|
Books > Philosophy > Western philosophy
Engaging with several emerging and interconnected approaches in the
social sciences, including pragmatism, system theory, processual
thinking and relational thinking, this book leverages John Dewey
and Arthur Bentley's often misunderstood concept of trans-action to
revisit and redefine our perceptions of social relations and social
life. The contributors gathered here use trans-action in a more
specific sense, showing why and how social scientists and
philosophers might use the concept to better understand our social
life and social problems. As the first collective sociological
attempt to apply the concept of trans-action to contemporary social
issues, this volume is a key reference for the growing audience of
relational and processual thinkers in the social sciences and
beyond.
This book is a consideration of Hegel's view on logic and basic
logical concepts such as truth, form, validity, and contradiction,
and aims to assess this view's relevance for contemporary
philosophical logic. The literature on Hegel's logic is fairly
rich. The attention to contemporary philosophical logic places the
present research closer to those works interested in the link
between Hegel's thought and analytical philosophy
(Stekeler-Weithofer 1992 and 2019, Berto 2005, Rockmore 2005,
Redding 2007, Nuzzo 2010 (ed.), Koch 2014, Brandom 2014, 1-15,
Pippin 2016, Moyar 2017, Quante & Mooren 2018 among others). In
this context, one particularity of this book consists in focusing
on something that has been generally underrated in the literature:
the idea that, for Hegel as well as for Aristotle and many other
authors (including Frege), logic is the study of the forms of
truth, i.e. the forms that our thought can (or ought to) assume in
searching for truth. In this light, Hegel's thinking about logic is
a fundamental reference point for anyone interested in a
philosophical foundation of logic.
This book offers an introduction to Socrates, ideal for
undergraduate students taking courses in Ancient and Greek
Philosophy. Socrates is regarded as the founder of Western
philosophical inquiry. Yet he left no writings and claimed to know
'nothing fine or worthy'. He spent his life perplexing those who
encountered him and is as important and perplexing now as he was
2500 years ago. Drawing on the various competing sources for
Socrates that are available to us, "Socrates: A Guide for the
Perplexed" guides the reader through the main themes and ideas of
Socrates' thought. Taking into account the puzzles surrounding his
trial and death, the philosophical methods and ethical positions
associated with Socrates, and his lasting influence, Sara
Ahbel-Rappe presents a concise and accessible introduction to this
most influential and important of philosophers. She concludes by
suggesting that it is in fact the Socratic insistence on
self-knowledge that makes Socrates at once so pivotal and so
elusive for the student of philosophy. This book is the ideal
companion to the study of key thinker in the history of philosophy.
Continuum's "Guides for the Perplexed" are clear, concise and
accessible introductions to thinkers, writers and subjects that
students and readers can find especially challenging - or indeed
downright bewildering. Concentrating specifically on what it is
that makes the subject difficult to grasp, these books explain and
explore key themes and ideas, guiding the reader towards a thorough
understanding of demanding material.
Written at a time when violence has many faces and goes by many
names, this collection is proof that philosophy can remain a vital
partner in the twin tasks of diagnosis and action. Emerging across
specters of genocide, racism, oppression, terror, poverty, or war,
the threat of violence is not only concrete and urgent, but all too
often throws the work of critical reflection into vulnerable
paralysis. With essays by some of today's finest scholars, these
pages breathe new life into the hard work of intellectual
engagement. Philosophers such as Peg Birmingham, Robert Bernasconi,
and Bernhard Waldenfels not only feel the distinct burden of our
age but, with unflagging attention to the philosophical tradition,
forge a pronounced counterweight to the violent gyre of today. The
result is a stirring critique that looks outward upon the phenomena
of injustice, and inward upon the instruments and assumptions of
philosophical discourse itself.
This is an important new monograph on Plato's metaphysics, focusing
on the theory of the forms, which is the central philosophical
concept in Plato's theory.Few philosophical doctrines have been as
influential and as widely discussed as Plato's theory of Forms; yet
few have been as misunderstood. Most philosophers, following the
recommendation of Aristotle, regard the Forms as abstract entities.
However, this view is difficult to square with other aspects of
Plato's thought, in particular his theory of knowledge.Francis A.
Grabowski aims to dissociate the theory of Forms from its
Aristotelian reception, by interpreting it within the larger
framework of Plato's philosophy. Grabowski notes that the theory
emerged largely from epistemological concerns. He shows that the
ancients conceived of knowledge almost exclusively as a
perception-like acquaintance with things. He goes on to examine
Plato's epistemology and shows that Plato also regards knowledge as
the mind being directly acquainted with its object. Grabowski
argues that, by modelling knowledge on perception, Plato could not
have conceived of the Forms as Aristotle and others have claimed.
