitude to the
inexpressible, is of central importance to many of the
contributions. By approaching this concern through the various
first-level issues that give rise to it, rather than from
entrenched schematic positions, the contributors demonstrate the
possibility of a more inclusive, constructive and fruitful mode of
engagement with Wittgenstein's text and with each other.
The problem of the unity of the proposition is almost as old as
philosophy itself, and was one of the central themes of early
analytical philosophy, greatly exercising the minds of Frege,
Russell, Wittgenstein, and Ramsey. The problem is how propositions
or meanings can be simultaneously unities (single things) and
complexes, made up of parts that are autonomous of the positions
they happen to fill in any given proposition. The problem has been
associated with numerous paradoxes and has motivated general
theories of thought and meaning, but has eluded any consensual
resolution; indeed, the problem is sometimes thought to be wholly
erroneous, a result of atomistic assumptions we should reject. In
short, the problem has been thought to be of merely historical
interest. Collins argues that the problem is very real and poses a
challenge to any theory of linguistic meaning. He seeks to resolve
the problem by laying down some minimal desiderata on a solution
and presenting a uniquely satisfying account. The first part of the
book surveys and rejects extant 'solutions' and dismissals of the
problem from (especially) Frege and Russell, and a host of more
contemporary thinkers, including Davidson and Dummett. The book's
second part offers a novel solution based upon the properties of a
basic syntactic principle called 'Merge', which may be said to
create objects inside objects, thus showing how unities can be both
single things but also made up of proper parts. The solution is
defended from both philosophical and linguistic perspectives. The
overarching ambition of the book, therefore, is to strengthen the
ties between current linguistics and contemporary philosophy of
language in a way that is genuinely sensitive to the history of
both fields.
The importance of Bessarion's contribution to the history of
Byzantine and Renaissance philosophy and culture during the 15th
century is beyond dispute. However, an adequate appreciation of his
contribution still remains a desideratum of scholarly research. One
serious impediment to scholarly progress is the fact that the
critical edition of his main philosophical work "In Calumniatorem
Platonis" is incomplete and that this work has not been translated
in its entirety into any modern language yet. Same can be stated
about several minor but equally important treatises on literary,
theological and philosophical subjects. This makes editing,
translating and interpreting his literary, religious and
philosophical works a scholarly priority. Papers assembled in this
volume highlight a number of philological, philosophical and
historical aspects that are crucial to our understanding of
Bessarion's role in the history of European civilization and to
setting the directions of future research in this field.
This important new book offers the first full-length interpretation
of the thought of Martin Heidegger with respect to irony. In a
radical reading of Heidegger's major works (from "Being and Time"
through the "Rector's Address" and the "Letter on Humanism" to "The
Origin of the Work of Art" and the Spiegel interview), Andrew Haas
does not claim that Heidegger is simply being ironic. Rather he
argues that Heidegger's writings make such an interpretation
possible - perhaps even necessary.Heidegger begins "Being and Time"
with a quote from Plato, a thinker famous for his insistence upon
Socratic irony. "The Irony of Heidegger" takes seriously the
apparently curious decision to introduce the threat of irony even
as philosophy begins in earnest to raise the question of the
meaning of being. Through a detailed and thorough reading of
Heidegger's major texts and the fundamental questions they raise,
Haas reveals that one of the most important philosophers of the
20th century can be read with as much irony as earnestness. "The
Irony of Heidegger" attempts to show that the essence of this irony
lies in uncertainty, and that the entire project of
onto-heno-chronophenomenology, therefore needs to be called into
question.
The Laws is Plato's last and longest dialogue. Although it has been
neglected (compared to such works as the Republic and Symposium),
it is beginning to receive a great deal of scholarly attention.
Book 10 of the Laws contains Plato's fullest defence of the
existence of the gods, and his last word on their nature, as well
as a presentation and defence of laws against impiety (e.g.
atheism). Plato's primary aim is to defend the idea that the gods
exist and that they are good - this latter meaning that they do not
neglect human beings and cannot be swayed by prayers and sacrifices
to overlook injustice. As such, the Laws is an important text for
anyone interested in ancient Greek religion, philosophy, and
politics generally, and the later thought of Plato in particular.
Robert Mayhew presents a new translation, with commentary, of Book
10 of the Laws. His primary aim in the translation is fidelity to
the Greek. His commentary focuses on philosophical issues (broadly
understood to include religion and politics), and deals with
philological matters only when doing so serves to better explain
those issues. Knowledge of Greek is not assumed, and the Greek that
does appear has been transliterated. It is the first commentary in
English of any kind on Laws 10 for nearly 140 years.
