|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy
This book intends to broaden the study of idealism beyond its
simplistic characterizations in contemporary philosophy. After
idealist stances have practically disappeared from the mental
landscape in the last hundred years, and the term "idealism" has
itself become a sort of philosophical anathema, continental
philosophy was, first, plunged into one of its deepest crises of
truth, culminating in postmodernism, and then, the 21st century
ushered in a new era of realism. Against this background, the
volume gathers a number of renowned philosophers, among them Slavoj
Zizek, Robert B. Pippin, Mladen Dolar, Sebastian Roedl, Paul
Redding, Isabelle Thomas-Fogiel, James I. Porter, and others, in
order to address the issue as to what exactly has been lost with
the retreat of idealism, and what kind of idealism could still be
rehabilitated in the present day. The contributions will both
provide historical studies on idealism, pointing out the little
known, overlooked, and surprising instances of idealist impulses,
and set out to develop new perspectives and possibilities for a
contemporary idealism. The appeal of the book lies in the fact that
it defends a philosophical concept that has been increasingly under
attack and thus contributes to an ongoing debate in ontology.
Teachers not only serve as caretakers for the students in their
classroom but also serve as stewards for society's next generation.
In this way, teachers are charged with responsibility for the
present and the future of their world. Shouldering this
responsibility is no less than an existential dilemma that requires
not only professional solutions but also personal responsibility
rooted in subjective authenticity. In the edited volume, authors
will explore how the philosophy of Existentialism can help
teachers, teacher educators, educational researchers, and
policymakers better understand the existential responsibility that
teachers shoulder. The core concepts of Existential philosophy
explored in this edited volume imply that a teacher's lived
experience cannot be defined solely by professional knowledge or
dictates. Teachers have the capacity to create subjective meaning
through their own agency, and there is no guarantee that those
subjective meanings will accord with professional dictates.
Furthermore, there is no guarantee that professional dictates are
more valid than the existential realities of individual teachers.
The philosophy of Existentialism encourages individuals to reflect
on the existential realities of isolation, freedom,
meaninglessness, and death in an effort to propel individuals
towards more authentic ways of engaging in the world. The chapters
of this edited volume advance the argument that being and becoming
a teacher must be understood - at least in part - from the
subjective perspective of the individual and that teachers are
responsible for authoring the meaning of their lives and of their
work.
Marx's early work is well known and widely available, but it
usually interpreted as at best a kind of stepping-stone to the Marx
of Capital. This book offers something completely different; it
reconstructs, from his first writings spanning from 1835 to 1846, a
coherent and well-rounded political philosophy. The influence of
Engels upon the development of that philosophy is discussed. This,
it is argued, was a philosophy that Marx could have presented had
he put the ideas together, as he hinted was his eventual intention.
Had he done so, this first Marx would have made an even greater
contribution to social and political philosophy than is generally
acknowledged today. Arguments regarding revolutionary change,
contradiction and other topics such as production, alienation and
emancipation contribute to a powerful analysis in the early works
of Marx, one which is worthy of discussion on its own merits. This
analysis is distributed among a range of books, papers, letters and
other writings, and is gathered here for the first time. Marx's
work of the period was driven by his commitment to emancipation.
Moreover, as is discussed in the conclusion to this book, his
emancipatory philosophy continues to have resonance today. This new
book presents Marx in a unique, new light and will be indispensable
reading for all studying and following his work.