He concludes that an interpretation of the Forms as concrete rather
than abstract entities provides a more plausible and coherent view
of Plato's overall philosophical project.
Human, All Too Human (1878) is often considered the start of
Friedrich Nietzsche's mature period. A complex work that explores
many themes to which Nietzsche later returned, it marks a
significant departure from his previous thinking. Here Nietzsche
breaks with his early allegiance to Schopenhauer and Wagner, and
establishes the overall framework of his later philosophy. In
contrast to his previous disdain for science, now Nietzsche views
science as key to undercutting traditional metaphysics. This he
sees as a crucial step in the emergence of free spirits who will be
the avant-garde of culture.
In summing up the crucial change of perspective expressed in
Human, All Too Human, Nietzsche used the following words in his
later work Ecce Homo:
Human, All Too Human is a memorial of a crisis.... W]ith this book
I liberated myself from that in my nature which did not belong to
me. Idealism does not belong to me...realities were altogether
lacking in my knowledge, and the 'idealities' were worth damn all A
downright burning thirst seized hold of me: thenceforward I pursued
in fact nothing other than physiology, medicine, and natural
science.
This is an essential work for anyone who wishes to understand
Nietzsche's incisive critique of Western culture and values.
John Searle (1932-) is one of the most famous living American
philosophers. A pupil of J. L. Austin at Oxford in the 1950s, he is
currently Mills Professor of the Philosophy of Mind and Language at
the University of California, Berkeley. In 1995 John Searle
published "The Construction of Social Reality", a text which not
only promises to disclose the institutional backdrop against which
speech takes place, but initiate a new 'philosophy of society'.
Since then "The Construction of Social Reality" has been subject to
a flurry of criticism. While many of Searle's interlocutors share
the sense that the text marks an important breakthrough, he has
time and again accused critics of misunderstanding his claims.
Despite Searle's characteristic crispness and clarity there remains
some confusion, among both philosophers and sociologists, regarding
the significance of his proposals. This book traces some of the
high points of this dialogue, leveraging Searle's own
clarifications to propose a new way of understanding the text. In
particular, Joshua Rust looks to Max Weber in suggesting that
Searle has articulated an ideal type. In locating The Construction
of Social Reality under the umbrella of one of sociology's founding
fathers, this book not only makes Searle's text more accessible to
the readers in the social sciences, but presents Max Weber as a
thinker worthy of philosophical reconsideration. Moreover, the
recharacterization of Searle's claims in terms of the ideal type
helps facilitate a comparison between Searle and other social
theorists such as Talcott Parsons.
This book explores the philosophical writings of Gerda Walther
(1897-1977). It features essays that recover large parts of
Walther's oeuvre in order to show her contribution to phenomenology
and philosophy. In addition, the volume contains an English
translation of part of her major work on mysticism. The essays
consider the interdisciplinary implications of Gerda Walther's
ideas. A student of Edmund Husserl, Edith Stein, and Alexander
Pfander, she wrote foundational studies on the ego, community,
mysticism and religion, and consciousness. Her discussions of
empathy, identification, the ego and ego-consciousness, alterity,
God, mysticism, sensation, intentionality, sociality, politics, and
woman are relevant not only to phenomenology and philosophy but
also to scholars of religion, women's and gender studies,
sociology, political science, and psychology. Gerda Walther was one
of the important figures of the early phenomenological movement.
However, as a woman, she could not habilitate at a German
university and was, therefore, denied a position. Her complete
works have yet to be published. This ground-breaking volume not
only helps readers discover a vital voice but it also demonstrates
the significant contributions of women to early phenomenological
thinking.
"In this massive, meticulously researched work Trinkaus makes a
major contribution to our understanding of the Italian humanists
and the Christian Renaissance in Italy. . . . The author argues
persuasively that the Italian humanists drew their inspiration more
from the church fathers than from the pagan ancients. . . . [This
is] the most comprehensive and most important study of Italian
humanism to appear in English. It is a mine of information,
offering, among other things, detailed analyses of texts which have
been ignored even by Italian scholars." -Library Journal
This is the second edition of the study of Ayn Rand's first novel,
which was published in 1936--ten years after she left Soviet
Russia, and during America's Red Decade. Essays deal with
historical, literary and philosophical themes. Essays on the
history of We the Living cover: the drafts of the novel; the
historical accuracy of its setting and the extent to which the
novel is autobiographical; and, Rand's struggles with a hostile
culture first to publish We the Living, and then to adapt it.