John Palmer develops and defends a modal interpretation of
Parmenides, according to which he was the first philosopher to
distinguish in a rigorous manner the fundamental modalities of
necessary being, necessary non-being or impossibility, and
non-necessary or contingent being. This book accordingly
reconsiders his place in the historical development of Presocratic
philosophy in light of this new interpretation. Careful treatment
of Parmenides' specification of the ways of inquiry that define his
metaphysical and epistemological outlook paves the way for detailed
analyses of his arguments demonstrating the temporal and spatial
attributes of what is and cannot not be. Since the existence of
this necessary being does not preclude the existence of other
entities that are but need not be, Parmenides' cosmology can
straightforwardly be taken as his account of the origin and
operation of the world's mutable entities. Later chapters reassess
the major Presocratics' relation to Parmenides in light of the
modal interpretation, focusing particularly on Zeno, Melissus,
Anaxagoras, and Empedocles. In the end, Parmenides' distinction
among the principal modes of being, and his arguments regarding
what what must be must be like, simply in virtue of its mode of
being, entitle him to be seen as the founder of metaphysics or
ontology as a domain of inquiry distinct from natural philosophy
and theology. An appendix presents a Greek text of the fragments of
Parmenides' poem with English translation and textual notes.
How are artificial intelligence (AI) and the strong claims made by
their philosophical representatives to be understood and evaluated
from a Kantian perspective? Conversely, what can we learn from AI
and its functions about Kantian philosophy's claims to validity?
This volume focuses on various aspects, such as the self, the
spirit, self-consciousness, ethics, law, and aesthetics to answer
these questions.
The concept of the Self has a long history that dates back from the
ancient Greeks such as Aristotle to more contemporary thinkers such
as Wundt, James, Mead, Cooley, Freud, Rogers, and Erikson (Tesser
& Felson, 2000). Research on the Self relates to a range of
phenomena including self-esteem, self-concept, self-protection,
self-verification, self-awareness, identity, self-efficacy,
self-determination etc. that could be sharply different or very
similar. Despite this long tradition of thinkers and the numerous
studies conducted on the Self, this concept is still not very well
defined. More precisely, it is not a precise object of study, but
rather a collection of loosely related subtopics (Baumesiter,
1998). Also, in the philosophical literature, the legitimacy of the
concept of "self" has been brought into question. Some authors have
argued that the self is not a psychological entity per se, but
rather an illusion created by the complex interplay between
cognitive and neurological subsystems (Zahavi, 2005). Although no
definitive consensus has been reached regarding the Self, we
emphasis in this volume that the Self and its related phenomena
including self-concept, motivation, and identity are crucial for
understanding consciousness and therefore important to understand
human behavior. Self-Concept, Motivation and Identity: Underpinning
Success with Research and Practice provides thus a unique insight
into self-concept and its relationship to motivation and identity
from varied theoretical and empirical perspectives. This volume is
intended to develop both theoretical and methodological ideas and
to present empirical evidence demonstrating the importance of
theory and research to effective practice.
Fifty-one years after the philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche died, My
Sister and I appeared on the American market as a book that was
reputedly written by him when he was an inmate in the Jena insane
asylum. Since the day it appeared, the book's authenticity has been
generally dismissed as a fraud.Walter Stewart takes a fresh look at
this book in what is the first detailed account of the myth,
legend, and scholarly criticism that has shrouded this work in
mystery for over half a century and for the first time unveils the
real truth about My Sister and I.
This volume is a detailed study of the concept of the nutritive
capacity of the soul and its actual manifestation in living bodies
(plants, animals, humans) in Aristotle and Aristotelianism.
Aristotle's innovative analysis of the nutritive faculty has laid
the intellectual foundation for the increasing appreciation of
nutrition as a prerequisite for the maintenance of life and health
that can be observed in the history of Greek thought. According to
Aristotle, apart from nutrition, the nutritive part of the soul is
also responsible for or interacts with many other bodily functions
or mechanisms, such as digestion, growth, reproduction, sleep, and
the innate heat. After Aristotle, these concepts were used and
further developed by a great number of Peripatetic philosophers,
commentators on Aristotle and Arabic thinkers until early modern
times. This volume is the first of its kind to provide an in-depth
survey of the development of this rather philosophical concept from
Aristotle to early modern thinkers. It is of key interest to
scholars working on classical, medieval and early modern
psycho-physiological accounts of living things, historians and
philosophers of science, biologists with interests in the history
of science, and, generally, students of the history of philosophy
and science.
|
You may like...
Recipes
SuzelleDIY
Paperback
R295
R272
Discovery Miles 2 720
Redeemed
Lauren Asher
Paperback
R305
R253
Discovery Miles 2 530
|