This book offers the first comprehensive evaluation of ethics in
the ancient Greek novel, demonstrating how their representation of
the cardinal virtue sophrosune positions these texts in their
literary, philosophical and cultural contexts. Sophrosune
encompasses the dispositions and psychological states of
temperance, self-control, chastity, sanity and moderation. The
Greek novels are the first examples of lengthy prose fiction in the
Greek world, composed between the first century BCE and the fourth
century CE. Each novel is concerned with a pair of beautiful,
aristocratic lovers who undergo trials and tribulations, before a
successful resolution is reached. Bird focuses on the extant
examples of the genre (Chariton’s Callirhoe, Xenophon of
Ephesus’ Ephesiaca, Longus’ Daphnis and Chloe, Achilles
Tatius’ Leucippe and Clitophon and Heliodorus’ Aethiopica),
which all have the virtue of sophrosune at their heart. As each
pair of lovers strives to retain their chastity in the face of
adversity, and under extreme pressure from eros, it is essential to
understand how this virtue is represented in the characters within
each novel. Invited modes of reading also involve sophrosune, and
the author provides an important exploration of how sophrosune in
the reader is both encouraged and undermined by these works of
fiction.
The Greek commentary tradition devoted to explicating Aristotle's
Nicomachean Ethics (NE) was extensive. It began in antiquity with
Aspasius and reached a point of immense sophistication in the
twelfth century with the commentaries of Eustratius of Nicaea and
Michael of Ephesus, which primarily served educational purposes.
The use of Aristotle's ethics in the classroom continued into the
late Byzantine period, but until recently scholastic use of the NE
was known mostly through George Pachymeres' epitome of the NE (Book
11 of his Philosophia). This volume radically changes the landscape
by providing the editio princeps of the last surviving exegetical
commentary on the NE stricto sensu, also penned by Pachymeres. This
represents a new witness to the importance of Aristotelian studies
in the cultural revival of late Byzantium. The editio princeps is
accompanied by an English translation and a thorough introduction,
which offers an informed reading of the commentary's genre and
layout, relationship to its sources, exegetical strategies, and
philosophical originality. This book also includes the edition of
diagrams and scholia accompanying Pachymeres' exegesis, whose
paratextual function is key to a full understanding of the work.
Addressing Merleau-Ponty's work Phenomenology of Perception, in
dialogue with The Visible and the Invisible, his lectures at the
College de France, and his reading of Proust, this book argues that
at play in his thought is a philosophy of "ontological lateness".
This describes the manner in which philosophical reflection is
fated to lag behind its objects; therefore an absolute grasp on
being remains beyond its reach. Merleau-Ponty articulates this
philosophy against the backdrop of what he calls "cruel thought", a
style of reflecting that seeks resolution by limiting,
circumscribing, and arresting its object. By contrast, the
philosophy of ontological lateness seeks no such finality-no
apocalypsis or unveiling-but is characterized by its ability to
accept the veiling of being and its own constitutive lack of
punctuality. To this extent, his thinking inaugurates a new
relation to the becoming of sense that overcomes cruel thought.
Merleau-Ponty's work gives voice to a wisdom of dispossession that
allows for the withdrawal of being. Never before has anyone engaged
with the theme of Merleau-Ponty's own understanding of philosophy
in such a sustained way as Whitmoyer does in this volume.
Humor has been praised by philosophers and poets as a balm to
soothe the sorrows that outrageous fortune's slings and arrows
cause inevitably, if not incessantly, to each and every one of us.
In mundane life, having a sense of humor is seen not only as a
positive trait of character, but as a social prerequisite, without
which a person's career and mating prospects are severely
diminished, if not annihilated. However, humor is much more than
this, and so much else. In particular, humor can accompany cruelty,
inform it, sustain it, and exemplify it. Therefore, in this book,
we provide a comprehensive, reasoned exploration of the vast
literature on the concepts of humor and cruelty, as these have been
tackled in Western philosophy, humanities, and social sciences,
especially psychology. Also, the apparent cacophony of extant
interpretations of these two concepts is explained as the
inevitable and even useful result of the polysemy inherent to all
common-sense concepts, in line with the understanding of concepts
developed by M. Polanyi in the 20th century. Thus, a thorough,
nuanced grasp of their complex mutual relationship is established,
and many platitudes affecting today's received views, and
scholarship, are cast aside.
|
|