Essays providing literary analyses include a comparison of We the
Living and the fiction of Victor Hugo (Rand's favorite writer).
Also covered are We the Living's plot, theme, characterization and
style--what Rand, in her writings on literary aesthetics,
considered the four essential attributes of a novel. The theme of
We the Living is the individual against the state, and the sanctity
of human life. These issues are dealt with in detail, especially in
the essays which focus on philosophical topics. A number of essays
in this collection make extensive use of previously unpublished
material from the Ayn Rand Archives.
This monograph details the entire scientific thought of an
influential natural philosopher whose contributions, unfortunately,
have become obscured by the pages of history. Readers will discover
an important thinker: Burchard de Volder. He was instrumental in
founding the first experimental cabinet at a European University in
1675. The author goes beyond the familiar image of De Volder as a
forerunner of Newtonianism in Continental Europe. He consults
neglected materials, including handwritten sources, and takes into
account new historiographical categories. His investigation maps
the thought of an author who did not sit with an univocal
philosophical school, but critically dealt with all the 'major'
philosophers and scientists of his age: from Descartes to Newton,
via Spinoza, Boyle, Huygens, Bernoulli, and Leibniz. It explores
the way De Volder's un-systematic thought used, rejected, and
re-shaped their theories and approaches. In addition, the title
includes transcriptions of De Volder's teaching materials:
disputations, dictations, and notes. Insightful analysis combined
with a trove of primary source material will help readers gain a
new perspective on a thinker so far mostly ignored by scholars.
They will find a thoughtful figure who engaged with early modern
science and developed a place that fostered experimental
philosophy.
Science is knowledge gained and justified methodically. It is
achieved by research and theory formation. But what is a methodical
procedure and what are methodically established justifications?
What kind of principles must be observed in order to obtain the
degree of objectivity that is generally claimed by science? What is
the relation between science in the research mode and science in
presentation mode, i.e., in its theoretical form? Do the same
principles hold here? And how are they justified? Is it even
possible to speak of justification in a theoretical sense? Or do we
have to be content with less - with corroboration and confirmation?
Is the distinction between the context of discovery and the context
of justification the last word in methodical and theoretical
matters? And how does this distinction relate to that between
research and presentation - the constitution of (scientific)
objects on the one hand and (theoretical) propositions about them
on the other? The analyses and constructions in this book take up
these questions. They are explicitly intended as philosophical
contributions, not only in the sense implied by the disciplinary
use of the term philosophy of science, but also in the sense of a
reflection on science that, alongside more technical aspects of
methodologies and elements of theories, also has an eye for
anthropological and cultural aspects.
This book brings together papers from a conference that took place
in the city of L'Aquila, 4-6 April 2019, to commemorate the 10th
anniversary of the earthquake that struck on 6 April 2009.
Philosophers and scientists from diverse fields of research debated
the problem that, on 6 April 1922, divided Einstein and Bergson:
the nature of time. For Einstein, scientific time is the only time
that matters and the only time we can rely on. Bergson, however,
believes that scientific time is derived by abstraction, even in
the sense of extraction, from a more fundamental time. The
plurality of times envisaged by the theory of Relativity does not,
for him, contradict the philosophical intuition of the existence of
a single time. But how do things stand today? What can we say about
the relationship between the quantitative and qualitative
dimensions of time in the light of contemporary science? What do
quantum mechanics, biology and neuroscience teach us about the
nature of time? The essays collected here take up the question that
pitted Einstein against Bergson, science against philosophy, in an
attempt to reverse the outcome of their monologue in two voices,
with a multilogue in several voices.
Jacques Ranciere: An Introduction offers the first comprehensive
introduction to the thought of one of today's most important and
influential theorists. Joseph Tanke situates Ranciere's distinctive
approach against the backdrop of Continental philosophy and extends
his insights into current discussions of art and politics. Tanke
explains how Ranciere's ideas allow us to understand art as having
a deeper social role than is customarily assigned to it, as well as
how political opposition can be revitalized. The book presents
Ranciere's body of work as a coherent whole, tracing key notions
such as the distribution of the sensible, the aesthetics of
politics, and the supposition of equality from his earliest
writings through to his most recent interventions. Tanke concludes
with a series of critical questions for Ranciere's work, indicating
how contemporary thought might proceed after its encounter with
him. The book provides readers new to Ranciere with a clear
overview of his enormous intellectual output. Engaging with many
un-translated and unpublished sources, the book will also be of
interest to Ranciere's long-time readers. >
 |
Meditations
(Hardcover)
Marcus Aurelius; Translated by George Long
|
R617
Discovery Miles 6 170
|
Ships in 12 - 19 working days
|
|
Constantly regard the universe as one living being, having one
substance and one soul; and observe how all things have reference
to one perception, the perception of this one living being; and how
all things act with one movement; and how all things are the
cooperating causes of all things which exist; observe too the
continuous spinning of the thread and the contexture of the web.A"
Marcus Aurelius - 'Meditations' Marcus Aurelius is considered to
one of the great Emperors of Rome who was not only a skilled
military leader but also a great philosopher in the Stoic
tradition. He was born in 121 AD and both of his parents came from
wealthy backgrounds. His father died when Marcus was 3 years old
and by the time he was 6 he had gained the attention of the Emperor
Hadrian who oversaw his education. Hadrian ensured that Marcus was
taught by some of the greatest scholars in Rome who educated him in
literature, drama, geometry, Greek oratory, Greek and Latin. Marcus
later abandoned most of those subjects in favor of philosophy, with
the work of the Greek philosopher Epictetus being a major influence
on his thinking. In 138, while still a young man, the Emperor
Antoninus Pius adopted Marcus, and in 161 he himself became
Emperor. Marcus insisted he would only take up the Emperorship if
Lucius Verus were also installed. Marcus's insistence on Lucius
joining him as Emperor was a military one. At that time Rome was
fighting wars on multiple fronts and Marcus wanted someone he could
trust to marshal the troops who he knew would not at some point
lead a revolt against him. Lucius and Marcus were loyal to each
other up until Lucius's death in 169 AD. After Lucius's death,
Marcus was the sole Emperor and due to the incessant wars in the
provinces he was unable to spend much time indulging his
philosophical pursuits. He did manage to found four Chairs of
Philosophy in Athens, one for each of the main philosophical
schools of thought, Aristotelian, Epicurean, Platonic and Stoic.
Although Marcus spent almost all of his reign on campaigns in
foreign territories, he managed to write down his thoughts and
these became what are now considered a masterpiece of Roman
philosophy, the discourses 'Meditations'. Marcus wrote
'Meditations' around 170 - 180, whilst on a campaign in central
Europe, most probably in what is now Serbia, Hungary and Austria.
The 12 books that make up 'Meditations' were not written as an
exercise in explaining his philosophy but rather as a personal
notebook for self-improvement and study. 'Meditations' illustrates
just how important Epictetus was to Marcus as he quotes the Greek
philosopher's famed 'Discourses' on more than one occasion.
Epictetus was a legendary figure in Greek philosophy and many claim
he is the greatest of the Stoics; texts that remain in existence
from the period suggest that in his native Greece, he was even more
popular than Plato. As was previously mentioned, 'Meditations' was
not written for public consumption but rather as an aid to personal
development. Marcus wanted to change his way of living and thinking
and to do this he embarked on a set of philosophical exercises. He
would reflect on philosophical ideas and by writing them down and
by repeating them he hoped to re-programme his mind and find his
own philosophy to live by. One of the key exercises in the book
discusses Marcus attempting to look at the world from 'the point of
view of the cosmos' in a bid to try and look at life and the
universe outside of the common and limited parameters of individual
concerns. You have the power to strip away many superfluous
troubles located wholly in your judgment, and to possess a large
room for yourself embracing in thought the whole cosmos, to
consider everlasting time, to think of the rapid change in the
parts of each thing, of how short it is from birth until
dissolution, and how the void before birth and that after
dissolution are equally infinite.A" Marcus Aurelius died on March
17, 180, in the city of Vindobona which was situated where Vienna
is today. History remembers him as the last of the 'Five Good
Emperors' of the Nervan-Antonian dynasty. Marcus' son Commodus
replaced his father as Emperor and although he reigned over a
relatively stable period in Roman history, in terms of war and
peace, his personal behavior and antics were not in the spirit of
those Emperors that came immediately before him. Commodus was
eventually murdered in a plot that involved his mistress Marcia,
thus bringing to an end the highly regarded Nervan-Antonian
dynasty.
A new account of Aristotle's Ethics, this book argues for the
central importance of the concept of techne or craft in Aristotle's
moral theory. Exploring the importance of techne in the Platonic
and pre-Platonic intellectual context in which Aristotle was
writing, Tom Angier here shows that this concept has an important
role in Aristotle's Ethics that has rarely been studied in
Anglo-American scholarship. Through close-analysis of the primary
texts, this book uses the focus on techne to systematically
critique and renew Aristotelian moral philosophy. Techne in
Aristotle's Ethics provides a novel and challenging approach to one
of the Ancient World's most enduring intellectual legacies.
Many of the earliest books, particularly those dating back to the
1900s and before, are now extremely scarce and increasingly
expensive. Pomona Press are republishing these classic works in
affordable, high quality, modern editions, using the original text
and artwork.
Filling a genuine gap in Zizek interpretation - through examining
his relationship with Martin Heidegger, the author offers a new and
useful overview of Zizek's work."Zizek and Heidegger" offers a
radical new interpretation of the work of Slavoj Zizek, one of the
world's leading contemporary thinkers, through a study of his
relationship with the work of Martin Heidegger. Thomas Brockelman
argues that Zizek's oeuvre is largely a response to Heidegger's
philosophy of finitude, an immanent critique of it which pulls it
in the direction of revolutionary praxis. Brockelman also finds
limitations in Zizek's relationship with Heidegger, specifically in
his ambivalence about Heidegger's technophobia.Brockelman's
critique of Zizek departs from this ambivalence - a fundamental
tension in Zizek's work between a historicist critical theory of
techno-capitalism and an anti-historicist theory of revolutionary
change. In addition to clarifying what Zizek has to say about our
world and about the possibility of radical change in it, "Zizek and
Heidegger" explores the various ways in which this split at the
center of his thought appears within it - in Zizek's views on
history or on the relationship between the revolutionary leader and
the proletariat or between the analyst and the analysand.
This book sheds new light on the history of the philosophically
crucial notion of intentionality, which accounts for one of the
most distinctive aspects of our mental life: the fact that our
thoughts are about objects. Intentionality is often described as a
certain kind of relation. Focusing on Franz Brentano, who
introduced the notion into contemporary philosophy, and on the
Aristotelian tradition, which was Brentano's main source of
inspiration, the book reveals a rich history of debate on precisely
the relational nature of intentionality. It shows that Brentano and
the Aristotelian authors from which he drew not only addressed the
question whether intentionality is a relation, but also devoted
extensive discussions to what kind of relation it is, if any. The
book aims to show that Brentano distinguishes the intentional
relation from two other relations with which it might be confused,
namely, causality and reference, which also hold between thoughts
and their objects. Intentionality accounts for the aboutness of a
thought; causality, by contrast, explains how the thought is
generated, and reference, understood as a sort of similarity,
occurs when the object towards which the thought is directed
exists. Brentano claims to find some anticipation of his views in
Aristotle. This book argues that, whether or not Brentano's
interpretation of Aristotle is correct, his claim is true of the
Aristotelian tradition as a whole, since followers of Aristotle
more or less explicitly made some or all of Brentano's
distinctions. This is demonstrated through examination of some
major figures of the Aristotelian tradition (broadly understood),
including Alexander of Aphrodisias, the Neoplatonic commentators,
Thomas Aquinas, Duns Scotus, and Francisco Suarez. This book
combines a longue duree approach - focusing on the long-term
evolution of philosophical concepts rather than restricting itself
to a specific author or period - with systematic analysis in the
history of philosophy. By studying Brentano and the Aristotelian
authors with theoretical sensitivity, it also aims to contribute to
our understanding of intentionality and cognate features of the
mind.
Hilary Putnam is one of America's most important living
philosophers. This book offers an introduction to and overview of
Putnam's ideas, his writings and his contributions to the various
fields of philosophy.Hilary Putnam is one of America's most
important and influential contemporary philosophers. He has made
considerable contributions to the philosophy of mind, philosophy of
language, philosophy of science, philosophy of mathematics, logic,
metaphysics and ethics. In many of these areas he has been not only
an active participant, but a foundational thinker. This book offers
an overview of Putnam's ideas, his key writings and his
contributions to the various fields of philosophy.Thematically
organized, the book begins with Putnam's work in the philosophy of
language and shows how his theory of semantic externalism serves as
a lynchpin for understanding his thought as a whole. Crucially,
Lance P. Hickey also examines the ways in which Putnam has shifted
his position on some key philosophical issues and argues that there
is in fact more unity to Putnam's thought than is widely believed.
This is the ideal companion to study of this hugely influential
thinker." The Continuum Contemporary American Thinkers" series
offers concise and accessible introductions to the most important
and influential thinkers at work in philosophy today. Designed
specifically to meet the needs of students and readers encountering
these thinkers for the first time, these informative books provide
a coherent overview and analysis of each thinker's vital
contribution to the field of philosophy. The series is the ideal
companion to the study of these most inspiring and challenging of
thinkers.
|
|